* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Nietzsche on Kant on Beauty and Disinterest
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
History of Philosophy Quarterly Volume 30, Number 1, January 2013 NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS Nick Zangwill H ow good is Friedrich Nietzsche’s critique of Immanuel Kant’s doctrine that pleasure in the beautiful is disinterested? I shall confine my attention to one short passage in the Genealogy of Morals where Nietzsche turns his attention specifically to Kant’s writings on disinterest, rather than those of other philosophers such as Arthur Schopenhauer. I want to examine and assess Nietzsche’s critique of Kant in this passage. We will see that Nietzsche’s criticisms are interesting and persuasive. 1. Introduction: Kant’s Doctrine of Disinterestedness We think of Nietzsche as a figure who has provocative and interesting things to say about a huge range of subjects. We do not expect scholarly care from him. He seems to be a kind of intellectual noble savage, a volcano of intellectual energy, showering us with burning-hot interesting ideas, without waiting to make tiresome caveats and scrupulously exact statements, without making tedious “academic” distinctions and demarcations. That at any rate is the stereotype. And on many topics that is his style. Yet in the passage we will focus on, for the most part, Nietzsche is not crude, careless, or uncharitable in his reading of Kant; and he has an interesting critique. Kant’s doctrine of disinterestedness, as it figures in his Critique of Judgment, is about pleasure in the beautiful; it is not primarily about the judgment of taste or attention, as is sometimes thought (Zangwill 1992). It is, roughly, the idea that pleasure in the beautiful is not connected with desire, in the sense that it is not based on desire and it (pleasure) does not produce desire of itself. (See further Zangwill 1995, and Wood 2004, ch. 8.) Kant writes: 75 76 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY Taste is the faculty of estimating an object or a mode of representation by means of a delight or aversion apart from any interest. The object of such delight is called beautiful. (Kant 1928, 50) Kant’s doctrine is often criticized. But, in my view, there is more to be said for it than many think, and, suitably qualified, I think it can, to an extent, be defended. My brief here is to examine Nietzsche’s criticism of Kant’s doctrine. Some might say that we cannot leap-frog over Schopenhauer in this way because Nietzsche is reacting to Schopenhauer, who is building on Kant. Nevertheless, I shall focus only on whether Nietzsche has good points to make in what he says about Kant, and I shall leave Schopenhauer entirely to one side. In this, I depart from most commentators. However, I assume that Nietzsche can distinguish Kant from Schopenhauer. The consideration of what Nietzsche says about Schopenhauer might be interesting in its own right, but it would distract us and confuse the issue over Nietzsche and Kant. I am aware that this runs against the grain of what we might call the “continental” tradition of Nietzsche interpretation, where Nietzsche is seem as occupying a position on a pedestal as one in a line of Great Dead German Philosophers. Nevertheless, that is my approach. I take what Nietzsche says at face value without imposing a grand narrative onto it. Moreover, this paper will avoid a holistic interpretation of what Nietzsche says about Kant on beauty and disinterest, whereby the passage is connected with what Nietzsche says elsewhere about similar and other topics. Many would argue that what Nietzsche says about Kant on beauty and disinterest must be seen in the light of Nietzsche’s treatment of “aestheticism,” or in the light of Nietzsche’s other views on art and culture. Many would also argue that, although Kant’s view of beauty and disinterest is Nietzsche’s narrow target, we should also take into account Kant’s wider “transcendental” system and his views on art and genius. My view is that, although all this would perhaps be interesting, it would be comparatively messy and highly speculative. My approach is more conservative and safer. I want to read closely rather than risk a speculative integrative approach. I take it that, if Nietzsche wrote something about Kant, then he meant that and not some other thing, and we do not have to help him out by bringing to bear his other writings on related topics or Kant’s other writings on related topics. In sum, in a number of senses, my approach here will be “analytic.” 2. Universality (a) My plan is to be completely flat-footed and quote the text, sentence by sentence—for it is a short passage—adding my comments. Here, NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 77 then, is the passage in the Maudemarie Clarke and Alan J. Swensen translation. The first sentence is this: Schopenhauer used the Kantian formulation of the aesthetic problem for his own purposes, although he most certainly did not view it with Kantian eyes. Nietzsche here marks a difference between Kant and Schopenhauer. Aesthetics textbooks sometimes conflate what Kant and Schopenhauer say under some catch-all notion of “disinterestedness”; but Nietzsche does not do this. This is important for our discussion, since we should distinguish the interpretation and evaluation of Nietzsche on Kant from the interpretation and evaluation of Nietzsche on Schopenhauer. (b) The second sentence is