Download Rethinking Foreign Policy

Document related concepts

Political economy in anthropology wikipedia , lookup

State (polity) wikipedia , lookup

Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
ROUTLEDGE ADVANCES IN INTERNATIONAL
RELATIONS AND GLOBAL POLITICS
Rethinking Foreign Policy
Edited by
Fredrik Bynander and
Stefano Guzzini
Rethinking Foreign Policy
This edited volume is a tribute to, and a debate with, the scholarship of Walter
Carlsnaes and his contribution to the study of foreign policy in both its conceptualisation and application.
This book probes the theoretical boundaries of foreign policy analysis, and
questions orthodox understandings of the field. It examines the agency–structure
debate, the question of how human decision making affects the norms and institutions of international interactions (and vice versa), and analyses how the study
of foreign policy can be applied to the European Union as a supranational entity
devoid of traditional statehood. Contributors offer an in-�depth discussion on the
intricacies of studying foreign policy, and provide new perspectives on the
standing of the European Union (EU) as a foreign policy entity.
Rethinking Foreign Policy will be of interest to students and scholars of International Relations, Foreign Policy, Global Governance, EU Studies and the work
of Walter Carlsnaes.
Fredrik Bynander is Associate Professor at the Swedish National Defence
College in Stockholm, Sweden and was, until recently, Head of Unit at the Prime
Minister’s Office.
Stefano Guzzini is Senior Researcher at the Danish Institute for International
Studies in Copenhagen, Denmark, and Professor of Government at Uppsala
�University, Sweden.
Routledge advances in international relations and global
politics
╇╇ 1 Foreign Policy and Discourse
Analysis
France, Britain and Europe
Henrik Larsen
╇╇ 2 Agency, Structure and
International Politics
From ontology to empirical
enquiry
Gil Friedman and Harvey Starr
╇╇ 3 The Political Economy of
Regional Co-�operation in the
Middle East
Ali Carkoglu, Mine Eder and
Kemal Kirisci
╇╇ 4 Peace Maintenance
The evolution of international
political authority
Jarat Chopra
╇╇ 5 International Relations and
Historical Sociology
Breaking down boundaries
Stephen Hobden
╇╇ 8 Politics and Globalisation
Knowledge, ethics and agency
Martin Shaw
╇╇ 9 History and International
Relations
Thomas W. Smith
╇ 10 Idealism and Realism in
International Relations
Robert M. A. Crawford
╇ 11 National and International
Conflicts, 1945–1995
New empirical and theoretical
approaches
Frank Pfetsch and
Christoph Rohloff
╇ 12 Party Systems and Voter
Alignments Revisited
Edited by Lauri Karvonen and
Stein Kuhnle
╇╇ 6 Equivalence in Comparative
Politics
Edited by Jan W. van Deth
╇ 13 Ethics, Justice and
International Relations
Constructing an international
community
Peter Sutch
╇╇ 7 The Politics of Central Banks
Robert Elgie and
Helen Thompson
╇ 14 Capturing Globalization
Edited by James H. Mittelman
and Norani Othman
╇ 15 Uncertain Europe
Building a new European
security order?
