Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
INTRANSITIVE DICE arXiv:1311.6511v1 [math.CO] 25 Nov 2013 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON Abstract. We conjecture that the probability that a random triple of dice is intransitive is 1/4. 1. Introduction We define an n-sided die to be an n-tuple (a1 , . . . , an ) of non-decreasing integers, a1 ≤ a2 ≤ · · · ≤ an . We denote the standard n-sided die as Pn = (1, 2, 3, . . . , n). Notice that the sum of the faces on Pn is 1 + 2 + ··· + n = n(n + 1) . 2 We call an n-sided die proper if the sides are whole numbers between 1 and n inclusive and the sum of the faces is n(n+1) . 2 Thus, every proper die which is not a standard one has faces with repeated numbers, i.e. ai = ai+1 for at least one i with 1 ≤ i ≤ n − 1. Here is a list of proper dice for n ≤ 5: n=1 n=2 n=3 n=4 n=5 (1) (1, 2) (1, 2, 3), (2, 2, 2) (1, 1, 4, 4), (1, 2, 3, 4), (1, 3, 3, 3), (2, 2, 2, 4), (2, 2, 3, 3) (1, 1, 3, 5, 5), (1, 1, 4, 4, 5), (1, 2, 2, 5, 5), (1, 2, 3, 4, 5), (1, 2, 4, 4, 4), (1, 3, 3, 3, 5), (1, 3, 3, 4, 4), (2, 2, 2, 4, 5), (2, 2, 3, 3, 5), (2, 2, 3, 4, 4), (2, 3, 3, 3, 4), (3, 3, 3, 3, 3) Research supported in part by a grant from the National Science Foundation. 1 2 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON Here is a table of the number P r(n) of proper n-sided dice for n ≤ 28 (sequence A076822 in the Online Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences): n 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 25 26 27 28 P r(n) 1 1 2 5 12 32 94 289 910 2934 9686 32540 110780 381676 1328980 4669367 16535154 58965214 211591218 763535450 2769176514 10089240974 36912710568 135565151486 499619269774 1847267563742 6850369296298 If we have two proper n-sided dice A = (a1 , . . . , an ) and B = (b1 , . . . , bn ) we say that A > B if the probability that A “rolls” a higher value than B is greater than the probability that B “rolls” a higher value than A. Put another way, if the probability that a randomly selected number from A is larger than a randomly selected number from B, then we say that A beats B and write A > B. Formally, A > B if and only if n X i,j=1 ai >bj 1> n X 1. i,j=1 bj >ai If the two sums are equal then we say that A and B tie. A table can help to make the comparisons. For example, if A = (1, 2, 4, 4, 4, 6) and B = (2, 2, 3, 3, 5, 6) then the table of INTRANSITIVE DICE 3 comparisons below shows that out of the 36 possible rolls A wins 17 times, B wins 16 times and there are 3 ties. Therefore, we say A > B. A\B 1 2 4 4 4 6 2 B A A A A 2 B A A A A 3 B B A A A A 3 B B A A A A 5 B B B B B A 6 B B B B B - One might think that given proper n-sided dice A, B and C that f A > B and B > C then it necessarily follows that A > C, i.e. that “beats” is a transitive relation. But it’s not! For example, if A = (1, 1, 4, 4), B = (1, 3, 3, 3), and C = (2, 2, 2, 4) then it is easy to check that A beats B, B beats C, and C beats A. Such a triple of dice is called intransitive. Specifically, a set of three dice is called “transitive” if there is a labeling A, B, C of the dice such that A > B, A > C, and B > C; it is called intransitive if there is a labeling such that A > B, B > C, and C > A. It is counter-intuitive that intransitive dice exist. But given that they do, one’s intuition might lead one to believe that they are rare. The purpose of this paper is to give evidence that suggests that not only do they exist but they are quite common! Suppose one is given a randomly selected set {A, B, C, . . . , Y, Z} of dice. Suppose you tabulate all but one of the pairwise comparisons A versus B, A versus C, B versus C and so on of these dice but leaving the last one Y versus Z unchecked. Surely knowing all of the previous comparisons must have some effect on the last one? We conjecture that it does not! Rather, independently of all of the checks made so far it is equally likely that Y beats Z as that Z beats Y , at least when we are sampling from proper n-sided dice and n → ∞. 