this: Kant thought he had honoured art when among the predicates of the beautiful he privileged and placed in the foreground those which constitute the honour of knowledge—impersonality and universal validity. There seems to be a confusion here between art and beauty. Kant was not primarily talking about art in the Critique of Judgment, which focuses mostly on beauty and judgments of taste, which may be either about art or nature (Kant 1928, sections 1–42 and 55–60; his theory of art occupies only sections 43–54.) Still, it is true that, for Kant, the primary dimension of assessment of art is beauty. So, we can put this seeming confusion to one side. Kant does indeed think that pleasure in the beauty of either art or nature rests on what is universal, present in all rational beings; and, in that sense, it is indeed impersonal. According to Kant, this is how it is possible for it to claim universal validity (Kant 1928, section 6). This is roughly where Nietzsche’s problem with Kant lies. But, to focus more precisely on what worries Nietzsche, we need to make a distinction. In the Critique of Judgment, Kant claims that judgments of taste make a claim to correctness. The judgments are put forward as universally valid for all human beings (in section 6–8 and 32). In this respect, Kant follows the eighteenth-century British aestheticians. I do not think that Nietzsche is objecting to that. (I discuss the contrary view in section 3 of this paper.) However, Kant also thinks that beauty is universally available. This is a different idea, and it is this that Nietzsche rejects, in my view. What Nietzsche dislikes about what he calls the “impersonality and universal validity” of the judgment of taste is not the claim to correctness or universal validity but the idea that the beauty of things is universally available. Both ideas are found in Kant. (Kant writes, “[The subject] must regard [the liking] as resting on what 78 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY he may presuppose in every other person” [Kant 1928, 51].) The idea of the universal availability of beauty is also a Renaissance humanist idea, to be found in Leon Battista Alberti and others (see Mitrovic 2004, 2005). (c) Nietzsche next says, Whether or not this was on the whole a mistake cannot be dealt with here. At face value, Nietzsche is not making an evaluation either way here about Kant’s impersonality and universality claim. Perhaps he does mean to condemn it and will do so. But this is left open at this point. Notice the qualification “on the whole.” This hints that he thinks that there is some truth in Kant’s account. One possibility would be that he is at least pulling apart the ideas of universal validity and universal accessibility. Nietzsche’s view may be subtle. Alternatively, Nietzsche might be putting a question mark over the idea that knowledge is always impersonal. Someone might say, “Ah, but Nietzsche is being ironic.” But it should be a methodological rule never to be sure when a writer is being ironic. We might be reading in more irony than is there. (A comparison: the troubled nature of much Wittgenstein interpretation should caution us against this; when, on the page, Wittgenstein says things that seem to run counter to the standard interpretation, it tends to be dismissed as ironic or perhaps the voice of his “interlocutor,” when it should at least be controversial whether it is so.) (d) Nietzsche continues: I only wish to underscore that Kant, like all philosophers, instead of envisaging the aesthetic problem starting from the experiences of the artist (the one who creates), thought about art and the beautiful from the view point of the “spectator” and therefore, without it being noticed, got the “spectator” himself into the concept “beautiful.” Kant’s spectator-centered approach, thus described, does not seem unreasonable to me, at least. Surely, beauty is what spectators appreciate. But Nietzsche might point out that I am a philosopher, so he might expect me to find it reasonable to sympathize with Kant. Since Nietzsche contrasts the point of view of the spectator with that of the artist, the question we need to consider is this: When we are thinking about the judgment of taste or beauty, why do artists’ experiences matter particularly? Two objections to focusing on the artist’s experiences are these: (1) Those who want buildings designed for them will employ architects, not art and architectural writers or critics, such NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 79 as Nikolaus Pevsner. But if they want to know about the architectural virtues of buildings, they should ask Pevsner not an architect. Perhaps artists or architects are too egotistically bound up with their artistic projects to be fair judges. In Britain, in particular, there is a notable gulf between the architectural tastes of architects and that of the general public. Many architects tend to speak like adolescent proto-Nietzscheans (often because they imbibed Ayn Rand’s Fountainhead at an impressionable age), dismissing ordinary people’s architectural judgments as shallow and sentimental. Unfortunately, British architects’ judgments about architecture are not better than nonarchitect’s judgments—indeed they are often worse— hence, the British wry comment “It probably got an award” said of ugly recent buildings. (2) Reflective phenomenology does not support the idea that artists’ experiences are a better guide to beauty than nonartists’ experiences. There