
Some Principles of Logic
... is probably but not necessarily true • The conclusion contains information not present, even implicitly, in the premises ...
... is probably but not necessarily true • The conclusion contains information not present, even implicitly, in the premises ...
ordinal logics and the characterization of informal concepts of proof
... is also a proof predicate, but Gonx8 is provable in (S) itself. To give a precise treatment of this idea of recognizing a proof predicate as such we shall consider formal systems whose constants are not only numerical terms and function symbols, but also proof predicates. This is independently justi ...
... is also a proof predicate, but Gonx8 is provable in (S) itself. To give a precise treatment of this idea of recognizing a proof predicate as such we shall consider formal systems whose constants are not only numerical terms and function symbols, but also proof predicates. This is independently justi ...
sentential logic
... and here "he" refers to the player. But if it is not clear who you are pointing to, then we might not know to whom the pronoun refers, and so might not be able to determine whether you are saying something true. Referential ambiguity can also arise if you are talking about a group using an expressio ...
... and here "he" refers to the player. But if it is not clear who you are pointing to, then we might not know to whom the pronoun refers, and so might not be able to determine whether you are saying something true. Referential ambiguity can also arise if you are talking about a group using an expressio ...
Justification logic with approximate conditional probabilities
... us the connection between justification formulas and probabilistic formulas. Rules 3 and 4 are infinitary rules of inference and Rule 3 states that the probability of any formula belongs to S. Rule 5 formalizes that in neat models only the empty set has probability zero. This rule makes it possible ...
... us the connection between justification formulas and probabilistic formulas. Rules 3 and 4 are infinitary rules of inference and Rule 3 states that the probability of any formula belongs to S. Rule 5 formalizes that in neat models only the empty set has probability zero. This rule makes it possible ...
Dependent Types In Lambda Cube
... This work covers to a certain extent some backgrounds for author’s further study of dependent types. Chapter 2 contains basic information about two different special dependent types - Pi-type and Sigma-type. The chapter also discuss the problem of confusing terminology for these types and tries to ex ...
... This work covers to a certain extent some backgrounds for author’s further study of dependent types. Chapter 2 contains basic information about two different special dependent types - Pi-type and Sigma-type. The chapter also discuss the problem of confusing terminology for these types and tries to ex ...
Hugs (Haskell)
... Variables begin with a lowercase letter Type names begin with an uppercase letter Braces and semicolons can be used, but it’s not common Tabs can really obscure the indentation; set your text editor to replace tabs with spaces ...
... Variables begin with a lowercase letter Type names begin with an uppercase letter Braces and semicolons can be used, but it’s not common Tabs can really obscure the indentation; set your text editor to replace tabs with spaces ...
A Recursively Axiomatizable Subsystem of Levesque`s Logic of Only
... that serves as the skeleton for our model. Next, we associate to every node of the tree a maximal consistent set of sentences of a suitable language. Then we associate to every node of the tree a dierent possible world (i.e., set of atomic sentences). Finally, an accessibility relation is dened on ...
... that serves as the skeleton for our model. Next, we associate to every node of the tree a maximal consistent set of sentences of a suitable language. Then we associate to every node of the tree a dierent possible world (i.e., set of atomic sentences). Finally, an accessibility relation is dened on ...
From proof theory to theories theory
... theorems, and thus require a theory, has be given up and proofs have been studied for for their own sake. A typical example is linear logic [24]. The thesis we shall develop in this paper is that there is another possible way to go for proof theory: modify the notion of theory so that it can be prop ...
... theorems, and thus require a theory, has be given up and proofs have been studied for for their own sake. A typical example is linear logic [24]. The thesis we shall develop in this paper is that there is another possible way to go for proof theory: modify the notion of theory so that it can be prop ...
Document
... it must be shown that there exists some x in D such that (P(x ) → Q(x )) is not true This means that there exists some x in D such that P(x) is true but Q(x) is not true. Such an x is called a counterexample of the above implication To show that ∀x (P(x) → Q(x)) is false by finding an x in D such ...
... it must be shown that there exists some x in D such that (P(x ) → Q(x )) is not true This means that there exists some x in D such that P(x) is true but Q(x) is not true. Such an x is called a counterexample of the above implication To show that ∀x (P(x) → Q(x)) is false by finding an x in D such ...
GLukG logic and its application for non-monotonic reasoning
... following two properties: (i) is closed under modus ponens (i.e. if A and A → B are in the logic, then so is B) and (ii) is closed under substitution (i.e. if a formula A is in the logic, then any other formula obtained by replacing all occurrences of an atom b in A with another formula B is still i ...
... following two properties: (i) is closed under modus ponens (i.e. if A and A → B are in the logic, then so is B) and (ii) is closed under substitution (i.e. if a formula A is in the logic, then any other formula obtained by replacing all occurrences of an atom b in A with another formula B is still i ...
slides
... But first-class functions are useful anywhere for any kind of data – Can pass several functions as arguments – Can put functions in data structures (tuples, lists, etc.) – Can return functions as results – Can write higher-order functions that traverse your own data ...
