Download Semiotic freedom - Jesper Hoffmeyer`s Website

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Natural selection wikipedia , lookup

Sociobiology wikipedia , lookup

Evolution of metal ions in biological systems wikipedia , lookup

Hologenome theory of evolution wikipedia , lookup

Theistic evolution wikipedia , lookup

Adaptation wikipedia , lookup

Evolution wikipedia , lookup

Saltation (biology) wikipedia , lookup

Genetics and the Origin of Species wikipedia , lookup

Incomplete Nature wikipedia , lookup

Koinophilia wikipedia , lookup

Microbial cooperation wikipedia , lookup

Introduction to evolution wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
JESPER HOFFMEYER
Copenhagen University
10
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
The term “information” has become nearly omnipresent in
modern biology (and medicine). One would probably not exaggerate if
the famous saying of evolutionary biologist Theodosius Dobhzhansky,
that “nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution”
should nowadays be reframed as “nothing in biology makes sense
except in the light of information.” But are those two concepts, evolution and information, somehow internally related? And if so, how?
10.1 INFORMATION IN EVOLUTION
In textbooks, newspapers, and even scientific papers, the meanings
of the terms “evolution” and “information” are generally supposed
to be well known, and they are rarely explained. And yet, there is
no general consensus in science, or even in biology, about what they
really mean. For instance, the preferred exemplar (in the Kuhnian
sense) of evolution by natural selection is that of industrial melanism. In woodlands, where industrial pollution has killed the lichens
and exposed the dark brown tree trunks, dark forms of the peppered
moth – melanics – are supposedly better camouflaged against predation from birds than are the light gray forms that predominated before
the Industrial Revolution. The observation by 1950 that darker forms
had largely displaced lighter forms was thus taken as evidence for natural selection in action. This exemplar does indeed illustrate the effect
of natural selection, but whether it shows evolution depends on your
idea of evolution. Thus, if by the term “evolution” is meant something
like “the origin of species,” then it is remarkable that no speciation
has actually taken place here, and it is not obvious that any speciation would indeed occur in a case like this. So, populations do indeed
change as a result of natural selection, but is this mechanism also
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 155
155
4/26/2010 4:11:51 PM
156
Jesper Hoffmeyer
DNA
(
)
RNA
Protein
Fig. 10.1 According to the “central dogma,” the information flow in a
cell is one-way. Information is passed from DNA to RNA and further to
protein, but never in the reverse direction.
behind speciation and evolution at large? The majority of biologists
certainly feel assured that macroevolution – that is, evolution above
the level of species – is in fact the tardy result of an infinitely ongoing
microevolution (adaptation in populations), but there remains serious
disagreement on this (Depew and Weber, 1995; Gould, 2002).
Likewise, the meaning of the term “information” is loaded with
ambiguities. Whereas theorists may eradicate such ambiguities by
rigorous definition, it is often less than clear how well-defined concepts of information relate to the actual use of information as an
explanatory tool in biology. When talking about information, most
biologists probably have in mind the kind of information expressed in
the so-called “central dogma,” as stated by Francis Crick in the following terms: “Once information has passed into protein it cannot get out
again”; that is, the flow of information in the cell is unidirectional; it
originates in the gene and ends up as protein (see Figure 10.1).
Writers of textbooks are anxious to point out that the kind of
information we are talking about here is “sequential information,”
which is “replicated” when the cell divides, is “transcribed” into
mRNA, and is “expressed” by genes. Following transcription to mRNA,
the information is said to be “processed” or “edited,” whereupon
it “migrates” from the nucleus to the cytoplasm, where it is finally
“read” by a ribosome that “translates” it into protein. However, as was
shown by Sahorta Sarkar, nothing really goes on here that could not
be expressed by decent biochemical processes exhibiting traditional
efficient causality (Sarkar, 1996). So, why do molecular biologists prefer to talk about “information”?
