
The Axiom of Choice
... As you probably know, it is possible to make discussions involving sets precise via “axiomatic set theory.” In this class, we have chosen a more informal approach to sets, simply thinking of them as bins that we throw objects (numbers, other sets, or whatever) into. In fact, this is how the vast maj ...
... As you probably know, it is possible to make discussions involving sets precise via “axiomatic set theory.” In this class, we have chosen a more informal approach to sets, simply thinking of them as bins that we throw objects (numbers, other sets, or whatever) into. In fact, this is how the vast maj ...
F - Teaching-WIKI
... being conceptually simple; they directly manipulate interpretations of sentences • Unfortunately, the number of interpretations of a language grows exponentially with the number of logical constants. – When the number of logical constants in a propositional language is large, the number of interpret ...
... being conceptually simple; they directly manipulate interpretations of sentences • Unfortunately, the number of interpretations of a language grows exponentially with the number of logical constants. – When the number of logical constants in a propositional language is large, the number of interpret ...
The Formulae-as-Classes Interpretation of Constructive Set Theory
... (see [16]) to discover a simple formalism that relates to Bishop’s constructive mathematics as classical Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory with the axiom of choice relates to classical Cantorian mathematics. CST provides a standard set theoretical framework for the development of constructive mathematics ...
... (see [16]) to discover a simple formalism that relates to Bishop’s constructive mathematics as classical Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory with the axiom of choice relates to classical Cantorian mathematics. CST provides a standard set theoretical framework for the development of constructive mathematics ...
finite structural axiomatization of every finite
... which is not finitely based, i.e., for every consequence C + determined by a finite set of standard rules C 6= C + . In this paper it will be proved that for every strongly finite consequence C there is a consequence C + determined ...
... which is not finitely based, i.e., for every consequence C + determined by a finite set of standard rules C 6= C + . In this paper it will be proved that for every strongly finite consequence C there is a consequence C + determined ...
1 Introduction: Historical Background
... The rest of this paper is organized as follows: In Section 2 we give a characterization of the generalized Carmichael numbers and establish contact with the function g. In Section 3 we discuss several special cases and prove in particular, that C is nite and that Ck is innite whenever 1 , k > 1 is ...
... The rest of this paper is organized as follows: In Section 2 we give a characterization of the generalized Carmichael numbers and establish contact with the function g. In Section 3 we discuss several special cases and prove in particular, that C is nite and that Ck is innite whenever 1 , k > 1 is ...
Real Numbers and Monotone Sequences
... Look down the list of numbers. We claim that after a while the integer part and first k decimal places of the numbers on the list no longer change. Take these unchanging values to be the corresponding places of the decimal expansion of the limit L. To see this in more detail, look first at the integ ...
... Look down the list of numbers. We claim that after a while the integer part and first k decimal places of the numbers on the list no longer change. Take these unchanging values to be the corresponding places of the decimal expansion of the limit L. To see this in more detail, look first at the integ ...
Mathematical proof

In mathematics, a proof is a deductive argument for a mathematical statement. In the argument, other previously established statements, such as theorems, can be used. In principle, a proof can be traced back to self-evident or assumed statements, known as axioms. Proofs are examples of deductive reasoning and are distinguished from inductive or empirical arguments; a proof must demonstrate that a statement is always true (occasionally by listing all possible cases and showing that it holds in each), rather than enumerate many confirmatory cases. An unproved proposition that is believed true is known as a conjecture.Proofs employ logic but usually include some amount of natural language which usually admits some ambiguity. In fact, the vast majority of proofs in written mathematics can be considered as applications of rigorous informal logic. Purely formal proofs, written in symbolic language instead of natural language, are considered in proof theory. The distinction between formal and informal proofs has led to much examination of current and historical mathematical practice, quasi-empiricism in mathematics, and so-called folk mathematics (in both senses of that term). The philosophy of mathematics is concerned with the role of language and logic in proofs, and mathematics as a language.