Edited by Martin A. Smith and
Graham Timmins
╇ 16 Power, Postcolonialism and
International Relations
Reading race, gender and class
Edited by Geeta Chowdhry and
Sheila Nair
╇ 17 Constituting Human Rights
Global civil society and the
society of democratic states
Mervyn Frost
╇ 18 US Economic Statecraft for
Survival 1933–1991
Of sanctions, embargoes and
economic warfare
Alan P. Dobson
╇ 19 The EU and NATO
Enlargement
Richard McAllister and
Roland Dannreuther
╇ 20 Spatializing International
Politics
Analysing activism on the
internet
Jayne Rodgers
╇ 21 Ethnonationalism in the
Contemporary World
Walker Connor and the study of
nationalism
Edited by Daniele Conversi
╇ 22 Meaning and International
Relations
Edited by Peter Mandaville and
Andrew Williams
╇ 23 Political Loyalty and the
Nation-�State
Edited by Michael Waller and
Andrew Linklater
╇ 24 Russian Foreign Policy and the
CIS
Theories, debates and actions
Nicole J. Jackson
╇ 25 Asia and Europe
Development and different
dimensions of ASEM
Yeo Lay Hwee
╇ 26 Global Instability and Strategic
Crisis
Neville Brown
╇ 27 Africa in International Politics
External involvement on the
continent
Edited by Ian Taylor and
Paul Williams
╇ 28 Global Governmentality
Governing international spaces
Edited by Wendy Larner and
William Walters
╇ 29 Political Learning and
Citizenship Education Under
Conflict
The political socialization of
Israeli and Palestinian youngsters
Orit Ichilov
╇ 30 Gender and Civil Society
Transcending boundaries
Edited by Jude Howell and
Diane Mulligan
╇ 31 State Crises, Globalisation and
National Movements in
North-�East Africa
The Horn’s dilemma
Edited by Asafa Jalata
╇ 39 The International Criminal
Court
A global civil society
achievement
Marlies Glasius
╇ 32 Diplomacy and Developing
Nations
Post-�cold war foreign policy-�
making structures and processes
Edited by Justin Robertson and
Maurice A. East
╇ 40 A Human Security Doctrine for
Europe
Project, principles, practicalities
Edited by Marlies Glasius and
Mary Kaldor
╇ 33 Autonomy, Self-�governance
and Conflict Resolution
Innovative approaches to
institutional design in divided
societies
Edited by Marc Weller and
Stefan Wolff
╇ 34 Mediating International Crises
Jonathan Wilkenfeld,
Kathleen J. Young,
David M. Quinn and
Victor Asal
╇ 35 Postcolonial Politics, the
Internet and Everyday Life
Pacific traversals online
M. I. Franklin
╇ 36 Reconstituting the Global
Liberal Order
Legitimacy and regulation
Kanishka Jayasuriya
╇ 37 International Relations,
Security and Jeremy Bentham
Gunhild Hoogensen
╇ 38 Interregionalism and
International Relations
Edited by Heiner Hänggi,
Ralf Roloff and Jürgen Rüland
╇ 41 The History and Politics of
UN Security Council Reform
Dimitris Bourantonis
╇ 42 Russia and NATO Since 1991
From cold war through cold
peace to partnership?
Martin A. Smith
╇ 43 The Politics of Protection
Sites of insecurity and political
agency
Edited by Jef Huysmans,
Andrew Dobson and
Raia Prokhovnik
╇ 44 International Relations in
Europe
Traditions, perspectives and
destinations
Edited by Knud Erik Jørgensen
and Tonny Brems Knudsen
╇ 45 The Empire of Security and the
Safety of the People
Edited by William Bain
╇ 46 Globalization and Religious
Nationalism in India
The search for ontological
security
Catrina Kinnvall
╇ 47 Culture and International
Relations
Narratives, natives and tourists
Julie Reeves
╇ 55 Developing Countries and
Global Trade Negotiations
Edited by Larry Crump and
S. Javed Maswood
╇ 48 Global Civil Society
Contested futures
Edited by Gideon Baker and
David Chandler
╇ 56 Civil Society, Religion and
Global Governance
Paradigms of power and
persuasion
Edited by Helen James
╇ 49 Rethinking Ethical Foreign
Policy
Pitfalls, possibilities and
paradoxes
Edited by David Chandler and
Volker Heins
╇ 50 International Cooperation and
Arctic Governance
Regime effectiveness and
northern region building
Edited by Olav Schram Stokke
and Geir Hønneland
╇ 51 Human Security