There can, certainly, be no doubt about the heuristic value of
the information metaphor; something is added to our understanding when we talk about information rather than just about chemistry. In fact, without the information metaphor, it would be hard
to understand modern biochemistry at all.1 But whatever this added
1
One promising candidate for an information concept that is both rigorous and
biologically useful has been developed in ecology as the so-called “average mutual
information,” a measure for how well organized or determinate a configuration
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 156
4/26/2010 4:11:52 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
157
understanding consists of, it is not part of the cellular reality according to molecular biologists. At the cellular level chemistry exhausts
what goes on. The reason for this insistence on the reducibility of
information to chemistry, I shall suggest, is that the heuristic value
of the information concept is connected to the role that history (evolution) plays in the life of cells and organisms. What happens is that
“history talks,” but history is not considered part of biochemistry or
molecular biology. As shown by Terrence Deacon, in Chapter 8 of
this volume, the contextual (historical) aspect of information is due
ultimately to the fact that informative signals are necessarily caused
by externally derived perturbations of some medium away from its
expected state. The receipt of an informative signal ipso facto provides
evidence of the material influence of something other than the signal
itself, linking its resultant form to this “absent cause”: the immediate or mediating object of reference. Although history is, of course,
not “doing” anything, and most certainly does not “talk”, the present
form of the informative substrate – for example, the actual sequence
of nucleotides in a section of the DNA string – does nevertheless refer
to absent causes: that is, causes that are connected to the evolutionary
past of the species. This referential aspect of information furthermore
provides for the inherent intentionality of biological information to
the extent that it reflects the workings of natural selection. As Deacon
would put it, genetic and phenotypic representations with the least
correlation with environmental regularities will not be transmitted
(reproduced).
The (subconscious?) effect of the apparently unavoidable “information talk” in molecular biology may thus be to smuggle in the
intentional (semiotic) aspect of information by the back door, so to say.
At the surface, genetic information is treated as if it was just a simple
causal factor, but its deep appeal to our understanding derives from
its hidden connotation of an otherwise tabooed intentionality. The
exclusion of history may be relatively innocent at the level of molecular biology itself, but when molecular biology is understood as the
basis for genetics and evolution, this ahistorical understanding serves
to reify processes that are in fact embedded in contextual constraints
that should be accounted for in our theories. Genes are supposed to
specify particular traits or characters such as missing eyes in a fruit fly
of ecological relationships appears. Theoretical ecologist Robert Ulanowicz has
developed this concept further to a concept of ascendency that represents: “the
coherent power a system could bring to bear in ordering itself and the world
around it” (Ulanowicz, 2009).
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 157
4/26/2010 4:11:52 PM
158
Jesper Hoffmeyer
or Huntington’s chorea in human beings. So the question is, what does
it mean that genes are carrying information about such properties?
The identification of genetic information with “sequential information,” however, reinforces and is reinforced by the belief in genocentric versions of Darwinism. If information is nothing but a molecular
property of DNA, it may be replicated and transported down through
generations in well-defined and unambiguous units open to modification by the combined processes of mutation and selection. Natural
selection will then gradually optimize the set of instructional units
carried in the gene pool of a population. What is pushed aside in this
simplified view of gene function once again is the burden of context.
The concrete functioning of genes is dependent not only on the genetic
background on which they happen to be placed but also on a host of
circumstances normally described collectively as the milieu (Griffiths
and Gray, 1994; Gray, Griffiths, and Oyama, 2001). The conception of
genes as unambiguous or autonomous functional units does not even
come true in those monogenetic diseases that originally served as
models for our ideas of gene function. Thus, the monogenetic disease
PKU has now been shown to exhibit quite unexpected phenotypic variation (Scriver and Waters, 1999). Not all untreated carriers of the “disease gene” exhibit disturbed cognitive development, probably because
the build-up of toxic concentration of the amino acid phenylalanine in
the brain is influenced by unknown factors. Genetic information does
not simply “cause” things to happen.
Needless to say, proponents of the “intelligent design” movement use this kind of criticism to attack the legitimacy of evolutionary theory. And Darwinists, on their side, respond with deep suspicion
towards any criticism of the general scheme of evolutionary theory. A
third possibility exists though, and this is the possibility I am going to
present and discuss in the remaining part of this chapter: namely, the
approach called biosemiotics.
1 0 .2 S E M I O S I S A N D L I F E
Biosemiotics suggests that living systems should be studied as
semiotic2 systems in their own right. This idea is based on the belief that
the poverty of the information discourse in biological sciences results
from the reductive neglect of the interpretative aspect of biological
information. By introducing the concept of the sign, as developed by
2
Semiosis = sign activity. Semiotics = the sciences studying sign activity.
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 158
4/26/2010 4:11:52 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
Sign
Object
Interpretant
Smoke
159
Fire
Fear
Fig. 10.2 Sign action. Left: a graphical illustration of Charles Sanders
Peirce’s conception of a sign as a triadic relation connecting the
primary sign to its object through the production of an interpretant.
