
Why Dembski`s Design Inference Doesn`t Work
... SP criterion – specification and small probability. But in fact, the triangle can be generated by chance. Given just the specification of the Sierpinski triangle, investigators could easily eliminate the chance explanation and conclude that it exhibits design because the chance process that generate ...
... SP criterion – specification and small probability. But in fact, the triangle can be generated by chance. Given just the specification of the Sierpinski triangle, investigators could easily eliminate the chance explanation and conclude that it exhibits design because the chance process that generate ...
Aalborg Universitet Channel Modelling of MU-MIMO Systems by Quaternionic Free Probability
... a direct path is less probable than the existence of an indirect path. With the scattered component having higher rank, but lower power, the question which of the two components is more important is non-trivial. Furthermore, it is expected that the interplay of both components is important to unders ...
... a direct path is less probable than the existence of an indirect path. With the scattered component having higher rank, but lower power, the question which of the two components is more important is non-trivial. Furthermore, it is expected that the interplay of both components is important to unders ...
Chapter 2: Discrete Random Variables
... were more likely. But without any statistical data, is there any way to test whether these are really the right probability numbers to use?" "In a situation like this, without data, we have to use subjective probabilities," Eastmann explained. "That means that we can only go to our best expert and a ...
... were more likely. But without any statistical data, is there any way to test whether these are really the right probability numbers to use?" "In a situation like this, without data, we have to use subjective probabilities," Eastmann explained. "That means that we can only go to our best expert and a ...
Cascading Failures: Extreme Properties of Large Blackouts in the Electric Grid
... The risk of a bad day has gone from $0.00 to more than $4,000. The risk of a very bad day, in which the factory produces 1000 or more defective units is only slightly smaller at about $3,900. The powerlaw probability function causes the bulk of the risk to be associated with the infrequent, but larg ...
... The risk of a bad day has gone from $0.00 to more than $4,000. The risk of a very bad day, in which the factory produces 1000 or more defective units is only slightly smaller at about $3,900. The powerlaw probability function causes the bulk of the risk to be associated with the infrequent, but larg ...
Picturing Probability: the poverty of Venn diagrams, the richness of
... just about any diagram which marks regions in a plane a ‘Venn diagram’. Others have written that no diagram should be called a ‘Venn diagram’. Dunham (1994), for example, claims that the Venn diagram was produced a century before Venn by Euler and so “If justice is to be served, we should call this ...
... just about any diagram which marks regions in a plane a ‘Venn diagram’. Others have written that no diagram should be called a ‘Venn diagram’. Dunham (1994), for example, claims that the Venn diagram was produced a century before Venn by Euler and so “If justice is to be served, we should call this ...
Chapter 12: Probability and Statistics
... 27. OPEN ENDED Describe a situation in which you can use the Fundamental Counting Principle to show that there are 18 total possibilities. 28. REASONING Explain how choosing to buy a car or a pickup truck and then selecting the color of the vehicle could be dependent events. 29. CHALLENGE The member ...
... 27. OPEN ENDED Describe a situation in which you can use the Fundamental Counting Principle to show that there are 18 total possibilities. 28. REASONING Explain how choosing to buy a car or a pickup truck and then selecting the color of the vehicle could be dependent events. 29. CHALLENGE The member ...
Lecture 2 - Maths, NUS
... Kolmogorov’s Extension Theorem is much more general than what we need for the construction of product measures on a countable product of Borel spaces. First of all, the product space can be the product of an arbitrary collection of spaces (possibly uncountably many), as long as each is a Borel spac ...
... Kolmogorov’s Extension Theorem is much more general than what we need for the construction of product measures on a countable product of Borel spaces. First of all, the product space can be the product of an arbitrary collection of spaces (possibly uncountably many), as long as each is a Borel spac ...
Geometry Q3
... interpret the independence of A and B as saying that the conditional probability of A given B is the same as the probability of A, and the conditional probability of B given A is the same as the probability of B. (CCSS: S-CP.3) v. Recognize and explain the concepts of conditional probability and ind ...
... interpret the independence of A and B as saying that the conditional probability of A given B is the same as the probability of A, and the conditional probability of B given A is the same as the probability of B. (CCSS: S-CP.3) v. Recognize and explain the concepts of conditional probability and ind ...
The continuous probability density function
... which is less than 45 mm, as this is not the end point of any interval. However, if we had a mathematical formula to approximate the shape of the graph, then the formula could give us the answer to this important question. In the histogram, the midpoints at the top of each bar have been connected by ...
... which is less than 45 mm, as this is not the end point of any interval. However, if we had a mathematical formula to approximate the shape of the graph, then the formula could give us the answer to this important question. In the histogram, the midpoints at the top of each bar have been connected by ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.