Concepts and implications
Shahrbanou Tadjbakhsh and
Anuradha Chenoy
╇ 52 International Relations and
Security in the Digital Age
Edited by Johan Eriksson and
Giampiero Giacomello
╇ 53 State-�Building
Theory and practice
Edited by Aidan Hehir and
Neil Robinson
╇ 54 Violence and Non-�Violence in
Africa
Edited by Pal Ahluwalia,
Louise Bethlehem and
Ruth Ginio
╇ 57 War, Peace and Hegemony in a
Globalized World
The changing balance of power
in the 21st century
Edited by Chandra Chari
╇ 58 Eco nomic Globalisation as
Religious War
Tragic convergence
Michael McKinley
╇ 59 Globalization, Prostitution and
Sex-�trafficking
Corporeal politics
Elina Penttinen
╇ 60 Peacebuilding
Women in international
perspective
Elisabeth Porter
╇ 61 Ethics, Liberalism and Realism
in International Relations
Mark D. Gismondi
╇ 62 Law and Legalization in
Transnational Relations
Edited by Christian Brütsch and
Dirk Lehmkuhl
╇ 63 Fighting Terrorism and Drugs
Europe and international police
cooperation
Jörg Friedrichs
╇ 64 Identity Politics in the Age of
Genocide
The holocaust and historical
representation
David B. MacDonald
╇ 65 Globalisation, Public Opinion
and the State
Western Europe and East and
Southeast Asia
Edited by Takashi Inoguchi and
Ian Marsh
╇ 66 Urbicide
The politics of urban destruction
Martin Coward
╇ 67 Transnational Activism in the
UN and the EU
A comparative study
Jutta Joachim and Birgit Locher
╇ 68 Gender Inclusive
Essays on violence, men and
feminist international relations
Adam Jones
╇ 69 Capitalism, Democracy and the
Prevention of War and Poverty
Edited by Peter Graeff and
Guido Mehlkop
╇ 70 Environmental Change and
Foreign Policy
Theory and practice
Edited by Paul G. Harris
╇ 71 Climate Change and Foreign
Policy
Case studies from East to West
Edited by Paul G. Harris
╇ 72 Securitizations of Citizenship
Edited by Peter Nyers
╇ 73 The Power of Ideology
From the Roman Empire to
Al-�Qaeda
Alex Roberto Hybel
╇ 74 The Securitization of
Humanitarian Migration
Digging moats and sinking boats
Scott D. Watson
╇ 75 Mediation in the Asia-�Pacific
Region
Transforming conflicts and
building peace
Edited by Dale Bagshaw and
Elisabeth Porter
╇ 76 United Nations Reform
Heading North or South?
Spencer Zifcak
╇ 77 New Norms and Knowledge in
World Politics
Protecting people, intellectual
property and the environment
Preslava Stoeva
╇ 78 Power, Resistance and Conflict
in the Contemporary World
Social movements, networks and
hierarchies
Athina Karatzogianni and
Andrew Robinson
╇ 79 World-�Regional Social Policy
and Global Governance
New research and policy agendas
in Africa, Asia, Europe and Latin
America
Edited by Bob Deacon,
Maria Cristina Macovei,
Luk Van Langenhove and
Nicola Yeates
╇ 80 International Relations Theory
and Philosophy
Interpretive dialogues
Edited by Cerwyn Moore and
Chris Farrands
╇ 81 Superpower Rivalry and
Conflict
The long shadow of the Cold
War on the twenty-�first century
Edited by Chandra Chari
╇ 82 Coping and Conformity in
World Politics
Hugh C. Dyer
╇ 83 Defining and Defying
Organized Crime
Discourse, perception and reality
Edited by Felia Allum,
Francesca Longo, Daniela Irrera
and Panos A. Kostakos
╇ 88 Human Security, Law and the
Prevention of Terrorism
Andrej Zwitter
╇ 89 Multilayered Migration
Governance
The promise of partnership
Edited by Rahel Kunz,
Sandra Lavenex and
Marion Panizzon
╇ 90 Role Theory in International
Relations
Approaches and analyses
Edited by Sebastian Harnisch,
Cornelia Frank &
Hanns W. Maull
╇ 91 Issue Salience in International
Relations
Edited by Kai Oppermann and
Henrike Viehrig
╇ 84 Federalism in Asia
India, Pakistan and Malaysia
Harihar Bhattacharyya
╇ 92 Corporate Risk and National
Security Redefined
Karen Lund Petersen
╇ 85 The World Bank and HIV/
AIDS
Setting a global agenda
Sophie Harman
╇ 93 Interrogating Democracy in
World Politics
Edited by Joe Hoover,
Meera Sabaratnam and
Laust Schouenborg
╇ 86 The “War on Terror” and the
Growth of Executive Power?