Right: Smoke provokes the formation of an interpretant in the brain
of an animal causing it to flee. The animal is seized by alarm, and this
being “seized by alarm” is the interpretant. In this figure, the three
instances of the sign relation are connected by a tripod rather than by
a triangle in order to emphasize the internal logic of the sign relation,
which should never be confused with a mere summation of three
relations between corners in a triangle.
US chemist and philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) as a
substitute for information, it will be assured that the interpretative
side of information is not neglected. In everyday parlance, a sign is
simply “something that refers to something else,” like smoke refers
to a fire. This reference, however, cannot be brought about without a
process of interpretation. Thus, a baby will not know that smoke signifies fire. A deer, on the other hand, will perhaps not know that smoke
refers to fire, but it definitely takes smoke as a sign of danger. And
adult people, of course, usually turn their head in order to see where
the fire might be.3 An “interpretant” is constructed by brain processes
that mediate the connection between the sense impression of smoke
and the presumed existence of something burning. Thus, we get the
Peircean triadic sign concept, as given in Figure 10.2.
Signs, however, are not causes in the traditional sense of
(Aristotelian) efficient causality, for the effect of a sign is not compulsory but depends upon a process of interpretation, and the interpretation may well be – and probably most often is – “mistaken.” An
example of this is when a predator is lured away from a bird’s nest
because it misinterprets the clumsy behavior of the bird as a sign for
3
But indeed, inside a theater the smoke might just be faked. Semiotics, as Umberto
Eco once said, is the science of lying.
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 159
4/26/2010 4:11:52 PM
160
Jesper Hoffmeyer
an easy catch. The bird, however, just pretended to have a broken wing
and flew away the minute the predator had missed the nest. In this
semiotically interesting case, the bird profits from its “knowledge” of
the predator’s predictable habit of going for the easy catch. Whether
the bird’s “knowledge” in this case is phylogenetically (instinctually)
or ontogenetically (learned) rooted does not change the general logic
of the situation – what differs is only a question of the implied mechanism and the time span of the interpretative act. On the one hand, if
the bird’s behavior is instinctually based, it is the result of an evolutionary interpretation, and we are then talking of time spans of perhaps millions of years during which this particular habit developed in
the bird as an interpretative response to the predictable behavior of
predators. If, on the other hand, the behavior is based on learning, the
interpretative act is a product of brain processes not far from the brain
processes involved in our own human interpretative activity.
I said above that the heuristic value of the information concept
derives from the historical nature of living systems. Although nobody
in science denies that living creatures are the result of an evolutionary process, this process is normally not conceived as historical in
the usual sense of this term, because it is assumed to have obeyed
the deterministic rule of natural laws. The metaphysics of determinism, however, seem less and less supported by the findings of modern science. It cannot, of course, be excluded right away, but there no
longer seems to be a strong reason to adopt it. In Stuart Kauffman’s
book Investigations (2000), an important part of the analysis turns on
the question of the non-ergodicity of the universe, meaning that the
universe never had the time it would have needed should its present
state of affairs in any way be representative of its in-built possibilities.
The persistent movement of the universe into the “adjacent possible”
precludes it from ever reaching a state that depends on statistical likelihood. Instead, the universe is historical, for “history enters when the
space of the possible that might have been explored is larger, or vastly
larger, than what has actually occurred” (Kauffman, 2000, p. 152).
The historical nature of the world has profound consequences
for the study of life, because it confronts us with the problem of organization in a new way. If the complex forms of organization exhibited
by living systems – from the cell to the ecosystem – are not the inescapable result of predictable lawfulness, they must instead have emerged
through processes that are still in need of discovery. The principle of
natural selection, of course, greatly helps us in explaining the widespread adaptedness of biosystems, but we need an additional principle
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 160
4/26/2010 4:11:53 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
161
that would solve the fundamental question of the “aboutness” of
life, the never-ending chain of attempts by living systems to come
to terms with their conditions of life. As Stuart Kauffman and Philip
Clayton have formulated this: “it is a stunning fact that the universe
has given rise to entities that do, daily, modify the universe to their
own ends. We shall call this capacity agency” (Clayton and Kauffman,
2006, p. 504). This “agency” necessarily involves a kind of measuring
process, whereby the agent is enabled to modify its environment in a
selective way, furthering its own ends, and this measuring process is
the core of the striking “aboutness” that characterizes living systems.
