• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
A. Proof of Lemma 3.1 B. Compression Bound
A. Proof of Lemma 3.1 B. Compression Bound

full text pdf
full text pdf

DOC - Berkeley Statistics
DOC - Berkeley Statistics

A multi-party protocol for constructing the public parameters
A multi-party protocol for constructing the public parameters

M13/01
M13/01

... most general that is consistent with principles of causality and covariance ...
Design Argument - University of Mississippi
Design Argument - University of Mississippi

... replication of organisms via reproduction. For example, you may have heard the figures about how, if every fly-egg survived to become an adult fly, in a few weeks the whole Earth would be covered with flies. This would happen because flies reproduce at a rate far greater than is necessary just to re ...
Discrete Probability Distribution
Discrete Probability Distribution

... equal. But suppose you toss the coin twice, how many heads can you expect to get? You will learn how to answer questions like these in this chapter. When you have a fair coin, most people think that if you toss it several times, say a 100 times, that you should roughly get heads or tails every other ...
Lesson 3 Chapter 2: Introduction to Probability
Lesson 3 Chapter 2: Introduction to Probability

Quality of service parameters and link operating point estimation
Quality of service parameters and link operating point estimation

Statistics 2 - University of London International Programmes
Statistics 2 - University of London International Programmes

... The University of London asserts copyright over all material in this subject guide except where otherwise indicated. All rights reserved. No part of this work may be reproduced in any form, or by any means, without permission in writing from the publisher. We make every effort to respect copyright. ...
Lecture Notes for Introductory Probability
Lecture Notes for Introductory Probability

Introduction to Probability: Problem Solutions
Introduction to Probability: Problem Solutions

Uncertainty 99 - Microsoft Research
Uncertainty 99 - Microsoft Research

214.7 (MH) - Duke Statistical
214.7 (MH) - Duke Statistical

S3.Hidden Markov Models-Additional notes for
S3.Hidden Markov Models-Additional notes for

Chapter 15 Probability - Huntington Union Free School District
Chapter 15 Probability - Huntington Union Free School District

... Experiments in Probability A single attempt at doing something, such as tossing a coin only once, is called a trial. We perform experiments in probability by repeating the same trial many times. Experiments are aimed at finding the probabilities to be assigned to the occurrences of an event, such as ...
STA 130 (Winter 2016): An Introduction to Statistical
STA 130 (Winter 2016): An Introduction to Statistical

Learning Objectives for Chapter 4
Learning Objectives for Chapter 4

STOCHASTIC PROCESSES 0. htrodwction. The universally
STOCHASTIC PROCESSES 0. htrodwction. The universally

ALG II/Unit 3(EX) v2.0
ALG II/Unit 3(EX) v2.0

... this key on your graph as well. ...
Lecture 10: Pseudorandom Generators (Sep 29, Karn Seth)
Lecture 10: Pseudorandom Generators (Sep 29, Karn Seth)

A Categorical Basis for Conditional Probability
A Categorical Basis for Conditional Probability

Probability Distributions
Probability Distributions

... A prescription for the probability model of an experiment contains two basic ingredients: the sample space and the assignment of probability to each elementary outcome. In Chapter 4, we encountered several examples where the elementary outcomes had only qualitative descriptions rather than numerical ...
Line-of-sight percolation
Line-of-sight percolation

... and we let ω → ∞. All asymptotic notation refers to this limit. Usually, in showing that the neighbourhood exploration process in some random graph is well approximated by a branching process, one first shows that a given vertex is unlikely to be in a short cycle. Here the latter statement is false: ...
A BOOLEAN ACTION OF C(M,U(1)) WITHOUT A
A BOOLEAN ACTION OF C(M,U(1)) WITHOUT A

< 1 ... 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 ... 305 >

Probability interpretations



The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report