A comparative analysis
Edited by John E. Owens and
Riccardo Pelizzo
╇ 87 The Contested Politics of
Mobility
Borderzones and irregularity
Edited by Vicki Squires
╇ 94 Globalizing Resistance against
War
Theories of resistance and the
new anti-�war movement
Tiina Seppälä
╇ 95 The Politics of Self-�
Determination
Beyond the decolonisation
process
Kristina Roepstorff
╇ 96 Sovereignty and the
Responsibility to Protect
The power of norms and the
norms of the powerful
Theresa Reinold
╇ 99 Genocide, Ethnonationalism,
and the United Nations
Exploring the causes of mass
killing since 1945
Hannibal Travis
╇ 97 Anglo-�American Relations
Contemporary perspectives
Edited by Alan P. Dobson and
Steve Marsh
100 Caribbean Sovereignty,
Development and Democracy
in an Age of Globalization
Edited by Linden Lewis
╇ 98 The Emerging Politics of
Antarctica
Edited by Anne-�Marie Brady
101 Rethinking Foreign Policy
Edited by Fredrik Bynander and
Stefano Guzzini
Rethinking Foreign Policy
Edited by Fredrik Bynander and
Stefano Guzzini
First published 2013
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business.
© 2013 Fredrik Bynander and Stefano Guzzini for selection and editorial
matter; individual contributors for their contribution.
The right of Fredrik Bynander and Stefano Guzzini to be identified as the
authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual
chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Rethinking foreign policy / [edited by] Fredrik Bynander, Stefano Guzzini.
p. cm. – (Routledge advances in international relations and global
politics)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. European Union countries–Foreign relations. 2. Europe–Foreign
relations–1989– 3. Carlsnaes, Walter. I. Bynander, Fredrik.
II. Guzzini, Stefano.
D2010.R48 2013
341.242'2–dc23
2012026854
ISBN: 978-0-415-63343-7 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-0-203-07362-9 (ebk)
Typeset in Times New Roman
by Wearset Ltd, Boldon, Tyne and Wear
Contents
Contributors
General preface
xiii
xvii
F r e dri k B y n a nd e r a nd S t e f a no G u z z ini
Abbreviations
Part I
xxii
Walter Carlsnaesâ•›.â•›.â•›.
1
╇ 1 In the beginning was conceptualisation
3
S t e f a no G u z z ini
╇ 2 Coming to terms with the ‘Other’: towards IR going global
15
A . J . R . G room
Part II
The agency–structure problemâ•›.â•›.â•›.
29
╇ 3 Agency, structure, international relations and foreign policy
31
C o l in W ig h t
╇ 4 Agency, structures and time: from atemporal ontologies to
explicit geo-�historical hypotheses and anticipation of global
democracy
45
H e i k k i P a tom ä k i
╇ 5 Theories, truisms and tools in international relations
59
K jell G oldmann
╇ 6 The ritual/performance problem in foreign policy analysis:
European diplomats at the Chinese court
Eri k R ingm a r
68
xii╇╇ Contents
╇ 7 Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices
81
M agnus E kengren
╇ 8 Agents, structures and international regime significance
95
C harles F . P arker
Part III
.â•›.â•›.â•›and the study of foreign policy
107
9
109
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?
Kn u d Eri k J ø rg e ns e n
10 A foreign policy without a state? Accounting for the CFSP
123
H elene S jursen
11 EU foreign policy: ‘High politics’, low impact – and vice
versa?
137
J anne H aaland M atlary
12 The EU foreign and security policy: High expectations, low
capabilities?
150
P e rni l l e R i e k e r
13 Ideas in foreign policy decision making: The invasion of
Iraq
163
F r e dri k B y n a nd e r
14 Foreign policy analysis and the governance turn
176
T h om a s R iss e
15 Apostleship: A South African national role conception
186
D eon G eldenhuys
PART IV
Select publication list
Bibliography
203
205
W alter C arlsnaes
Index
207
Contributors
Fredrik Bynander had Walter Carlsnaes as supervisor for his doctoral dissertation, which he defended at Uppsala University in 2003. Since then he has
published on European security, crisis management and leadership succession
effects in journals such as Political Psychology, Public Administration and
Government & Opposition. Currently, Bynander divides his time between an
Associate Professorship at the Swedish National Defence College, where he
is the Research Director for CRISMART, and a position as special adviser at
the Swedish Prime Minister’s Office.