2. Triples of dice Suppose we choose 3 n-sided proper dice at random from the set of all n-sided proper dice. Assuming there are no ties the triple of dice we get is either transitive, i.e., one die beats the other two or else it is intransitive, i.e., each die beats one other. What is the probability that our random triple is intransitive? As an example, consider the case where n = 4. There are 5 proper dice and so 53 = 10 different triples of dice. Exactly one of those triples is intransitive (namely the one mentioned above) and so the probability that a triple of proper 4-sided dice is intransitive is 1/10. We investigated this numerically. Our data, based on 10,000 experiments for each of 10-sided, 20-sided, 30-sided, 40-sided, and 50-sided dice, is below. We used two different methods (labeled I and II, both of which we believe to be approximately uniform over our collection of proper dice) to generate proper dice and found 4 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON n 10 20 30 40 50 %intrans, I % intrans, II 15.7 15.8 21.3 20.6 22.0 21.9 22.9 23.3 23.7 22.9 We began to suspect that the correct answer is 25% and we formalize that here with Conjecture 1. Suppose three dice are chosen at random from the collection of n-sided proper dice. Then, the probability that this triple is intransitive approaches 1/4 as n → ∞. We believe that this conjecture will be difficult to prove. But we do have some theoretical evidence, namely if we dilute the sample space (almost to nothing!) then we can prove this conjecture. The simplest possible case is when each die in the population from which we sample deviates from the standard die Pn by as little as possible. This occurs when one face is increased by one and another face is decreased by one. For example, (1, 2, 3, 4, 4, 6, 7, 9, 9, 10) is a 10-sided die that differs from the standard die P10 in that the 8 increases to 9 and the 5 decreases to 4. We denote this die by s(8, 5). We studied triples of n-sided dice that all have this shape s(a, b) which means that face a increases by one and face b decreases by one. We call these “1-step” dice. How many 1-step dice are there? If n = 3 there is only 1: s(1, 3) = (2, 2, 2) If n = 4, we have s(1, 3) s(1, 4) s(2, 4) s(3, 2) = = = = (2, 2, 2, 4) (2, 2, 3, 3) (1, 3, 3, 3) (1, 1, 4, 4) INTRANSITIVE DICE 5 If n = 5, we have s(1, 3) s(1, 4) s(1, 5) s(2, 4) s(2, 5) s(3, 2) s(3, 5) s(4, 2) s(4, 3) = = = = = = = = = (2, 2, 2, 4, 5) (2, 2, 3, 3, 5) (2, 2, 3, 4, 4) (1, 3, 3, 3, 5) (1, 3, 3, 4, 4) (1, 1, 4, 4, 5) (1, 2, 4, 4, 4) (1, 1, 3, 5, 5) (1, 2, 2, 5, 5) How many n-sided one-step dice are there? We can pick a as the face to increase in (n − 1) different ways—we can’t allow an increase in face n. And we can decrease (n − 3) different faces— we don’t allow a decrease in face 1 or in the face that went up or in the face after the one that went up. Of course, if we increase face number 1 then we can decrease in faces 3, 4, . . . , n. In total we find that there are n2 − 4n + 4 = (n − 2)2 1-step dice. So there are (n − 2)2 3 triples of dice we could select for our experiment. However, in practice we find that almost all such triples involve ties. For example, the standard die ties with every other proper die! The following lemma is easily checked. Lemma 1. If s(a, b) and s(c, d) are proper n-sided dice and s(a, b) > s(c, d), then s(a, b) > s(c, d) has one of the following four forms: s(x, y) s(x, y) s(x + 1, y) s(x, y + 1) > > > > s(y, z) s(z, x + 2) s(x, z) s(z, y) where a, b, c, d are numbers between 1 and n (with some obvious restrictions such as a 6= 1, a 6= b, etc.) We give some examples of each of these four types of inequalities. We have circled the places where “something out of the ordinary” happens, i.e. the pattern of A’s below the main diagional, − on the main diagonal, and B’s above the main diagonal that one would see if the standard die were matched against itself. 