is the phenomenon of artistic understanding destroying the appreciation of beauty, as when one learns how an effect was produced. For example, I can remember hearing a certain musical phrase that intrigued me. It seemed to have a distinctive magical effect. What was it? How was it done? I sat down and worked it out. Thereafter, that music never sounded magical to me in the same way. The music was thereafter disenchanted for me. I knew how the trick was done. Being a musician had damaged my musical experience in this case. So, not only is it difficult to see why the artist’s aesthetic judgments are generally preferable to nonartists’ aesthetic judgments, it seems not to have the support of everyday observation or intuitiveness. However, Nietzsche goes on precisely to address this. It is, thus, evident that his text is not an unstructured rant or ramble. Before we proceed, let us note that there is another way to take what Nietzsche says about beauty, art, and spectators. A more metaphysical way to interpret Nietzsche is as expressing sympathy for a form of “aesthetic realism.” Nietzsche implies that he wants to get the spectator out of the concept of beauty. But realism is a commitment to a spectator-independent notion of beauty—something that might be created by artists but, having been created, is independent of them. This independence is a hallmark of realism about the aesthetic. Nietzsche might add that proper superior artistic spectators think of beauty as something independent of them that they are aware of. The text thus far is compatible with this metaphysical reading. But if we look at 80 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY what ensues, we see that Nietzsche’s point is primarily normative. To say that, however, is not to deny a metaphysical interpretation. The normative and the metaphysical are not opposed. (There are some who interpret Nietzsche as a value nihilist, but I see little to be said for that interpretation.) (e) Nietzsche next writes: If only this “spectator” had at least been sufficiently familiar to the philosophers of the beautiful, however—namely, as the great personal fact and experience, as a wealth of most personal intense experiences, desires, surprises, and delight in the realm of the beautiful! One interpretation would be that Nietzsche is describing the artist spectator rather than the nonartist spectator, and the characteristics that Nietzsche mentions are supposed to be respects in which artist spectators are superior. (We might wonder whether it is fair to say that the nonartist spectator lacks these characteristics: are these not also characteristics of a connoisseur like Pevsner?) My view is that, in fact, the artist/nonartist contrast is a distraction in understanding this passage. It is not really doing work for Nietzsche that it appears to be doing. What is important is the kind of character that Nietzsche associates (rightly or wrongly) with each kind of spectator. We might note that this is an odd list since it includes delight in the beautiful along with other psychological events. This does not fit comfortably with this interpretation. (f) Nietzsche continues: But I fear the opposite was always the case: and thus we receive from them, right from the beginning definitions in which, as in that famous definition Kant gives of the beautiful, the lack of a more refined selfexperience sits in the shape of a fat worm of basic error. On the present interpretation, Nietzsche is criticizing Kant for focusing on the judgment of nonartists because it foregrounds those who lack “intense experiences, desires, surprises”—those who “lack of finer sensitivity.” (Let us put aside the question of whether this is fair to critics like Pevsner.) On this interpretation, the contrast between the artist spectator and the nonartist spectator is not the important point; instead, this distinction serves to illustrate what he is really concerned with, which are the qualities of mind of the true judger and experiencer. This interpretation fits with an elitist theme in some of Nietzsche’s other writings—the idea being that only to the kind of spectators that Nietzsche describes are real beauties available. Only people of a certain artistic sort are able to reach the kind of (“intense”) states that are required to appreciate more elusive beauties. NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 81 An alternative interpretation is that the problem with nonartists is not their lack of refined sensitivity but their lack of self-knowledge. Nietzsche accuses Kant of lack of knowledge (“familiarity”) of the spectator. How then are artists relevant? It is not that they are a different type of spectator, more intense and passionate than most, but that they have greater self-knowledge and, thus, know that desire is involved in their pleasure in beauty. (Artists have a “more refined ‘self-experience.’”) Thus, if one looks at the “aesthetic problem” from the point of view of the artist, the personal and individual nature of our aesthetic life would be obvious. On this interpretation, the list “personal intense experiences, desires, surprises, and delight in the realm of the beautiful!” makes more sense since what is known is the way our pleasures in beauty are integrated with the many desires in play in our lives. There is something to be said for both interpretations. (g) Nietzsche continues: “The Beautiful,” Kant said, “is what pleases without interest.” Without interest! Recall here what disinterestedness means for Kant—a disinterested pleasure is one that lacks a direct connection to desire. This is because pleasure in beauty is supposed to be rooted in our nature as rational beings, which we share with everybody, and it is not rooted in what is idiosyncratic, special to me. Universal validity is supposed to be derived from disinterestedness (Kant 1928, section 6). 