Stefano Guzzini is Senior Researcher at the Danish Institute for International
Studies, Copenhagen, and Professor at Uppsala University, Sweden. He previously held tenured or guest professor positions at the Central European University (Budapest), Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, Bremen International
Graduate School for Social Science, and Pontifícia Universidade Católica do
Rio de Janeiro (PUC-Rio). Recent and forthcoming publications include
�Foreign Policy Analysis, 5 vols. (Sage, 2011, co-edited with Walter Carlsnaes), The Diffusion of Power in Global Governance: International Political
Economy meets Foucault (Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, co-edited with Iver
Neumann), The Return of Geopolitics in Europe? Social Mechanisms and
Foreign Policy Identity Crises (Cambridge University Press, 2013), and
Power, Realism and Constructivism (Routledge, 2013).
Magnus Ekengren is Associate Professor, Director of the Programme for European Security Research and Co-�director of the international research programme Building Societal Security in Europe at the Swedish National
Defence College. He is a former Swedish diplomat and was previously
Deputy Director at the Policy Planning Unit of the Swedish Ministry for Foreign Affairs. He has served at the Political and the European Union Department of the Ministry and handled issues related to EU enlargement and
institutional reform and the Common Foreign and Security Policy. Ekengren
has worked at the European Commission and been posted at the Swedish representation to the Council of Europe, Strasbourg. He has been Visiting Professor at the Munk School of Global Affairs, University of Toronto. His
recent publications include an article on transboundary threats and new forms
xiv╇╇ Contributors
of EU security co-�operation (European Security) and the book The Time of
European Governance (Manchester University Press, 2002). His latest books
are called The Politics of Security Sector Reform – Challenges and Opportunities for the EU’s Global Role (Ashgate, 2011) and The EU as Crisis Manager – Patterns and Prospects (Cambridge University Press, 2013).
Deon Geldenhuys is Professor of Politics at the University of Johannesburg,
South Africa. Focusing on international relations, he has published several
books dealing with non-�conformist state behaviour.
Kjell Goldmann has been Professor of Political Science at Stockholm University since 1978 and is now emeritus. He was Dean of the Faculty of Social
Sciences 1986–1996. Visiting appointments include those at Harvard University, Princeton University, Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin, Hebrew University
of Jerusalem, University of British Columbia and McGill University. He is a
Member of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences and the Royal Swedish
Academy of War Sciences. He is the author of the main chapter on Inter�
national Relations in A New Handbook of Political Science (1996). Among
his books in English are The Logic of Internationalism (Routledge, 1994),
Transforming the European Nation-State: Dynamics of Internationalization
(Sage, 2001), and Nationalism and Internationalism in the Post-Cold War
Era (Routledge, 2000, co-edited with Ulf Hannerz and Charles Westin).
A.J.R. Groom is Emeritus Professor of International Relations at the University
of Kent. He teaches regular courses at Kent, Canterbury Christ Church University, Sciences-Â�Po Paris, Université Libre de Bruxelles and the Diplomatische Akademie Wien. He has published 16 volumes and over 160 articles
and chapters in the fields of IR theory, Conflict and Strategic Studies, International Organisation and European International Relations as well as founding
two journals – the European Journal of International Relations and Global
Society, the latter of which he has also been the Editor. He has been on the
ECPR Executive, Chairman of BISA, Vice President of ISA, Board member
of ACUNS, Chair of the Scientific Council of the Flemish Peace Institute as
well as Executive Secretary of WISC, and founder and Chairman of SGIR.