“Aboutness,” thus, is not derivable from the principle of natural selection for the simple reason that it is required for natural selection to
operate in the first place.4 If organisms did not exhibit aboutness, if
they did not “take an interest” in the world around them (if they did
not “strive” – to use Darwin’s own term), there would be no “competition for survival” but only disorganized activity leading nowhere.
However, if natural selection is not responsible for this aboutness, what then is the basis of it? Kauffman and Clayton propose a
tentative five-part definition:
a minimal molecular autonomous agent: such a system should be able
to reproduce with heritable variation, should perform at least one
work cycle, should have boundaries such that it can be individuated
naturally, should engage in self-propagating work and constraint
construction, and should be able to choose between at least two
alternatives (Clayton and Kauffman, 2006)
Terence Deacon has suggested an even more simple system as a candidate for the prebiotic emergence of life and agency, a system that
he calls the “autocell” (Deacon and Sherman, 2008). Autocells are selfassembling molecular structures that derive their individuality from
a synergistic relationship between two kinds of self-organizing processes that reciprocally depend upon one another’s persistence. Such
autocells could have been an important stepping stone in the process
leading from the non-living to the living. However, as Deacon and
Sherman themselves point out, autocells are not yet full-blown living systems. They lack several features that are generally considered
criteria for being alive, such as the possession of the replicative molecules of RNA or DNA, and differential survival through replications.
Furthermore, autocells will not meet the set of criteria put forward
4
In the simplest case, the intentional dynamics of aboutness shows itself as
fertility.
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 161
4/26/2010 4:11:53 PM
162
Jesper Hoffmeyer
by Kauffman and Clayton. The autocell model, however, does demonstrate a possible unbroken continuity from thermodynamics to
evolvability.
The difficult problem to solve in any theory of the origin of
agency and life is how to unify two normally quite separate kinds of
dynamics: a dynamics of chemical interaction patterns and a dynamics
of signification or semiosis. This immediately places this question in
the contextual situation of the environment. The Kauffman–Clayton
criteria clearly do so, but they also presuppose a far more complex
beginning than Deacon’s autocell model. It remains to be seen if, or
how, these two approaches might be reconciled.
Biosemiotics, of course, immediately reminds us that “to ask
for the origin of life is to ask for the origin of the environment”
(Hoffmeyer, 1998). Living organisms are inscribed in their environments much like patterns woven into a carpet – the two cannot get
apart. From a semiotic point of view, the decisive step in the process
that led to the origin of life was the appearance in the world of a
new kind of asymmetry, an asymmetry between inside and outside. The
formation of a closed membrane around an autocatalytically closed
system of components (Kauffman, 1993) might have been an initial
step. Such a membrane would have created what is probably the most
essential and unique characteristic of life: the never-ending interest of
the insides into their outsides or, in other words, cellular aboutness. I
have suggested that this “interest” should be understood as a property
that ultimately was derived from the primordial membrane itself. A
closed membrane sheet necessarily has two distinct kinds of exteriors, the inside exterior and the outside exterior. For agency to appear,
such membranes must have managed not only to canalize a selective
flow of chemicals across themselves but also to subsume their interior system of components to help them resist the flow of perturbations from the outside exterior. Or, in other words, for the membranes
to persist, they would have to function as interfaces connecting their
inside worlds to the outside world. At some point in prebiotic development, a self-referential digital description (in RNA or DNA) of constitutive “cell” components was established. For a prebiotic system to
become a true living system, however, this self-referential description
of the system had to be integrated (for example through signal transduction) into the other-referential system of receptors at the surface
of the cell. Such a stable integration of a self-referential digitally coded system
into an other-referential analogically coded system may perhaps be seen as a definition of life (Hoffmeyer, 1998).
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 162
4/26/2010 4:11:53 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
163
10.3 SEMIOTIC FREEDOM
When a bacterial cell finds itself in a gradient of nutrients and swims
right instead of left, the cell is making a choice.5 The choice is of course
based on a complicated chemotactical machinery (comprising some
scores of different protein species), but a biochemical analysis of the
chemotactic system does not exhaust our need for understanding. We
also need to know why this apparatus was developed in the first place.
