• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
Relevant Logic A Philosophical Examination of Inference Stephen Read February 21, 2012
Relevant Logic A Philosophical Examination of Inference Stephen Read February 21, 2012

... strange formal notions in its analysis of the intensional operators. Among various attempts to give these formal semantic notions some intuitive feel, two have come to be known as the American and Australian plans, the former proposing two new ’truth-values’, Both and Neither (that is, both and neit ...
CHAPTER 1. SENTENTIAL LOGIC 1. Introduction In sentential logic
CHAPTER 1. SENTENTIAL LOGIC 1. Introduction In sentential logic

... • If 7 is not odd then 2 is odd • If 7 is odd and 2 is odd then 2 is not prime • (7 is odd and 2 is odd) or 2 is prime We have improved on English in the last example by using parentheses to resolve an ambiguity. And, or, not, if . . . then (or implies) are called (sentential) connectives. Using the ...
CUED PhD and MPhil Thesis Classes
CUED PhD and MPhil Thesis Classes

Continuous first order logic and local stability
Continuous first order logic and local stability

... Yet, continuous first order logic has significant advantages over earlier formalisms for metric structures. To begin with, it is an immediate generalisation of classical first order logic, more natural and less technically involved than previous formalisms. More importantly, it allows us to beat the ab ...
Review - UT Computer Science
Review - UT Computer Science

... There are interesting first-order theories that are both consistent and complete with respect to particular interpretations of interest. One example is Presburger arithmetic, in which the universe is the natural numbers and there is a single function, plus, whose properties are axiomatized. There ar ...
A treatise on properly writing mathematical proofs.
A treatise on properly writing mathematical proofs.

Chapter 11: Other Logical Tools Syllogisms and Quantification
Chapter 11: Other Logical Tools Syllogisms and Quantification

The History of Categorical Logic
The History of Categorical Logic

... with higher-order logic and type theories. Both Lawvere and Tierney were aiming at an elementary, that is first-order, axiomatic presentation of what are now called Grothendieck toposes, a special type of categories introduced by Alexandre Grothendieck in the context of algebraic geometry and sheaf ...
1Propositional Logic - Princeton University Press
1Propositional Logic - Princeton University Press

... means without prior written permission of the publisher. ...
The substitutional theory of logical consequence
The substitutional theory of logical consequence

... from the model-theoretic definition of logical consequence, because the universal quantifier over interpretations in the definition ranges over all models in the technical sense; but the ‘intended interpretation’ is not one of these models and cannot easily be identified with one of these models. M ...
Ways Things Can`t Be
Ways Things Can`t Be

In terlea v ed
In terlea v ed

... programs on a single processor (see e.g. [2]). In a popular formal model concurrency is represented by interleaving . This means that parallel processes are never executed at precisely the same instant, but take turns in executing atomic transitions. When one of the participating processes executes ...
Contents 1 The Natural Numbers
Contents 1 The Natural Numbers

Deep Sequent Systems for Modal Logic
Deep Sequent Systems for Modal Logic

... classes: labelled formalisms, which incorporate Kripke semantics in the proof system, and unlabelled formalisms, which do not. Prominent examples of unlabelled formalisms are the hypersequent calculus [1] and the display calculus [2, 10]. These and more can be found in the survey by Wansing [11]. A ...
How to Express Self-Referential Probability and Avoid the
How to Express Self-Referential Probability and Avoid the

Modular Construction of Complete Coalgebraic Logics
Modular Construction of Complete Coalgebraic Logics

... property which ensures that combined logics have the Hennessy-Milner property w.r.t. behavioural equivalence, that is, the logical equivalence of states coincides with behavioural equivalence. Since this property is present in all of the basic constructs and is preserved by each combination of const ...
Polarizing Double-Negation Translations
Polarizing Double-Negation Translations

Finite Presentations of Infinite Structures: Automata and
Finite Presentations of Infinite Structures: Automata and

Homogeneous structures, ω-categoricity and amalgamation
Homogeneous structures, ω-categoricity and amalgamation

Scattered Sentences have Few Separable Randomizations
Scattered Sentences have Few Separable Randomizations

The Arithmetical Hierarchy Math 503
The Arithmetical Hierarchy Math 503

... sets according to some property, usually akin to complexity. A prototypical example is the cumulative hierarchy of set theory, which contains sets of ever-increasing size built up from smaller sets via the operations of power set and union. In recursion theory, the sets of immediate interest are tho ...
minimum models: reasoning and automation
minimum models: reasoning and automation

Studying Sequent Systems via Non-deterministic Multiple
Studying Sequent Systems via Non-deterministic Multiple

... the cut-free fragment of LK, and provided semantics for this fragment using (non-deterministic) three-valued valuations.† Together with better understanding of the semantic role of the cut rule, this three-valued semantics was applied for proving several generalizations of the cut-elimination theore ...
The Relative Efficiency of Propositional Proof
The Relative Efficiency of Propositional Proof

FC §1.1, §1.2 - Mypage at Indiana University
FC §1.1, §1.2 - Mypage at Indiana University

... mulas themselves. But it is the applications that bring the subject to life for most people. We will, of course, cover some applications as we go along. In a sense, though, the real applications of logic include much of computer science and of mathematics itself. Among the fundamental elements of th ...
< 1 ... 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 ... 72 >

Mathematical logic

Mathematical logic is a subfield of mathematics exploring the applications of formal logic to mathematics. It bears close connections to metamathematics, the foundations of mathematics, and theoretical computer science. The unifying themes in mathematical logic include the study of the expressive power of formal systems and the deductive power of formal proof systems.Mathematical logic is often divided into the fields of set theory, model theory, recursion theory, and proof theory. These areas share basic results on logic, particularly first-order logic, and definability. In computer science (particularly in the ACM Classification) mathematical logic encompasses additional topics not detailed in this article; see Logic in computer science for those.Since its inception, mathematical logic has both contributed to, and has been motivated by, the study of foundations of mathematics. This study began in the late 19th century with the development of axiomatic frameworks for geometry, arithmetic, and analysis. In the early 20th century it was shaped by David Hilbert's program to prove the consistency of foundational theories. Results of Kurt Gödel, Gerhard Gentzen, and others provided partial resolution to the program, and clarified the issues involved in proving consistency. Work in set theory showed that almost all ordinary mathematics can be formalized in terms of sets, although there are some theorems that cannot be proven in common axiom systems for set theory. Contemporary work in the foundations of mathematics often focuses on establishing which parts of mathematics can be formalized in particular formal systems (as in reverse mathematics) rather than trying to find theories in which all of mathematics can be developed.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report