Knud Erik Jørgensen is Professor in the Department of Political Science at
Aarhus University. He has been a visiting fellow at Chatham House in
London, at the European University Institute in Florence and at the University
of Toronto. He is the former editor of the journal Cooperation and Conflict
and editor/co-�editor of Reflective Approaches to European Governance (Macmillan, 1997); European Approaches to Crisis Management (Kluwer, 1997);
The Social Construction of Europe (Sage, 2001, with Thomas Christiansen
and Antje Wiener); Constructing International Relations (ME Sharpe, 2001,
with Karin M. Fierke); International Relations in Europe. Traditions, Perspectives and Destinations (Routledge, 2006, with Tonny B. Knudsen);
Handbook of European Union Politics (Sage, 2007, with Mark Pollack and
Ben Rosamond); The European Union and International Organizations
Contributors╇╇ xv
(Routledge, 2009); and a new textbook, International Relations Theory: A
New Introduction (Palgrave, 2010).
Janne Haaland Matlary is Professor and Director of International Studies at
the Department of Political Science, University of Oslo, and at the Norwegian
Defence University College. Recent publications include European Union
Security Dynamics: In the New National Interest (Palgrave Macmillan, 2009,
forthcoming paperback 2013), NATO: The Power of Partnerships (Palgrave
Macmillan, 2011, editor and author), and NATO’s European Allies: Military
Capacity and Political Will (Palgrave Macmillan, forthcoming January 2013,
editor and author).
Charles F. Parker is Associate Professor of Political Science at the Department
of Government, Uppsala University. His research has focused on international
and EU climate change politics, the impact of international institutions, international regime theory, and the origins and consequences of the warning–
response problem. His work has appeared in journals such as the Journal of
Common Market Studies, Political Psychology, Global Environmental Politics, Foreign Policy Analysis, Public Administration, Cooperation and Conflict and the Journal of Contingencies and Crisis Management.
Heikki Patomäki is a Professor of World Politics at the University of Helsinki,
Finland. His research interests include philosophy and methodology of social
sciences, peace research, global political economy, political theory of global
justice and democracy and global futures. Patomäki’s papers have appeared in
numerous journals and anthologies. His recent books include Democratising
Globalisation: The Leverage of the Tobin Tax (Zed Books, 2001), After International Relations: Critical Realism and the (Re)Construction of World Politics
(Routledge, 2002), A Possible World: Democratic Transformation of Global
Institutions (with Teivo Teivainen, Zed Books, 2004), The Political Economy
of Global Security: War, Future Crises and Changes in Global Governance
(Routledge, 2008), and The Great Eurozone Disaster: From Crisis to Global
New Deal (Zed Books, 2013).
Pernille Rieker is a Senior Researcher at the Norwegian Institute of International Affairs (NUPI). She holds a doctoral degree from the University of
Oslo (2004). Her dissertation, The Europeanization of National Security Identity: The EU and the Changing Security Identities of the Nordic States, was
published by Routledge in 2006. Rieker has also published several articles
and book chapters about European, Nordic and French security policy.
Erik Ringmar is Zhi Yuan Chair Professor of International Relations at Shanghai Jiaotong University, Shanghai, China PRC. He graduated with a PhD in
political science from Yale University and for 12 years he taught courses in
comparative politics at the London School of Economics and Political Science. He is the author of five books and some 30 articles. He is a faculty
xvi╇╇ Contributors
fellow at the Center for Cultural Sociology, Yale University. His next book
will deal with boredom and war.
Thomas Risse is Professor of International Politics at the Otto Suhr Institute for
Political Science, Freie Universität Berlin. He co-Â�directs the Collaborative
Research Center ‘Governance in Areas of Limited Statehood’ at the Freie
Universität Berlin and the Research College ‘The Transformative Power of
Europe’, both funded by the German Research Foundation. He has taught at
the European University Institute, Florence, Italy, at the University of Konstanz, as well as Harvard, Stanford, Yale and Cornell Universities, and the
University of Wyoming. His most recent publications include A Community
of Europeans? Transnational Identities and Public Spheres (Cornell University Press, 2010), Governance without a State? Policies and Politics in Areas
of Limited Statehood (Columbia University Press, 2011) and Handbook of
International Relations, 2nd edition (co-edited with Walter Carlsnaes and
Beth Simmons: Sage, 2013).