3. Discussion: Nietzsche, Hume, Kant, Relativism Let us now step a little way away from the text to discuss and offer some critical assessment of what we have covered so far. Compare and contrast Nietzsche’s “wealth of most personal intense experiences, desires, surprises,” with Hume’s description of the ideal critic: “Strong sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by comparison, and cleared of all prejudice, can alone entitle critics to this valuable character; and the joint verdict of such, wherever they are to be found, is the true standard of taste and beauty” (Hume 1985, 241). We can imagine Nietzsche endorsing “intense” over “delicate” sentiments. In fact, Hume’s account allows for considerable refinements of our sensibilities. Still, there is no denying the large difference between Hume and Nietzsche. An especially clear contrast with Nietzsche is Hume’s requirement that “[a] perfect serenity of mind” is necessary for being a good judge of beauty (Hume 1985, 232). For Hume, we should judge when we are cool and collected. However, perhaps someone in a manic exalted state can grasp higher beauties not available to those in 82 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY a cool, serene frame of mind that Hume seems to require. There is some evidence, I gather, that successful artists are more disposed to be manicdepressive than scientists and ordinary people. The question is this: Does that make them better judges, as opposed to being better creators? Are moody and emotional judgers better at judging? Philosophers for the most part aspire to the more “Apollonian” rather than “Dionysian” frame of mind and are themselves of the cool, serene, and detached disposition that Hume requires for judging beauty. (I have not found a place where Kant makes a similar claim, but the idea of contemplative pleasure seems to imply it.) There is certainly a question about the requirement of coolness. Perhaps there are more profound beauties that are best appreciated in an ecstatic or trance-like state, rather than a state of cool serenity. Consider lack of prejudice, an important virtue in a critic for both Hume and Kant, which dramatizes the contrast with Nietzsche. This was one of Hume’s desiderata, and it resurfaces in Kant’s claim that “[e]veryone must agree that if a judgement of the beautiful is tinged with the slightest interest, then it is very partial and not a pure judgement of taste” (Kant 1928, 43). Nietzsche would, I think, argue that prejudiced critics may be able to grasp beauties beyond the reach of cool, fair, impartial, dispassionate, and impersonal spectators of the sort that Hume or Kant recommend. Suppose certain critics have a prejudice in favor of some group X (nation, religion, and so forth). Then, such critics may be influenced in favor of a work by someone that they believe to belong to that group. They might as a consequence be unfair to those not of group X, judging their work to be worse that they would if they believed them to be the work of someone of group X. Those critics are not impartial judges and are politically bigoted and unjust. Nevertheless, it may be that they have an enhanced appreciation of X art and may be able to find beauties in those works that are lost on more impartial spectators. Nietzsche would, I think, say that fair-mindedness is all very well, but, if it comes at the expense of the intense passions that we need to reap the more subtle and deeper pleasures in more profound beauties, then impartial judges are not ideal judges. What are vices of a critic, in Hume and Kant’s way of thinking, may in fact be necessary vices if one is to have the virtues of an excellent judge. Philippa Foot suggests that Nietzsche believes that the virtues are an essential disunity in that having certain virtues may mean having corresponding vices (Foot 2002, 58). It is similar with taste. A true judge should not be overly fair. Justice is not the first virtue of the ideal aesthetic judge. Indeed, justice may even sometimes be a vice if it stands in the way of passionate and partial engagement with works. By way of illustrating Nietzsche’s view, it may be useful to compare it with a common contemporary view according to which, if a thing is NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 83 beautiful, then standard observers under standard conditions experience it in a certain way. Nietzsche would deny this. He thinks that exceptional people in exceptional conditions may have insight into beauties that are not available to standard observers under standard conditions. Perhaps to appreciate great artistic or natural beauty, it takes an aristocratic soul and an aristocratic sensibility and heightened ecstatic experiences. The highest beauty may be elusive and only available to a few exceptional people in exceptional circumstances in exceptional psychological states. Somewhat similarly, some have claimed that, under the influence of hallucinogenic drugs, people can have experiences that reveal more to them (through “the doors of perception”) than in their normal sober state. I am