Biochemistry essentially helps us constructing an image of cellular life
as chains or webs of chemical reactions taking place inside a cell or an
organism. This of course is extremely useful in many contexts, but in
itself, it does not contain information about the structural logic that
has ruled the organization of this apparent mess of millions of chemical reactions taking place in a cell. As Nobel laureate and biochemist
Alfred Gilman once told Scientific American:
I could draw you a map of all the tens of thousands of components in
a single-celled organism and put all the proper arrows connecting them
(and even then) I or anybody else would look at that map and have
absolutely no ability whatsoever to predict anything. (Gibbs,
2001, p. 53)
The key to cellular or organismic organization must be searched for
in the historical (evolutionary) constraints on the interaction of simple biosystems with each other and with their environments. In the
semiotic understanding outlined above, the chemotactic machinery
serves to integrate the sensing of the outer world to the reality of the
inner world as this reality is described in the self-referential, or genetic, system. Natural selection, of course, has modulated this system
all the way down from the first cells on Earth; and for all we know,
the system is very well safeguarded. The possibility remains, however,
5
Again I am here using teleological language. The idea is not, of course, that the
bacterium makes a conscious choice, but only that it systematically favors a distinct response out of several equally possible behaviors. If it is objected that this
“preference” is not a real “preference” or “choice” because the bacterium could
not possibly have failed to respond the way it did, I will contend that: (1) considered as an evolving species the bacterium does in fact have a choice in the
sense that it might have evolved differently; and (2) even single bacterial cells are
complex systems that exhibit truly unpredictable (chaotic) behavior and, in fact,
mutant cells might behave differently in the same situation. It should be noticed
here that the idea of an original “wild-type” bacterium has now been given up: all
bacterial cells are thus “mutants” or “normal,” depending on how the context
is defined.
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 163
4/26/2010 4:11:54 PM
164
Jesper Hoffmeyer
that mutations will spoil or change it and, more importantly perhaps,
that external factors may fool it. Researchers may, for instance, easily
fool the bacterial chemotactic system by adding nutrient analogs (such
as artificial sweeteners in stead of glucose) to the medium; and most
likely nature itself will from time to time “invent” comparable kinds
of dupe.
In such cases, it seems appropriate to say that the cell misinterprets the chemical signs of its environment. Such misinterpretations
are dangerous, and natural selection will favor any solution that helps
the organism to better interpret the situations it meets. Indeed, selection would be expected to favor the evolution of more sophisticated
forms of “semiotic freedom” in the sense of an increased capacity for
responding to a variety of signs through the formation of (locally)
“meaningful” interpretants. Semiotic freedom (or interpretance) allows
a system to “read” many sorts of “cues” in the surroundings, and this
would normally have beneficial effects on fitness. Thus, from the modest beginnings we saw in chemotactic bacteria the semiotic freedom
of organic systems would have tended to increase, and although it has
not been easy to prove that any systematic increase in complexity, as
this concept has traditionally been defined, has in fact accompanied
the evolutionary process, it is quite obvious that semiotic complexity
or freedom has indeed attained higher levels in later stages, advanced
species of birds and mammals in general being semiotically much
more sophisticated than less advanced species (Hoffmeyer, 1996).
Allowing for semiotic freedom in the organic world significantly
changes the task of explaining emergent evolution, because semiotic
freedom has a self-amplifying dynamic. Communicative patterns in
assemblies of cells or individuals may often have first appeared as a
simple result of the trial-and-error process of normal interaction, and
may then endure for considerable periods of time. If such patterns
are advantageous to the populations (cells or organisms), they may
eventually become scaffolded by later mutational events. Through this
“semi-Baldwinian” mechanism, the evolutionary process will enter a
formerly forbidden area of goal-directedness (Hoffmeyer, 2003).
Biosemiotics presents a strong argument for an emergentist view
of life. By semiotic emergence, I mean the establishment of macroentities or higher-level patterns through a situated exchange of signs
between sub-components. The important point here is that whereas
the emergence of higher-level patterns may seem to be slightly mysterious (often raising suspicion of vitalism), as long as only physical
interactions between entities are considered, the same outcome
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 164
4/26/2010 4:11:54 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
165
becomes quite understandable when based on semiotic interactions
among entities at the lower level. Most importantly, semiotic emergence
in this sense may stand as a possible alternative candidate to natural
selection as a mechanism for explaining the evolution of purposive
behavior.