Helene Sjursen is a Research Professor at ARENA – Centre for European Studies at the University of Oslo. Amongst her publications are ‘The EU as a
“normative” power: How can this be?’ Journal of European Public Policy
(2006); Enlargement and the Nature of the Euro-�polity (Routledge, 2006);
Contemporary European Foreign Policy (co-�edited with Walter Carlsnaes
and Brian White, Sage, 2004); ‘The EU’s Common Foreign and Security
Policy: The quest for democracy’ Journal of European Public Policy 18(8)
2011, guest editor.
Colin Wight is Professor of International Relations at the Department of Politics, University of Exeter and Editor in Chief of the European Journal of
International Relations. His research focuses on the relationships between
International Relations Theory, Social Theory, and the Philosophy of Social
Science. He has published in Millennium, International Studies Quarterly,
Political Studies, European Journal of International Relations, Review of
International Studies and Philosophy of the Social Sciences. His book,
Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology, was
published by Cambridge University Press in 2006. He is currently researching
the role played by the ‘idea’ of science in the development of political science
as an academic discipline.
General preface
Fredrik Bynander and Stefano Guzzini
This anthology on the study of foreign policy is inspired by the work of Walter
Carlsnaes, Professor of Government at Uppsala University and longstanding
contributor to core theoretical debates in international relations and foreign
policy analysis. The authors are colleagues and friends of Walter who did not
just gather for a traditional Festschrift in his honour, but wanted to make a more
coordinated contribution to the topics closest to his heart. In so doing, we either
engaged in a dialogue directly with his work or picked one of his favourite issues
for our analysis.
There are certainly aspects of his scholarship that perhaps made our endeavour difficult: its impressive theoretical scope and depth, its polemic qualities for
the debates that have been engaged, and the complexity of the issues broached.
Yet the clarity of argument and the acute sense of relevance that you get from
reading his work make it easy to interact with and the room for dialogue
considerable.
In conceiving this volume, we decided to focus on the core of Walter’s contribution, the study of foreign policy1 – but in the particular way he conceived of
it, with an interpretivist theory of action at its heart. For, despite having had most
of his early experiences in South Africa, and having received much of his collegiate education in the United States, Walter is at heart a thinker in a more classical European tradition. He has resisted the calls for instant answers residing in
unreflecting rationalism or behaviouralism. In its stead, he favours an altogether
nuanced approach to the subject of international relations and foreign policy.
Walter’s is a more humanist tradition, and his world is succinctly populated by
ideas, governed by the interplay between actors, dispositions and structures, and
only understandable through a comprehensive perspective. This principled position may not have earned him any shortcuts into the scholarly walk of fame, but
they guarantee that his relevance will be above and beyond yesterday’s topic du
jour.
Foreign policy has always been in the foreground of Walter Carlsnaes’ work,
as an object of study from a comparative perspective, and with considerable
attention to ideational reasons of foreign policy actions. Ideology, he argues,
works primarily through intentional psychological (as opposed to dispositional)
processes and he thus takes issue with behaviourist and structuralist explanations
xviii╇╇ General Preface
of foreign policy actions. Individuals as decision makers are, in Carlsnaes’ world
not merely ‘rational actors’, but meaning-Â�givers. The trappings of rational choice
explanations, therefore, are not sufficient for providing a theoretical guide to
political action. The typical rational choice causation is teleological (meaning a
simple statement of the intention-�action relationship) and thus ignorant of underlying reasons for political behaviour. Carlsnaes has thus carved a niche for an
interpretivist science of political action as reasoned choice – informed by ideas –
in a time when the ‘constructivist turn’ in international relations was yet to come.
Another theme that became increasingly important in Carlsnaes’ scholarship
is the standing of the European Union in foreign policy and as a foreign policy
actor. In European Foreign Policy: The EC and Changing Perspectives in
Europe, a volume co-�edited with Steve Smith, he helped usher in European
foreign policy as a major sub-�discipline of the field. The debate that the two
editors decided to use to encapsulate their book was the agency–structure debate,
and it is fair to say that this exchange of ideas between the co-�editors has come
to frame a longstanding and important debate in the study of international cooperation as will be illustrated by several of the contributions to the present
volume. As the founding editor for the European Journal of International Relations, Carlsnaes encouraged scholarship that took these metatheoretical issues
seriously. The journal became a clearing-�house of critical theory and constructivist approaches.