skeptical about that. But it is certainly a possible view. Why prioritize statistical normality? Perhaps a drugged person is a better judge than an undrugged one in certain matters. Why not? Similarly, perhaps a manic-depressive prejudiced bigot is a better judge of beauty than someone who is cool and calm and fair and impartial and terribly nice. Before we rejoin Nietzsche, there is one common kind of criticism of Kant that I want to mention to contrast it with the much more interesting criticism that I think Nietzsche is proposing. Some Marxists and feminists criticize Kant’s claim that judgments of taste lay claim to correctness or universality, which they connect with disinterestedness (Eagleton 1984; Bourdieu 1984, 1996; Wolff 1984). These writers also see Kant’s pretension to neutrality—the idea that pleasure in beauty is disconnected from interest—as, in fact, concealing the dominance of once kind of “interest” (bourgeois? male?), one that “silences” others (Devereaux 2003; Korsmeyer 2004). However, in Kant’s defense, we can point out that there is much to be said for the idea that judgments of taste aspire to a kind of correctness, one that judgments of the merely agreeable do not (Kant 1928, sections 2–6). This is not a controversial addition to the judgment of taste but essential to it. Relativism is implausible at least as a thesis about what is implicit in the act of judgment. Moreover, since only pure judgments of taste are completely disinterested, Kant can happily admit impure judgments of taste. So Kant’s doctrine not only need not be found objectionable by those who want to import dominance-oppression politics into aesthetics; they could perhaps even use his doctrine to help their cause, since they could complain about the impurity of people’s actual judgments, which are warped in bourgeois, patriarchal, or whatever ways. It must be noted that this type of criticism usually also involves a very crude unsympathetic interpretation of Kant, one that makes of him a pop-Kant substitute. (Eagleton 1984 and Bourdieu 1984 and 1996 are particularly unimpressive on this score; see Zangwill 2002 for 84 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY a critique.) In fact, Kant can be easily defended against these kinds of criticisms. However, my point in mentioning them is not just to complain about the inadequacy of a common kind of discussion and criticism of Kant—which would be uninteresting—but to provide a clear contrast with Nietzsche’s much more interesting criticism. Nietzsche offers an elitist critique of the leveling idea of the universal availability of beauty. That is, he regards some beauty as “difficult,” as has often been claimed by those in various twentieth-century modernist movements, in visual art and architecture, music, and literature. Nietzsche seems to be objecting to Kant’s Enlightenment and humanist universalism, according to which beauty is within reach of everyone. That is too democratic for Nietzsche. Nietzsche’s criticism of Kant is, thus, the complete opposite of that of the Marxist and feminist critics. They think that Kant’s view that aesthetic judgment claims correctness and universality is somehow badly exclusionary. Not enough! Nietzsche would reply. Some beauty, higher beauty, can be grasped only by a select few. 4. Desire Let us now return to the text. (h) Nietzsche continues: Compare this definition with one made by a real “spectator” and artist—Stendhal, who in one place calls the beautiful une promesse de bonheur [a promise of happiness]. It is hard to reconstruct a Stendhalian theory on the basis of the little that Nietzsche says here. Nietzsche seems to be assuming that happiness involves interested pleasure in some way because it is connected with desire. (i) Next, What is rejected and crossed out here, in any case, is precisely the one thing that Kant emphasizes in the aesthetic condition: le désintéressement. “One thing” is hardly fair. For Kant, disinterestedness is one necessary condition of pleasure in beauty, and there is much more to Kant’s account than that. Nietzsche seems to be picking up on one aspect of Kant’s view of pleasure in beauty and ignoring the rest. Nevertheless, it is true that, for Kant, pleasures in beauty not only are not based on desires but also do not produce desire by themselves (although Kant does allow that they may produce desire in conjunction with an “empirical” or “intellectual” interest, in sections 41 and 42 of the Critique of Judgment). Nietzsche’s NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 85 Stendahl would be relevant to Kant’s views on disinterestedness if we interpret Nietzsche as saying that pleasure in beauty produces desire of itself and, in this sense, pleasure in beauty “promises happiness.” Nietzsche, in fact, confirms that this is what he means later in the same section, while discussing Schopenhauer. He writes, “[T]he beautiful arouses the will (‘interestedness’).” It would still be possible to claim that pleasures in beauty are not grounded in desire, though they do produce desire. But that takes away the purity of the operation of taste, on Kant’s picture, as a faculty completely distinct from our practical and appetitive lives. The autonomy of the faculty is compromised. (j) Nietzsche asks, Who’s right, Kant or Stendhal? The reader hopes that Nietzsche’s answer to this question will help elucidate the Stendahlian theory. (k) What Nietzsche then says is disappointing in this respect, since he