The biosemiotic understanding also implies that semiosis cannot be used to mark off the human species from the rest of the world’s
creatures. Our species’ linguistic skills make us very different from
other species on Earth, indeed, but as shown in the work of Terrence
Deacon, the capacity for semiotic reference is not in itself the distinctive mark between humans and animals. What is distinctive is our
unmatched talent for that particular kind of semiotic activity that is
symbolic reference (Deacon, 1997), and thus languaging. We share the
semiotic capacity as such (that is, the iconic and indexical referencing)
with all life forms, and biosemiotics thus puts us back into nature
in the same time as it reconstructs nature as a place for humans to
belong. Nature is much more like us than science – in its obedience
to the anthropocentric taboo – has allowed. Instead of the Cartesian
either-or thinking, biosemiotics institutes a more-or-less thinking.
John Deely has called the human being “the semiotic animal”
(Deely, 2007). Semiosis – sign action – takes place all over the life
sphere, but only humans know the difference between signs and things;
only humans are semiotic animals.
10.4 SEMIOTIC EMERGENCE AND DOWNWARD CAUSATION
A key question in discussions of emergence concerns the ontological
reality of causative influences upon lower-level entities exerted by the
macrostate of the system. The expression “downward causation” is
often used in this type of causal relationship in which a macrostate
acts upon the very microstates of which it consists (Campbell, 1974).
The term may be seen as an attempt to express parts of what used to
be called “final causation” without linking ourselves to the cultural
inheritance of Aristotelianism and all the baggage this implies. As
we shall see, semiotic emergence and downward causation are two
sides – or rather two aspects – of the same coin, which I would prefer
to call “semiotic causation”, bringing about effects through a process
of interpretation.
Deborah Gordon’s laborious and highly rewarding work with
ants of the species Pogonomyrmex barbatus (who live in a harsh zone
bordering the deserts between Arizona and New Mexico) is illustrative
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 165
4/26/2010 4:11:54 PM
166
Jesper Hoffmeyer
here. Gordon’s work revealed that the survival of colonies of this species are deeply dependent on the regulation of a sophisticated pattern
of semiotic interactions between individual ants, which then raises
the question of whether the ant colony deserves to be seen as a “superorganism.” (Gordon, 1995, 1999). Seen from a semiotic point of view,
a superorganism might be understood as an assembly of organisms
that collectively interacts with its environments in a way that depends
on a finely elaborated internal semiotic activity among the individual
organisms – a “proto-endosemiotics” (Hoffmeyer, 2008). Gordon found
that a particularly important element in the colony’s behavior and
growth process is what she calls “job allocation” – and she shows that
although this task does indeed rely on a quite schematic interaction
pattern between different groups of ants, an element of unpredictability persists:
An ant does not respond the same way every time to the same
stimulus; nor do colonies. Some events influence the probabilities that
certain ants will perform certain tasks, and this regularity leads to
predictable tendencies rather than perfectly deterministic outcomes
(Gordon, 1999, p. 139).
Gordon’s experiments in this area may be seen as a response to experiments performed by the founder of sociobiology, Edward O. Wilson,
that were claimed to show a full-blown determinism in the response
pattern of ants to chemical signals (for example oleic acid (Wilson,
1975)). Gordon’s experiments, on the contrary, showed that “just as
the same word can have different meanings in different situations . . .
so the same chemical cue can elicit different responses in different
social situations” (Gordon, 1999, p. 97). Physiological, social, and ecological processes are simultaneously at work, says Gordon, and none
of them are more basic than the others: “Living levels of organization is central to any study of social behavior. For humans and other
social animals, an individual’s behavior is always embedded in a social
world” (ibid., p. 96).
The semiotic competence of subunits, then – whether these
subunits are human individuals in a society, plants in an ecosystem,
cells in a multicellular organism, or ants in an ant colony – is the
medium through which the behavior and integrity of the higher-level
entity is produced and maintained. To the extent that such a system’s
endosemiotic relations perceive and utilize cues and signs that indicate
(are indices for) the state of the holistic unit and its “needs”, it seems
justified to talk about these processes as genuinely endosemiotic – and
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 166
4/26/2010 4:11:54 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
167
Endosemiotic processes
Downward causation
Semiotic emergence
Organ
(ant hill)
Cell
(Ants)
Fig. 10.3 The connection between semiotic emergence and
“downward causation.” Downward causation operates through
indexical sign relations; that is, the values of system parameters are
interpreted by lower-level agents as indexical signs. But this state of
affairs in itself presupposes the formation in the first place of a largescale pattern with a behavior that stabilizes the semiotic interaction
between parts (from Hoffmeyer, 2008).
consequently, the holistic system itself deserves to be ascribed a status
as an autonomous unit: a superorganism.