6 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON s(X,Y) > s(Y,Z) B = s(5,8) A = s(2,5) s(X,Y) > s(Z,X+2) A = s(4,9) B = s(1,6) INTRANSITIVE DICE 7 s(X+1,Y) > s(X,Z) B = s(5,2) A=s(6,9) s(X,Y+1) > s(Z,Y) B = s(8,4) A= s(1,5) Using this lemma we see for example that the triple A = s(X, X + 2), B = s(X, Z), C = s(X + 1, Y ) produces a triple where A < B by the second of the inequalities above, 8 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON B < C by the third inequality and A < C by the third inequality. This triple will be proper as long as 1 ≤ X ≤ n − 2, 2 ≤ Y ≤ n and 2 ≤ Z ≤ n. The value X = n is not allowed because then dice A would be s(n, n+2) which has a face labeled n+1 which is not permitted in n-sided proper dice. Similarly neither Y = 1 nor Z = 1 is permitted since they would lead to a face labeled 0. There are actually 64 different cases of triples of proper 1-step dice that are mutually comparable. The example s(X, X + 2), s(X, Z), s(X + 1, Y ) is one of those 64. In our next lemma, we list all 64 of these cases, the first one being this example we have just discussed. It is extremely tedious to find and list all 64 of these cases; we have used a computer to help make sure that we have found all of them and that they are all different from each other. Each case leads to a parametric solution of triples, i.e. we can substitute numbers from 1 to n in for the parameters X, Y, Z and so have numerical triples of proper n-sided 1-step dice. There are some issues of coincidences and boundaries but the order of magnitude of these exceptions is n2 amongst the n3 triples produced by one of our parametrizations. Lemma 2. Suppose we have three proper n-sided dice s(a, b), s(c, d) and s(e, f ) that are mutually comparable, i.e. between each pair one is better. Then the three dice {s(a, b), s(c, d), s(e, f )} can be represented by one of the following 64 triples: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 s(X, 2 + X) s(X, 2 + X) s(X, 4 + X) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Y ) s(X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(1 + X, 3 + X) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Z, X) s(Z, X) s(Z, X) s(1 + X, Y ) s(2 + X, Y ) s(2 + X, Y ) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, 1 + Z) s(2 + X, X) s(2 + X, 1 + Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Y, 1 + Z) s(1 + Y, X) s(1 + Y, 2 + X) s(Z, X) s(1 + Z, X) s(1 + Z, 2 + X) s(1 + Z, 1 + Y ) INTRANSITIVE DICE 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 1 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 2 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(X, 3 + Y ) s(1 + X, 1 + Y ) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, 2 + Z) s(Y, X) s(Y, X) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(1 + Y, Z) s(1 + Y, 2 + Z) s(Z, X) s(Z, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(1 + X, Y ) s(1 + X, Y ) s(1 + X, 2 + Y ) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, Z) s(1 + X, 1 + Z) s(Y, 1 + X) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, 4 + Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, Z) s(Y, 1 + Z) s(Y, 2 + Z) s(Y, 2 + Z) s(Y, 2 + Z) s(2 + Y, Y ) s(Y, X) s(Y, X) s(Y, 2 + X) s(Y, 2 + X) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, 2 + Y ) s(Y, 4 + Y ) s(Y, 4 + Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(2 + X, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(Z, Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(Z, Y ) s(2 + Y, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(Z, Y ) s(1 + Z, Y ) s(1 + Z, X) s(1 + Z, 2 + X) s(1 + Z, Y ) s(1 + Z, 2 + Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Z, 1 + Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Y, 1 + X) s(Y, 1 + Z) s(Y, Z) s(Z, X) s(Y, Z) s(2 + Y, Z) s(Z, 1 + Y ) s(2 + Y, Z) s(Y, 1 + Z) s(1 + Y, X) s(1 + Y, 2 + X) s(1 + Y, 3 + Y ) s(2 + Y, Y ) s(2 + Y, 1 + Z) s(Z, X) s(Z, 1 + Y ) s(2 + Y, Z) s(Z, X) s(Z, 2 + X) s(Z, 1 + Y ) s(Z, 1 + Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(Z, 