moves on to what seems like a new point, or one that is only loosely related: Admittedly if our aestheticians never tire of throwing into the balance in Kant’s favour, that under the influence of beauty people can look at even robeless female statues “without interest,” then we may laugh a little at their expense. This seems unfair as a criticism of Kant, for Kant can happily concede that some pleasures in contemplating nude female statues are interested pleasures. Kant allows for both disinterested pure pleasures and impure interested pleasures in the same thing. This is one point at which the apparent confusion of art and beauty, noted at the beginning of this paper, is important. For works of art are complex and may have many aspects other than their beauty. This seems a lapse on Nietzsche’s part. On the other hand, he says “our aestheticians,” so it is not clear that Kant himself is his target. A complication is that, although pleasure in contemplating the statue of the nude female may be pleasure in the beauty of the statue, such beauty may be what Kant calls dependent beauty. Dependent beauty is the beauty that a thing has as a thing of a teleological kind (Kant 1928, section 16). Beauty that is not “dependent” is “free” beauty. Furthermore, we can distinguish the (dependently) beautiful representation of a nude woman from the representation of a (dependently) beautiful woman. The statue may have both of these. It may also have free beauty (= nondependent beauty), and the appreciation of that free beauty may be disintinterested. The statue may have beauty of different kinds, and the pleasures taken in the statue may be of different kinds. 86 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY Perhaps Nietzsche does not see this, or else he is criticizing Kant for allowing such distinctions. But such distinctions are crucial, and they cast much light in aesthetics. It is obvious that we may take nonaesthetic pleasures in contemplating the nude statue, pleasures that are not disinterested. Furthermore, it is not obvious that we cannot also take pleasure in the statue’s free beauties, if any, where those pleasures are disinterested. It is not even clear that one cannot have pleasures in the beauty of the representation of the nude woman that are disinterested, even if one risks being laughed at a little. Why not, exactly? True, the erotic aspect should not be ignored. But a work of art is a complex thing, and we can appreciate many different aspects of one work in different ways. Thus, Nietzsche’s point about nude statues seems weak if Kant himself is his target. For Kant has a complex and variegated theory of the pleasures we take in art. However, Nietzsche seems not to be singling out Kant here but unnamed followers of Kant, who think of themselves as agreeing with Kant. So perhaps this is not meant to be an objection to Kant himself. (l) Nietzsche then writes, The experiences of artists in connection with this delicate matter are more “interesting,” and Pygmalion was in any case not necessarily an “un-aesthetic” human being. Again, Kant can concede that many pleasures taken in the contemplation of statues of female nudes and also flesh-and-blood nude females are interested pleasures. Kant would agree that Pygmalion’s red-blooded appreciation of fleshly female erotic beauty (a case of dependent beauty) is not disinterested. Still, some disinterested pleasures in contemplating nude female statues seem possible. (m) Nietzsche continues: Let’s think more highly of the innocence of our aestheticians that is reflected in such arguments. Nietzsche seems to be admitting that a distinction can be made between pure pleasures and impure ones since it is possible to be innocent. It is possible to view the statue innocently and also in a knowing sexual way. Both are possible. If so, what is the criticism of Kant and the argument in favor of Stendahl? (n) Next, For example, let us give Kant credit for knowing how to teach—with the naïveté of a country priest—about the characteristic properties of the sense of touch! NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 87 Two preliminary comments: First, “For example” seems to refer back to “our aestheticians” in the previous sentence and, thus, seems here to include Kant as one of them, as opposed to interpreters of Kant who might not get Kant right. This closes off an interpretative possibility left open earlier. Second, it is not obvious which passage of Kant Nietzsche had in mind. Nietzsche may have been thinking about a passage in the Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (Kant 2006), where Kant talks about the sense of touch as a way of knowing about physical shape It is not clear exactly how Nietzsche’s remark about touch bears on Kant’s views on disinterestedness. Is the suggested point that many pleasures of touch are not disinterested, being sensual or erotic? But why should that generate a difficulty for Kant? Kant can admit an erotic dimension to some of our pleasures of touch but distinguish that from pure pleasures in beauty, which typically derive from sight and hearing, not touch. Perhaps Nietzsche sees the point about touch as bearing on the possibility of viewing nude female statues disinterestedly. Perhaps when we look at the statue, we imagine touching it. Perhaps it is difficult or even impossible to enjoy particularly luscious female nude sculptures in a pure disinterested way. But strictly speaking, Nietzsche is not criticizing Kant here. Reading this sentence in its most straightforward way, Nietzsche is praising Kant for his naiveté in what he says about touch. That is to put possible irony to one side. But even if we suppose that Nietzsche was playfully mocking Kant, there is no reason to think that the implied point is that there is no nonerotic conception of the pleasures of touch. (o) Nietzsche resumes: And here we come back to Schopenhauer, who stood much closer to the arts than Kant and still did not get out from the spell of the Kantian definition. Since Nietzsche’s attention shifts away from Kant to Schopenhauer, I end my sentence-by-sentence commentary. 