Download Abstract

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Persephone wikipedia , lookup

The God Beneath the Sea wikipedia , lookup

Greek underworld wikipedia , lookup

Hades wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
The Tablet-Writing Mind of Hades: A Third Model of Justice in the Eumenides
The movement from bloody vendetta to Athena’s establishment of a human law
court does not exhaust the possibilities of formal justice in the Eumenides. For, in a
widely neglected passage, the Furies refer to a different assessor and punisher of every
mortal, Hades (μέγας γὰρ Ἅιδης ἐστὶν εὔθυνος βροτῶν, Eu. 267-75). Unlike the Furies,
Hades is not assimilated to Athens at the end of the trilogy: his power remains valid
despite the foundation of a court system. Divine underworld judgment therefore presents
a parallel for and continuing challenge to the polis-based justice of the ending.
Influential scholarship dealing with justice in the Oresteia (e.g. Kitto 1961;
Lebeck 1971; Lloyd-Jones 1971; Euben 1982; Winnington-Ingram 1983; Goldhill 1984;
and Sommerstein 2010), though at times quite skeptical about whether the ending affords
closure, rests on the premise that the trilogy dramatizes only two notions of justice. This
paper shows that the third paradigm of justice, that of Hades, questions the values
underlying the Eumenides’ Athenocentric law court.
The first part of this paper briefly contextualizes Aeschylus’s description of
afterlife judgment within literary mythology, such as the Homeric underworld
(specifically Minos as judge and the punishments described in Odyssey 11.568ff.) and
Pindar (Olympian 2 and fragments 129, 130). It also distinguishes such an afterlife
judgment from the improved human destiny offered by contemporary mystery cults
(Eleusinian, Bacchic, Pythagorean, and Orphic). The Eumenides actually heightens
anxiety over an individual’s fate in the afterlife and focuses the notion of judgment on the
implacable, divine character of Hades. This, in turn, sharply contrasts with Athena’s
newly invented system, which begins with an acquittal and grants power over punishment
to humanity.
The second part of the paper differentiates Hades from the Furies. Though both
act as witness, judge, and punisher, the Furies are liminal beings—they are chthonic and
yet act in the world, unlike Hades—and can be goaded (Eu. 155-61, 842). These
characteristics make the Furies accessible, thus subject to Athena’s peitho, persuasion
(Eu. 885-7, 970-2), which leads to their integration into Athens and their promotion of
polis values. Hades remains unapproachable, uncompromising, and unassimilated.
The last and main section of the paper uses Hades’ judgment to question the
trilogy’s celebration of Athenian law. Several scholars have seen representations of
aristocracy, tyranny, or even Zeus’s kingship as an integral part of the challenge which
tragedy (among other Athenian political texts) offers to the radical democracy of the time
(e.g. Griffith 1995; Ober 1998; Morgan 2003; and Carter 2007). The power of humans
over each other at the end of the trilogy has its menacing aspect: the Furies explicitly tie
their violence to instilling a righteous fear in mortals (Eu. 517-25), a stance that Athena
reaffirms as she transfers power over judgment and violence to the Areopagus council
(Eu. 697-706, calling it sharp to anger, ὀξύθυμον). The new court is founded by and tries
its first case directly under Athena, but it continues as a human institution, referring
forward to the contemporary justice system of Athens. In contrast to the procedures of
human magistrates, Hades, in his divine oversight and recording of all the acts of men
(Eu. 273-5) seems to have no need for oaths, witnesses, or arguments, all of which are so
problematic in both the Eumenides and judicial reality. Though Hades governs
relationships (human-divine, guest-host, child-parent, Eu. 270-1) he engages in none,
offering an absolute tribunal, free from personal sway or state concerns and explicitly
focused on the individual. In these ways his is an anti-political model of judgment. The
representation of Hades as judge of actions that are independent of a civic framework
contests the claim of the collective, persuadable polis to be the only determiner of justice.
Hades is the single outside force left at the end of the trilogy that continues to challenge
the justifications—even in a legal, civic context—for humanity’s use of violence.
Carter, D. M. 2007. The Politics of Greek Tragedy. Exeter.
Euben, J. Peter. 1982. "Justice and the Oresteia." The American Political Science Review
76 (1): 22-33.
Goldhill, Simon. 1984. Language, Sexuality, Narrative, the Oresteia. Cambridge.
Griffith, Mark. 1995. "Brilliant Dynasts: Power and Politics in the Oresteia." Classical
Antiquity 14 (1): 62-129.
Kitto, H. D. F. 1961. Greek Tragedy: A Literary Study. 3rd ed. London.
Lebeck, Anne. 1971. The Oresteia: A Study in Language and Structure. Washington.
Lloyd-Jones, Hugh. 1971. The Justice of Zeus. Berkeley.
Morgan, Kathryn A. 2003. Popular Tyranny: Sovereignty and Its Discontents in Ancient
Greece. Austin.
Ober, Josiah. 1998. Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of
Popular Rule. Princeton, N.J.
Sommerstein, A. H. 2010. Aeschylean Tragedy. 2nd rev. ed. London.
Winnington-Ingram, R. P. 1983. Studies in Aeschylus. Cambridge.