2 + Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(Z, 2 + Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(Z, 2 + Y ) s(1 + Y, Z) s(Z, 2 + Y ) 9 10 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON In these triples the letters X, Y and Z are allowed to be anything from 1 to n as long as the dice produced are proper n-sided dice. We analyze each case as follows. The four reasons for one die beating another may be labeled as (1) s(x, y) > s(y, z) (2) s(x, y) > s(z, x + 2) (3) s(x + 1, y) > s(x, z) (4) s(x, y + 1) > s(z, y) Then the reasoning for case 1 may be described as: A B C B C C = = = > > > s(X, 2 + X) s(X, Z) s(1 + X, Y ) A (2) B (3) A (3) Since C > B and C > A this triple is transitive. We analyzed all of the triples in this way and found (briefly expressed): 1.T : (2)(3)(3) CBA 5.T : (3)(2)(3) CBA 9.T : (1)(2)(1) ACB 13.I : (1)(1)(1) ABC 17.T : (3)(4)(4) BAC 21.I : (1)(3)(1) ACB 25.T : (1)(3)(4) ACB 29.T : (4)(3)(1) CAB 33.T : (3)(1)(2) BCA 37.T : (3)(4)(2) CBA 41.T : (2)(1)(1) BAC 45.T : (2)(3)(1) CBA 49.I : (2)(4)(1) ACB 53.T : (2)(2)(1) CBA 57.T : (1)(3)(2) CBA 61.T : (4)(3)(2) CAB 2.I : (3)(3)(1) ACB 6.T : (3)(4)(3) CBA 10.T : (1)(4)(1) ACB 14.T : (1)(3)(1) CBA 18.I : (3)(3)(4) ACB 22.I : (1)(1)(4) ACB 26.T : (1)(1)(4) ABC 30.T : (4)(3)(2) ACB 34.I : (3)(4)(4) ACB 38.T : (3)(4)(2) BCA 42.T : (2)(4)(4) BAC 46.I : (2)(3)(2) ACB 50.T : (2)(1)(1) BCA 54.I : (2)(2)(2) ACB 58.T : (1)(2)(4) BAC 62.T : (4)(2)(4) ABC 3.T : (3)(3)(2) CBA 7.T : (3)(3)(1) CBA 11.T : (1)(3)(1) CAB 15.I : (1)(3)(2) ACB 19.T : (3)(1)(4) BAC 23.I : (4)(3)(1) ACB 27.T : (1)(2)(4) ACB 31.T : (4)(3)(4) ACB 35.T : (3)(2)(2) CBA 39.T : (2)(4)(1) BCA 43.I : (2)(2)(1) ACB 47.T : (2)(3)(4) CBA 51.T : (2)(1)(4) BAC 55.I : (2)(2)(4) ACB 59.T : (2)(3)(2) CAB 63.T : (4)(3)(2) CBA 4.T : (4)(3)(3) CBA 8.T : (3)(3)(4) CBA 12.T : (1)(3)(2) ACB 16.T : (1)(3)(4) CBA 20.I : (3)(2)(4) ACB 24.I : (4)(1)(4) ACB 28.I : (1)(3)(4) ACB 32.T : (4)(3)(4) CAB 36.T : (3)(1)(2) CBA 40.T : (2)(2)(2) CBA 44.T : (2)(4)(2) CBA 48.I : (2)(1)(1) ACB 52.T : (2)(4)(1) BAC 56.T : (1)(4)(4) ACB 60.T : (2)(2)(4) ABC 64.T : (4)(2)(4) BAC We give an example of how to read this table. Recall that entry 38 from our lemma corresponds to A = s(X, 2 + Y ), B = s(1 + X, 1 + Z) and C = s(Y, Z). Now entry 38 above says T : (3)(4)(2) BCA. The reasons (3)(4)(2) are for the comparisons A versus B, B versus C and C versus A in that order. The BCA together with the T (for transitive) means that INTRANSITIVE DICE 11 B > C, C > A, and B > A. In entry 46 we have an I for intransitive so that the letters ACB mean that A > C > B > A. Now notice that the 17 cases 2, 13, 15, 18, 20, 21, 22, 23, 24, 28, 34, 43, 46, 48, 49, 54 and 55 all give intransitive triples and the other 47 cases give transitive triples. In general given a triple, we let the variables X, Y , and Z run from 1 to n and in doing so produce n3 triples of mutually comparable n-sided proper dice. There are some boundary issues for values of X, Y and Z near to 1 or to n. But the number of such boundary issues is O(n2 ) and so does not effect the main term which is of order of magnitude n3 . However, two of our 64 triples are special, namely numbers 13 and 54 s(X, Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Z, X) and s(X, Y ) s(Y, Z) s(Z, X) in that they have automorphisms. Each of these produces 3 repeats when X, Y, and Z are allowed to run from 1 to n. So really each should be counted with a weight 1/3. This means that our 64 cases are really 62 23 cases. And 15 23 of these cases are intransitive. Notice that 15 23 is exactly 1/4 of 62 23 . Thus, we have found 188 3 n + O(n2 ) 3 triples of mutually comparable n-sided 1-step dice. Of these, 47 3 n + O(n2 ) 3 are intransitive. We take take the ratio as n → ∞ and get 1/4. Thus, we have proven Theorem 1. Consider the space of all triples of proper n-sided one step dice which have the property that no two of the dice on the triple tie each other. Then, in the limit as n → ∞ we have 1/4 of the triples are intransitive. 