5. Discussion One way to take what Nietzsche seems to be implying here is that he thinks that what appears to be pure disinterested pleasure is, in fact, erotic or sexual pleasure, which puritan thinkers like Kant are blind to and do not recognize. Many think of Nietzsche as a proto-Freudian. But we need to see good reasons to accept a sexualized view of pleasure in beauty in general. I suppose it is possible that pleasure in beauty somehow has an erotic aspect that we are not aware of. Is Nietzsche, 88 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY like Aquinas, denying the existence of free beauty (see McCloskey 1987), but then, unlike Aquinas, claiming that all beauty is somehow erotic? I see no reason to think that Nietzsche thinks this. Nor is it plausible. We appreciate the beauty of many natural things, such as flowers, trees, and hills. What have they got to do with the erotic? One can view flowers, trees, and hills in a sexual way. But one need not, and it is implausible that we must do so in order to appreciate their beauty. Perhaps the pleasures taken in many Western figurative representational paintings have a sexual or erotic aspect, given the usual themes of those paintings. But we will need very strong reasons for thinking of pleasures taken in many natural beauties, abstract design, and absolute music (that is, music without words) as covertly sexual. (Musicologists sometimes argue for the prevalence of sexual content in absolute music, but I suspect that those claims reveal more about the musicologists than the music!) Alternatively, perhaps no general claim about beauty and the erotic is being claimed. Instead, the erotic beauty of nude female statues is supposed to be a particular telling example of a case where the defender of disinterested beauty might have difficulties. But what is the point that we are supposed to take from such examples? It is that the will is not distinct from pleasures in beauty, quite generally. It is obviously not in the case of erotic beauty. And the idea seems to be that we can generalize and think that other cases are mired in desire, but less obviously so. But how could we show that? How could we justify the generalization? And is erotic beauty really a form of beauty or merely a case of the agreeable? What, then, is Nietzsche’s point here? I think that he is not denying the possibility claim—that we can view nude female statues disinterestedly or even that pleasures in beauty are completely severed from desire and the will. Instead, what we have is a continuation of the praise of the passionate spectator, which is not a denial of the possibility of the disinterested spectator. Above all, Nietzsche is not making a general claim about the nature of aesthetic judgment and aesthetic pleasure. In that sense, he is not criticizing Kant’s analysis of pleasure in the beautiful. Nietzsche’s purpose, I believe, is normative, not so much a philosophical inquiry into the general nature of pleasure in beauty. Nietzsche admits the possibility and actuality of disinterested aesthetic appreciation but issues an evaluative challenge. Compare Hume, once again: Jerrold Levinson has argued that the real problem with Hume’s theory of taste, according to which we aspire to be “ideal critics” (where this is cashed out in terms of the various features of such a critic) is not that it is not descriptively adequate but that it does not answer the “normative question” about why we should want to be such an ideal critic or value being such an ideal critic (Levinson NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 89 2002). By analogy, Nietzsche is not, in these passages, criticizing Kant’s account according to which pleasure in the beautiful is disinterested. Instead, he is raising the normative question of why such pleasures should have the lofty or even supreme value traditionally accorded to them by Kant. There are also impure erotic interested pleasures, and the question is why we should value pure disinterested pleasures more than these. This is not a critique of the illusory purity of Kant’s judgment of taste (as many Marxists and feminists say). He grants the existence of such pleasures, of such judgments, and of the faculty for making such judgments; but he questions their value. Kant’s account cuts off pleasure in beauty from desire in that the pleasure is not based on desire, nor does it produce desire by itself in the way that pleasure in the agreeable does (Kant 1928, section 3; see Zangwill 1995). We can take Nietzsche to be denying not that aesthetic pleasure, as characterized by Kant, exists, but rather that aesthetic pleasure has the value Kant attaches to it, a value greater than that of interested pleasures. Kant’s more substantive account of the nature of the aesthetic pleasure is that it is the “free play of the cognitive