The evolutionary formation of this kind of autonomous macroentity is the quintessence of what is called “downward causation” as
defined above, and it is suggested that the connection between semiotic emergence and downward causation is taken as constitutive for
both phenomena, as shown in Figure 10.3.
The semiotic relations between subunits that collectively
account for the stability of the large-scale or holistic system (for
instance the ant hill, the multicellular organism, or perhaps the symbiotic system of bobtail squids and light-emitting Vibrio bacteria, see
below) must necessarily be geared to respond to changes in the environment in ways that do not threaten the integrity of the large-scale
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 167
4/26/2010 4:11:54 PM
168
Jesper Hoffmeyer
system. Sub-units, for their part, must receive messages telling them
how to uphold the macro-system, and the easiest way to do this is probably to distribute the needs of the macro-system via “indexical” signs.
An interesting example is the so-called “quorum sensing.”
Quorum sensing has become the designation for a kind of communicative activity in bacteria in which the density of bacteria present
is a causal factor. In short, quorum sensing is the result of a process
in which each single bacterium excretes a certain chemical compound such that the concentration of this compound in the medium
will reflect the number of bacteria per unit volume. Quorum sensing
occurs if the compound, after having reached a threshold concentration, binds to a regulatory protein in the cell and thereby initiates the
transcription of specific genes. An illustrative case of quorum sensing
occurs in a species of squid, Euprymna scolopes, which hunts small fish
by night on the coral reefs off the coast of Hawaii.6 Moonlight causes
the squid to cast a shadow that makes them an easy catch for predators. As a defense strategy, E. scolopes has evolved a sophisticated way
of emitting light that effectively “hides” its own shadow. “Counterillumination” is the name given to this kind of camouflage, and it is
only made possible by the squid’s symbiotic relationship with luminous bacteria called Vibrio fischeri that live in the mantel cavity of the
squid. Living on food provided by the digestive system of the squid,
the bacteria emit light of the exact same intensity and color as the
light reaching the squid from the Moon, and this prevents predators
from seeing the squid from below (McFall-Ngai and Ruby, 1998).
In the morning, the squid bury themselves in the sand and excrete
90–95% of the bacteria, which brings the density of the remaining bacteria well below the threshold level. The bacteria continue producing
the particular substance, N-acyl homoserine lactone, which triggers
the induction of light emission, but because the density of bacteria is
low the concentration of this substance remains too low to elicit any
induction of the involved lux genes. Apparently, the squid is in full
control of the bacterial growth rate by adjusting the supply of oxygen,
and at sunset the population of bacteria reaches the threshold level
once again. When night approaches, the squid makes sure that the
bacterial density in its mantel cavity (and thus the N-acyl homoserine
lactone concentration) is high enough for the bacteria to respond by
allowing for the transcription of lux operon genes – and thus for light
6
For a detailed account of the semiotics of this case, see Bruni (2007) and Hoffmeyer
(2008).
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 168
4/26/2010 4:11:55 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
169
emission – to start. The point I want to make here is that the semiotic emergence whereby this system was gradually established in the
course of evolution necessarily also demanded the invention of semiotic means for assuring the stability of the system, and these “semiotic
means” are precisely what we understand by “downward causation.”
And here I have only touched upon the surface of the complexities
of the communicative network operative in bringing this symbiotic
interaction between the squid and the bacterium to work.
Downward causation and semiotic emergence are thus two interwoven, but not identical, aspects of the same process. That this mechanism, based on indexical semiosis, is indeed coupled to the circadian
rhythms of the squid was confirmed by the finding that the squid has
means at its disposal to fine-tune light emission. It may, for instance,
change the wavelength of the emitted light by help of a “yellow filter,”
and it may weaken the intensity of light by opening a bag of “ink”
(Bruni, 2007). Presumably, the indexical sign process itself is too slow
in its effects to compensate for momentary variations in background
light (as occurs under cloudy conditions), and evolution therefore had
to provide the macro-system (the squid) with a number of “additional
screws” for fine-tuning.
10.5 BIOSEMIOTICS AND GOD
Contrary to the genocentric neo-Darwinian orthodoxy, the view of
animate nature as profuse with signs does not contradict the fact that
our Earth has supported the evolution of human conscious beings
with moral feelings. Biosemiotics may potentially account for the
appearance of such creatures through immanent natural processes.