3. 4 or more dice We have a more general conjecture about what happens with larger sets of proper dice. To explain this we look at the case of triples in a different light. There are 8 possible orderings among 3 dice A, B, and C (we assume there are no ties). Namely A>B B>C C>A A>B A>B A>B A<B A<B A<B B B B B B B C C C C C C >C <C <C >C >C <C <A >A <A >A <A >A 12 BRIAN CONREY, JAMES GABBARD, KATIE GRANT, ANDREW LIU, KENT MORRISON A<B B<C C<A Two of these are intransitive (the first and last) and all the others are transitive. We conjecture that all 8 of these cases are equally likely. Then the 1/4 of our earlier conjecture is just a reflection of this more general conjecture together with the fact that 2 of the 8 scenarios above are intransitive. If we have four n-sided proper dice A, B, C, and D, then we expect every possible relation between any two dice to be equally likely. Now there are 4 2( 2 ) = 26 = 64 different possibilities. We expect each choice of relation to occur 1/64th of the time. What are the possible scenarios now? There are I. Completely Transitive. For example, A > B, C, D; B > C, D; C > D; II. One dominant plus intransitive loop. A > B, C, D; B > C > D > B; III. One inferior plus an intransitive loop. A < B, C, D; B > C > D > B; IV No dominant, no inferior. A > B, C; B > C, D; D > A; C > D. How do the 64 assignments split up into these categories? (3,2,1,0) Completely Transitive. For example A > B, C, D; B > C, D; C > D . A has 3 wins; B has 2 wins; C has 1 win; and D has 0 wins. With relabelings there are are 4! = 24 of these. So the probability of getting this configuration is 24/64 = 3/8. (3,1,1,1) One dominant plus intransitive loop: A > B, C, D; B > C > D > B. There are 4 ways to pick the big winner, then two ways to cycle around the intransitive loop. This accounts for 4 × 2 = 8 with relabelings; the probability that 4 random dice are in this configuration is 1/8. (2,2,2,0) One inferior plus an intransitive loop: A < B, C, D; B > C > D > B. Just as the previous case there are 4 × 2 = 8 of these. (2,2,1,1) No dominant, no inferior A > B, C; B > C, D; D > A; C > D. Choose the two winners in 42 = 6 ways. Then choose which of the “winners” beats the other and which of the “losers” beats the other. There are 24 cases. This configuration has 2 intransitive loops and occurs in 3/8 random choices of 4 dice. It’s possible to do similar analysis with any number of dice. The big conjecture is that when choosing k dice from a large collection of proper n-sided dice, the probability of each k of the 2( 2 ) possible assignments of < or > to each pair of dice is equally likely in the limit as n → ∞. INTRANSITIVE DICE 13 In practice to calculate the probability that k dice will roll to give a specified configuration, i.e., a tournament graph on k-vertices, all one needs to do is to calculate the probability of that tournament graph (or an isomorphic copy) arising from a random assignment of edge directions on the complete graph on k-vertices. Here is an example with 5 dice: 5 dice example (2,2,2,2,2) Intransitive cycles (ABE) (BCE) (CDE) (DEA) (EAB) (ABEC) (ADBE) (ADEC) (ADBC) (BECD) (ABCDE) (ADBEC) A=(1,1,3,5,5) B=(1,3,3,4,4) A E C=(2,2,2,4,5) D=(1,2,4,4,4) B E=(2,2,3,3,5) D C The probability of getting this configuration from 5 randomly chosen dice should be 5!/2^10=15/128=0.117 We conclude with a possible way to generalize the conjecture to functions. Suppose we have the space of monotonic functions f on [0, 1] with f (0) = 0 and f (1) = 1. If f and g are two such functions then we say that f > g if Z 1 Z 1 sign(f (x) − g(x)) dx > sign(g(x) − f (x)) dx. 0 0 Then, with an appopriate measure on this space we conjecture that if three such functions are chosen at random, the probability that they form an intransitive triple is 1/4. And similarly for random choices of k such functions. American Institute of Mathematics, 360 Portage Ave, Palo Alto, CA 94306 USA