faculties” (Kant 1928, section 9, 35–38). It is not merely that Kant has transferred the characteristics of knowledge in general to art, as Nietzsche says, but that aesthetic pleasure is a particular activity of the cognitive faculties, which produce knowledge. But what it is that produces knowledge is thought to be universal, sharable, not highly personal intense experiences of the sort that Nietzsche thinks that appreciating beauty involves. And that is Nietzsche’s problem—that something so widely sharable could not have the value of something preciously personal and particular. Kant’s reply cannot just be that that we need the pure aesthetic pleasures because of their role in our entire cognitive system. While such an account of their value gives them an essential function in our cognitive economy, that value is unacceptably instrumental. The value is not inherent in the pleasure itself. Nietzsche would also complain that that value is unacceptably dislocated from the other things we value greatly, the “personal intense experiences, desires [and] surprises” in our lives, which lie far both from the impersonal world of knowledge and the world of the rational will. Coda What we can take from this whole passage is the following. First, there is an interesting critique of the impersonal and impartial aspect of Kant’s disinterestedness doctrine, as opposed to the claim to 90 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY universal validity of the judgment of taste. For Kant, judgments of taste rest on something universal in human nature. So, correct judgments of taste, like the capacity to do the morally right thing, are available to all. Nietzsche disputes this democratic view. He thinks that beauty may be highly personal, elusive, and not universally available, and perhaps is available only to aristocratic souls in unusual enhanced ecstatic experiences. On this point, Nietzsche poses an insightful and interesting challenge to Kant’s idea that pleasure in beauty has its source in what we all share. Second, Nietzsche comments on beauty, desire, and erotic beauty are doing something different. Nietzsche’s point is a normative one and does not critique the adequacy of Kant’s account of pure disinterested pleasure. The point is to question the high value accorded to such pleasures, by contrast with pleasure that are intimately and immediately bound up with desire, such as the erotic pleasures of viewing nude female statues or felt by artists toward their models or to their imaginary creations. Here, too, there is a case to answer. Whence the superiority of the pure over the impure? In sum, we should be impressed by both Nietzsche’s idea of an elusive beauty that is not democratically available and his advocacy of impure pleasures. These two related criticisms have force and those who would defend Kant need to address them.* Durham University * Many thanks for very helpful comments from Lilian Alweiss, Daniel Came, Victor Dura Vila, two referees for this journal, and especially Rachel Zuckert REFERENCES Bourdieu, Pierre. 1984. Distinction. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. ———. 1996. “On the Historical Genesis of the Pure Aesthetic.” In The Rules of Art, 285–312. Oxford: Polity. Devereaux, Mary. 2003. “Feminist Aesthetics.” In Oxford Companion to Aesthetics, ed. Jerrold Levinson, 647–66. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Eagleton, Terry. 1984. The Ideology of the Aesthetic. Oxford: Blackwell. Foot, Philippa. 2002. Moral Dilemmas. Oxford: Clarendon. Hume, David. 1985. “Of the Standard of Taste.” In Essays: Moral, Political and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller, 226–49. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty. NIETZSCHE ON KANT ON BEAUTY AND DISINTERESTEDNESS 91 Kant, Immanuel. 1928. Critique of Judgment, trans. James Meredith. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ———. 2006. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. Ed. Robert B. Louden. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Korsmeyer, Carolyn. 2004. Gender and Aesthetics. London: Routledge. Levinson, Jerrold. 2002. “Hume’s Standard of Taste: The Real Problem.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60, no. 3: 227–38. McClosekey, Mary. 1987. Kant’s Aesthetic. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Mitrovic, Branko. 2004. Learning from Palladio. New York: W.W. Norton & Company. ———. 2005. Serene Greed of the Eye. Munich: Deutscher Kunstverlag. Nietzsche, Frederich. 1998: On the Geneology of Morals. Trans. Maudemarie Clarke and Alan J. Swensen. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Wolff, Janet. 1984. The Social Production of Art. London: Methuen. Wood, Allen. 2004. Kant. Oxford: Blackwell. Zangwill, Nick. 1992. “UnKantian Notions of Disinterest.” British Journal of Aesthetics 32, no. 2: 149–52. ———. 1995. “Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53, no. 2: 167–76 ———. 1999. “Feasible Aesthetic Formalism.” Nous 33, no. 4: 610–29; reprinted in Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty, 52–81. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001. ———. 2001. “Hume, Taste and Teleology.” In The Metaphysics of Beauty, 149–65. ———. 2002. “Against the Sociology of the Aesthetic.” Cultural Values 6, no. 4: 443–52; also printed in the Metaphysics of Beauty, 207–17. ———. 2003. “Aesthetic Realism.” Oxford Companion to of Aesthetics, ed. Jerrold Levinson, 63–79. Oxford: Oxford University Press. x