
Introduction to the Practice of Statistics
... A student is chosen at random; what ist he probability that the student is male and not a binge drinker? But the question is What is the probability that a randomly selected male student is not a binge drinker? P(not binge drinker | male) = ...
... A student is chosen at random; what ist he probability that the student is male and not a binge drinker? But the question is What is the probability that a randomly selected male student is not a binge drinker? P(not binge drinker | male) = ...
Factorization of Discrete Probability Distributions
... in terms of a polynomial mapping from a set of parameters to distributions and analyze the algebraic properties of these models. Our analysis provides necessary and sufficient conditions for a discrete probability distribution to factor according to a n undirected graphical model, or a log-linear mo ...
... in terms of a polynomial mapping from a set of parameters to distributions and analyze the algebraic properties of these models. Our analysis provides necessary and sufficient conditions for a discrete probability distribution to factor according to a n undirected graphical model, or a log-linear mo ...
Uncertainty and probability for branching selves
... To make my case, I will need to refer to three prominent accounts of personal identity in branching situations. According to the first account, a person is a three-dimensional object that persists over time. There is one person prior to the branching event, and there are two persons after the branch ...
... To make my case, I will need to refer to three prominent accounts of personal identity in branching situations. According to the first account, a person is a three-dimensional object that persists over time. There is one person prior to the branching event, and there are two persons after the branch ...
P-Values and Formal Statistical Tests
... We have already seen one example of formal statistical testing when we tested for the normality of a sample from a univariate distribution. To reiterate, formal statistical testing begins with a statement of the null hypothesis, H0. The odd thing about the null hypothesis is that you will try to sho ...
... We have already seen one example of formal statistical testing when we tested for the normality of a sample from a univariate distribution. To reiterate, formal statistical testing begins with a statement of the null hypothesis, H0. The odd thing about the null hypothesis is that you will try to sho ...
Basic Business Statistics, 10th edition
... EXPLANATION: We do not know if they are collectively exhaustive. 10. If two equally likely events A and B are collectively exhaustive, what is the probability that event A occurs? a) 0. b) 0.50. c) 1.00. d) Cannot be determined from the information given. ANSWER: d TYPE: MC DIFFICULTY: moderate KEYW ...
... EXPLANATION: We do not know if they are collectively exhaustive. 10. If two equally likely events A and B are collectively exhaustive, what is the probability that event A occurs? a) 0. b) 0.50. c) 1.00. d) Cannot be determined from the information given. ANSWER: d TYPE: MC DIFFICULTY: moderate KEYW ...
Solutions - OCCC.edu
... So with 95% confidence we think that the true proportion of students who have taken calculus at OCCC is somewhere between 15.8% and 44.2% Question 5: The price of a particular brand of jeans has a mean of $37.99 (just assume 38) and a standard deviation of $7. A sample of 49 pairs of jeans is selec ...
... So with 95% confidence we think that the true proportion of students who have taken calculus at OCCC is somewhere between 15.8% and 44.2% Question 5: The price of a particular brand of jeans has a mean of $37.99 (just assume 38) and a standard deviation of $7. A sample of 49 pairs of jeans is selec ...
Introduction to Probability 2nd Edition Problem
... Thus, the observation of a white cow makes the hypothesis “all cows are white” more likely to be true. Solution to Problem 1.27. Since Bob tosses one more coin that Alice, it is impossible that they toss both the same number of heads and the same number of tails. So Bob tosses either more heads tha ...
... Thus, the observation of a white cow makes the hypothesis “all cows are white” more likely to be true. Solution to Problem 1.27. Since Bob tosses one more coin that Alice, it is impossible that they toss both the same number of heads and the same number of tails. So Bob tosses either more heads tha ...
Uncertainty and probability for branching selves
... To make my case, I will need to refer to three prominent accounts of personal identity in branching situations. According to the first account, a person is a three-dimensional object that persists over time. There is one person prior to the branching event, and there are two persons after the branch ...
... To make my case, I will need to refer to three prominent accounts of personal identity in branching situations. According to the first account, a person is a three-dimensional object that persists over time. There is one person prior to the branching event, and there are two persons after the branch ...
7th Grade Math Pacing - Houston County Schools
... 7.8 Understand that rewriting an expression in different forms in a problem context can shed light on the problem, and how the quantities in it are related. [7-EE2] 7.9 Solve multistep real-life and mathematical problems posed with positive and negative rational numbers in any form (whole numbers, f ...
... 7.8 Understand that rewriting an expression in different forms in a problem context can shed light on the problem, and how the quantities in it are related. [7-EE2] 7.9 Solve multistep real-life and mathematical problems posed with positive and negative rational numbers in any form (whole numbers, f ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.