The biosemiotic approach thereby overturns the need for, or legitimacy of, the argument for intelligent design. Biosemiotics does not
logically entail any stance on the presence or absence of a transcendental creator, but it may be seen as rescuing the scientific world view
from the need for admitting such a transcendental power, a need that
seems rather inescapable if one adheres to a traditional scientific perspective. As Deacon and Sherman have put it:
In the debate between science and fundamentalist religion that the
world’s citizens watch so attentively, the burden is on science to
demonstrate how purposive processes can emerge in the absence
of antecedent intelligence, carefully selected prior conditions, or
intrinsically teleological components (Deacon and Sherman, 2008,
pp. 59–76).
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 169
4/26/2010 4:11:55 PM
170
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Deacon and Sherman have made an impressive attempt at “tracking the emergence of the fledgling precursor to these intentional
relations,” but although their approach is perfectly naturalistic, its
emphasis on theories of complexity and semiotics unfortunately
brings it well outside the narrow space of accepted causative agencies
in mainstream scientific world view.
The present author remains agnostic towards the questions of
a transcendent or immanent deity, but notes that such agnosticism
would have been hard or impossible to maintain, had it not been
for the biosemiotic solution to the hard problems of natural intentionality. For in the classical scientific image of the world as ruled by
unbreakable natural laws, only a deity could possibly have created
such “unnatural” beings as you and me.
REFERENCES
Bruni, L. E. (2007). Cellular semiotics and signal transduction. In Cellular Semiotics
and Signal Transduction, ed. M. Barbieri. Dordrecht: Springer, 365–407.
Campbell, D. T. (1974). “Downward causation” in hierarchically organised biological systems. In Downward Causation, eds F. I. Ayala and T. Dobzhansky.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 179–186.
Clayton, P., and Kauffman, S. (2006). On emergence, agency, and organization.
Biology and Philosophy, 21: 501–521.
Deacon, T. (1997). The Symbolic Species. New York: Norton.
Deacon, T., and Sherman, J. (2008). The pattern which connects pleroma
to creatura: The autocell bridge from physics to life. In A Legacy for
Living Systems: Gregory Bateson as Precursor to Biosemiotics, ed. J. Hoffmeyer.
Dordrecht: Springer, 59–76.
Deely, J. (2007). Intentionality and Semiotics: A Story of Mutual Fecundation. Scranton,
PA: University of Scranton Press.
Depew, D. J., and Weber, B. H. (1995). Darwinism Evolving: Systems Dynamics and the
Genealogy of Natural Selection. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/The MIT Press.
Gibbs, W. (2001). Cybernetic cells. Scientific American, August, 285: 52–57.
Gordon, D. M. (1995). The development of organization in an ant colony.
American Scientist, 83: 50–57.
Gordon, D. (1999). Ants at Work. How an Insect Society is Organized. New York: The
Free Press.
Gould, S. J. (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, MA: The
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Gray, R., Griffiths, P., and Oyama, S. (2001). Cycles of Contingency. Developmental
Systems and Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Griffiths, P. E., and Gray, R. D. (1994). Developmental systems and evolutionary
explanation. Journal of Philosophy, XCI(6): 277–304.
Hoffmeyer, J. (1996). Signs of Meaning in the Universe. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
Hoffmeyer, J. (1998). Semiosis and biohistory: A reply. Semiotica 120
(3/4): 455–482.
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 170
4/26/2010 4:11:55 PM
Semiotic freedom: an emerging force
171
Hoffmeyer, J. (2003). Baldwin and biosemiotics: What intelligence is for. In
Evolution and Learning, eds B. Weber and D. J. Depew. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 253–272.
Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics. An Examination into the Signs of Life and the Life of
Signs. Scranton, PA: University of Scranton Press.
Kauffman, S. (1993). Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Kauffman, S. A. (2000). Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press.
McFall-Ngai, M. J., and Ruby, E. G. (1998). Sepiolids and vibrios: When first they
meet. BioScience, 48: 257–65.
Sarkar, S. (1996). Biological information: A skeptical look at some central
dogmas of molecular biology. In The Philosophy and History of Molecular Biology:
New Perspective, ed. S. Sarkar. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 187–231.
Scriver, C. R., and Waters, P. J. (1999). Monogenic traits are not simple. Trends in
Genetics, 15(7): 267–272.
Ulanowicz, R. E. (2009). A Third Window: Natural Foundations for Life.
Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press.
Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology. The New Synthesis. London: Belknap Press.
9780521762250c10_p155-171.indd 171
4/26/2010 4:11:56 PM