• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
Comments on predicative logic
Comments on predicative logic

Size of nondeterministic and deterministic automata for certain
Size of nondeterministic and deterministic automata for certain

Note 2 - EECS: www-inst.eecs.berkeley.edu
Note 2 - EECS: www-inst.eecs.berkeley.edu

Full text
Full text

Weak Theories and Essential Incompleteness
Weak Theories and Essential Incompleteness

c dn> = loglog x + Bl + O(l/log x)
c dn> = loglog x + Bl + O(l/log x)

... If we start with (4-l) and reason as above, we might suppose v, - Var, v loglog x. This is quite wrong in view of Theorems 8 and 9. A Poisson distribution with parameter h concentrates its mass close to the mean A so that (4-2) is more relevant than (4-l). Let S be the set of square free numbers. Gi ...
pythagorean theorem applications2 and outline - Mrs-Cook
pythagorean theorem applications2 and outline - Mrs-Cook

Full text
Full text

The Surprise Examination Paradox and the Second Incompleteness
The Surprise Examination Paradox and the Second Incompleteness

Mathematical Reasoning (Part III)
Mathematical Reasoning (Part III)

The stronger mixing variables method
The stronger mixing variables method

ZENO`S PARADOX – THEOREM AND PROOF 1
ZENO`S PARADOX – THEOREM AND PROOF 1

Your Name Goes Here
Your Name Goes Here

Goldbach`s Conjecture
Goldbach`s Conjecture

... 2 Future Research Unfortunatly, this relationship does not prove Goldbach’s Conjecture, it only shows that any ‘disproofs’ will likely be isolated cases. Research is continuing towards the following: Theorem 4. There exists no n such that φC (n + m) ≥ π(n + m) for all m ∈ N. This appears to be true ...
CHAPTER 8 Hilbert Proof Systems, Formal Proofs, Deduction
CHAPTER 8 Hilbert Proof Systems, Formal Proofs, Deduction

... to denote that a formula A has a formal proof in H2 (from the set of logical axioms A1, A2, A3). We write Γ `H2 A to denote that a formula A has a formal proof in H2 from a set of formulas Γ (and the set of logical axioms A1, A2, A3). Observe that system H2 was obtained by adding axiom A3 to the sy ...
Pascal`s Triangle and Binomial Coefficients
Pascal`s Triangle and Binomial Coefficients

Propositional Logic Proof
Propositional Logic Proof

... By the end of this unit, you should be able to: – Explore the consequences of a set of propositional logic statements by application of equivalence and inference rules, especially in order to massage statements into a desired form. Note: in this learning goal, we are not asking you to memorize the i ...
paper by David Pierce
paper by David Pierce

Full text
Full text

Divide and Conquer Algorithms
Divide and Conquer Algorithms

... recurrence relation, we want to find a "closed form" of the function. In other words, we would like to eliminate recursion from the function definition.  There are several techniques for solving recurrence relations. The main techniques for us are the iteration method (also called expansion, or unf ...
Monadic Predicate Logic is Decidable
Monadic Predicate Logic is Decidable

... These 2 sequences of domain objects do not match: c1,..,cn = a,b,a d1,..,dn = a,b,c If a and c are similar then clause 1 is fulfilled, but clause 2 is not (because c1=c3 but d1<>d3) Reason behind clause 2: equality statements in FOPL (e.g. in the sentence AxEy -(x=y)) ...
.pdf
.pdf

Proofs - Stanford University
Proofs - Stanford University

1.6 Exploring the Pythagorean Theorem Notes
1.6 Exploring the Pythagorean Theorem Notes

Lecture2-1
Lecture2-1

< 1 ... 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 ... 170 >

Theorem



In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proven on the basis of previously established statements, such as other theorems—and generally accepted statements, such as axioms. The proof of a mathematical theorem is a logical argument for the theorem statement given in accord with the rules of a deductive system. The proof of a theorem is often interpreted as justification of the truth of the theorem statement. In light of the requirement that theorems be proved, the concept of a theorem is fundamentally deductive, in contrast to the notion of a scientific theory, which is empirical.Many mathematical theorems are conditional statements. In this case, the proof deduces the conclusion from conditions called hypotheses or premises. In light of the interpretation of proof as justification of truth, the conclusion is often viewed as a necessary consequence of the hypotheses, namely, that the conclusion is true in case the hypotheses are true, without any further assumptions. However, the conditional could be interpreted differently in certain deductive systems, depending on the meanings assigned to the derivation rules and the conditional symbol.Although they can be written in a completely symbolic form, for example, within the propositional calculus, theorems are often expressed in a natural language such as English. The same is true of proofs, which are often expressed as logically organized and clearly worded informal arguments, intended to convince readers of the truth of the statement of the theorem beyond any doubt, and from which a formal symbolic proof can in principle be constructed. Such arguments are typically easier to check than purely symbolic ones—indeed, many mathematicians would express a preference for a proof that not only demonstrates the validity of a theorem, but also explains in some way why it is obviously true. In some cases, a picture alone may be sufficient to prove a theorem. Because theorems lie at the core of mathematics, they are also central to its aesthetics. Theorems are often described as being ""trivial"", or ""difficult"", or ""deep"", or even ""beautiful"". These subjective judgments vary not only from person to person, but also with time: for example, as a proof is simplified or better understood, a theorem that was once difficult may become trivial. On the other hand, a deep theorem may be simply stated, but its proof may involve surprising and subtle connections between disparate areas of mathematics. Fermat's Last Theorem is a particularly well-known example of such a theorem.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report