... But first-class functions are useful anywhere for any kind of data – Can pass several functions as arguments – Can put functions in data structures (tuples, lists, etc.) – Can return functions as results – Can write higher-order functions that traverse your own data ...
Document
... two-valued logic – every sentence is either true or false some sentences are minimal – no proper part which is also a sentence others – can be taken apart into smaller parts we can build larger sentences from smaller ones by using connectives ...
... two-valued logic – every sentence is either true or false some sentences are minimal – no proper part which is also a sentence others – can be taken apart into smaller parts we can build larger sentences from smaller ones by using connectives ...
Post Systems in Programming Languages Pr ecis 1 Introduction
... of a premise. If a variable appears twice in a premise, then any instance of the production must insert the same string in place of all occurrences of the variable. A single production in a grammar cannot achieve the same result (although the same eect can be achieved in a grammar through a complex ...
... of a premise. If a variable appears twice in a premise, then any instance of the production must insert the same string in place of all occurrences of the variable. A single production in a grammar cannot achieve the same result (although the same eect can be achieved in a grammar through a complex ...
Chapter 2, Logic
... The three examples at the end of the last section illustrate some of the limitations of Aristotelian Logic, yet little was done extend formal Logic until Mathematicians began to take an interest in the subject. For more that two millennia after Aristotle’s death Logic, despite minor amplifications, ...
... The three examples at the end of the last section illustrate some of the limitations of Aristotelian Logic, yet little was done extend formal Logic until Mathematicians began to take an interest in the subject. For more that two millennia after Aristotle’s death Logic, despite minor amplifications, ...
CSE 452: Programming Languages
... The process of determining useful values for variables in propositions to find values for variables that allow the resolution process to succeed. ...
... The process of determining useful values for variables in propositions to find values for variables that allow the resolution process to succeed. ...
a basis for a mathematical theory of computation
... Composition. Now we shall describe the ways in which new functions are defined from old. The first way may be called (generalized) composition and involves the use of forms. We shall use the letters x, y, ... (sometimes with subscripts) for variables and will suppose that there is a notation for co ...
... Composition. Now we shall describe the ways in which new functions are defined from old. The first way may be called (generalized) composition and involves the use of forms. We shall use the letters x, y, ... (sometimes with subscripts) for variables and will suppose that there is a notation for co ...
A Basis for a Mathematical Theory of Computation
... Composition. Now we shall describe the ways in which new functions are defined from old. The first way may be called (generalized) composition and involves the use of forms. We shall use the letters x, y, ... (sometimes with subscripts) for variables and will suppose that there is a notation for co ...
... Composition. Now we shall describe the ways in which new functions are defined from old. The first way may be called (generalized) composition and involves the use of forms. We shall use the letters x, y, ... (sometimes with subscripts) for variables and will suppose that there is a notation for co ...
4.1 Characteristics of Functional Programming Languages Chapter
... result or possibly both. Although imperative languages can provide similar functionality, for example C allows function pointers to be passed to other functions, syntactically these can be much cumbersome than in functional languages. Let’s take a look at higher order functions in the functional pro ...
... result or possibly both. Although imperative languages can provide similar functionality, for example C allows function pointers to be passed to other functions, syntactically these can be much cumbersome than in functional languages. Let’s take a look at higher order functions in the functional pro ...
Definability properties and the congruence closure
... to Friedman [Fr], and later generalized in [MaSh1, 2]. Recently Hella [HI has shown strong results which intersect at some points with ours, implying for example that AL,o,o(Q~,Q,+ 1) and Beth L~oo,(Q~)are not finitely generated for regular c% All logics considered in this paper will be single sorte ...
... to Friedman [Fr], and later generalized in [MaSh1, 2]. Recently Hella [HI has shown strong results which intersect at some points with ours, implying for example that AL,o,o(Q~,Q,+ 1) and Beth L~oo,(Q~)are not finitely generated for regular c% All logics considered in this paper will be single sorte ...
Identity and Harmony revisited ∗ Stephen Read University of St Andrews
... Is identity a logical operator? The rules for identity in a natural deduction setting are usually given in the form of Reflexivity and Congruence (see, e.g., [9] p. 77): a=b p Congr Refl a=a p(b/a) Here, p(b/a) denotes the result of replacing one or more occurrences of the term a in p by b. Refl wou ...
... Is identity a logical operator? The rules for identity in a natural deduction setting are usually given in the form of Reflexivity and Congruence (see, e.g., [9] p. 77): a=b p Congr Refl a=a p(b/a) Here, p(b/a) denotes the result of replacing one or more occurrences of the term a in p by b. Refl wou ...
Non-classical metatheory for non-classical logics
... that it satisfies condition (i), it is often pointed out that it is not fully faithful because it fails to represent the intended interpretation and other possible interpretations of a first order language which are too large to form a set. I think there are two points that ought to be made at this ...
... that it satisfies condition (i), it is often pointed out that it is not fully faithful because it fails to represent the intended interpretation and other possible interpretations of a first order language which are too large to form a set. I think there are two points that ought to be made at this ...