
Document
... Rules of Inference • Definition: An argument in propositional logic is a sequence of propositions. All but the final proposition in the argument are called premises and the final proposition is called the conclusion. An argument is valid if the truth of all its premises implies that the conclusion ...
... Rules of Inference • Definition: An argument in propositional logic is a sequence of propositions. All but the final proposition in the argument are called premises and the final proposition is called the conclusion. An argument is valid if the truth of all its premises implies that the conclusion ...
department of mathematics
... the responsibility of the student. Class begins promptly and you are expected to be present at the beginning and at the end of each class session. HOMEWORK POLICY: Homework problems are the best preparation for exams. You should try to work the homework problems without constant reference to the tex ...
... the responsibility of the student. Class begins promptly and you are expected to be present at the beginning and at the end of each class session. HOMEWORK POLICY: Homework problems are the best preparation for exams. You should try to work the homework problems without constant reference to the tex ...
Indexed Classes of Sets Let I be any nonempty set, and let S be a
... B, if there exists a one-to-one correspondence f : A → B . A set A is finite if A is empty or if A has the same cardinality as the set {1, 2, . . . , n} for some positive integer n. A set is infinite if it is not finite. Familiar examples of infinite sets are the natural numbers N, the integers Z, the r ...
... B, if there exists a one-to-one correspondence f : A → B . A set A is finite if A is empty or if A has the same cardinality as the set {1, 2, . . . , n} for some positive integer n. A set is infinite if it is not finite. Familiar examples of infinite sets are the natural numbers N, the integers Z, the r ...
Logic - Decision Procedures
... (3) I have not filed any of them that I can read; (4) None of them, that are written on one sheet, are undated; (5) All of them, that are not crossed, are in black ink; (6) All of them, written by Brown, begin with "Dear Sir"; (7) All of them, written on blue paper, are filed; (8) None of them, writ ...
... (3) I have not filed any of them that I can read; (4) None of them, that are written on one sheet, are undated; (5) All of them, that are not crossed, are in black ink; (6) All of them, written by Brown, begin with "Dear Sir"; (7) All of them, written on blue paper, are filed; (8) None of them, writ ...
Principia Mathematica

The Principia Mathematica is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics, written by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. In 1927, it appeared in a second edition with an important Introduction To the Second Edition, an Appendix A that replaced ✸9 and an all-new Appendix C.PM, as it is often abbreviated, was an attempt to describe a set of axioms and inference rules in symbolic logic from which all mathematical truths could in principle be proven. As such, this ambitious project is of great importance in the history of mathematics and philosophy, being one of the foremost products of the belief that such an undertaking may be achievable. However, in 1931, Gödel's incompleteness theorem proved definitively that PM, and in fact any other attempt, could never achieve this lofty goal; that is, for any set of axioms and inference rules proposed to encapsulate mathematics, either the system must be inconsistent, or there must in fact be some truths of mathematics which could not be deduced from them.One of the main inspirations and motivations for PM was the earlier work of Gottlob Frege on logic, which Russell discovered allowed for the construction of paradoxical sets. PM sought to avoid this problem by ruling out the unrestricted creation of arbitrary sets. This was achieved by replacing the notion of a general set with the notion of a hierarchy of sets of different 'types', a set of a certain type only allowed to contain sets of strictly lower types. Contemporary mathematics, however, avoids paradoxes such as Russell's in less unwieldy ways, such as the system of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.PM is not to be confused with Russell's 1903 Principles of Mathematics. PM states: ""The present work was originally intended by us to be comprised in a second volume of Principles of Mathematics... But as we advanced, it became increasingly evident that the subject is a very much larger one than we had supposed; moreover on many fundamental questions which had been left obscure and doubtful in the former work, we have now arrived at what we believe to be satisfactory solutions.""The Modern Library placed it 23rd in a list of the top 100 English-language nonfiction books of the twentieth century.