The authors in this volume have been fully committed to engage with these
important topics: how to conceive of a theory of political action and how that
impacts the study of foreign policy?
The first two chapters give a more general overview of Carlsnaes’ contribution, be it his intellectual scholarship and his role in the development of IR as a
discipline. Stefano Guzzini’s chapter deals with the importance of conceptualisation for the analytical use of theory, and the troubling back seat this endeavour
has taken to operationalisation and a rush to arrive at a ‘clean scientific language’. Guzzini argues that Carlsnaes’ early engagement with conceptual
analysis, and with the concept of ideology, is a necessary ingredient for understanding his theory of political action and study of foreign policy. In so doing,
the chapter problematises the co-�dependence of theory and concept, as does
Carlsnaes, and its repercussions for the study of foreign policy. A.J.R. Groom
takes a hard look at the sociological and political underpinnings of international
relations and foreign policy as its study is expanding across borders beyond the
habitual western ‘zone of comfort’. This process is one of engaging with the
Other, and unveils the Westphalian system as a means of exclusion, which has
come to distinguish also the social sciences. In this light, Groom points to the
significance of, as well as Carlsnaes’ contribution to, the professionalisation and
the Europeanisation of International Relations. If IR is indeed to go global, so
Groom argues, this development is crucial for the discipline to develop with full
engagement with the Other.
Colin Wight, in his chapter, scrutinises the problems attached with the often
haphazard and unreflecting treatment of agents and structures as ‘mutually
General Preface╇╇ xix
�
constitutive’.
As a grand statement of ontological fact, this is a position that
meets few objections, but as a point of departure for empirical analysis, few
scholars accept the implications for the constraints on ‘business as usual’ that
they are. The chapter follows Carlsnaes’ reintroduction of time to the agent–
structure problem and the three substantial uses which he makes of the debate:
as a methodological device, as an organising instrument for the analysis of
foreign policy, and as a mode of understanding the enduring interrelationship
between IR and foreign policy. Heikki Patomäki engages in the same debate as
Wight: the temporality of agency and structure, and adds to the analysis the geo-�
historical conditions of increasingly complex societies that have given rise to
effective agency in this sense. Processes of collective learning are changing the
fabric of international relations, and developing geo-�historical conditions are
thus indicative of new forms of global-�democratic interaction.
Kjell Goldmann offers a scathing criticism against structural theories of
power as statements of the obvious, and which are wholly unable to explain
change in the international system. The longstanding and outsized preoccupation
of the field with these theories is problematic for IR, and Goldmann suggests
that ways out of this monocausal thinking needs to be developed. He offers two
such escape routes: ideology and identity.
Erik Ringmar’s chapter is an observation of the role of culture in international
relations. He uses as his starting point the reaction of nineteenth-�century Europeans to the Chinese practice of koutou, the ritual of subordination by a full-�length
prostration before the throne of the Chinese emperor. The ritual was offensive to
most Europeans, but there were considerable utilitarian reasons for them to
swallow their pride and go through with the humiliating procedure. Ringmar
shows how national cultural traits are necessary in order to understand the choice
of delegates from these European courts whether ‘to koutou or not to koutou’.
Magnus Ekengren develops a Carlsnaesian agency–structure approach to European Union foreign policy that takes issue with the prevailing realist conception
of the national interest of the member states as determinant of EU foreign policy.
Ekengren argues the need for a ‘theory of practice’ concerning EU as an actor
and an open-�ended and empirically guided approach to the importance of agency
in IR in general and to the EU in particular.
Charles Parker takes stock of international regime theory and its conceptualisation of agency–structure. He argues that the poor attention paid to this dimension of IR is causing regime theory to under-Â�perform on some of its
self-�professed core tasks. Parker discusses the agency of international organisations as purposive but circumscribed, and the regime as superordinate of the
organisation. Regimes are social institutions that enable and constrain the interaction between actors by favouring ‘norm-Â�directed behaviour’ and shaping their
interests and behaviour. In order to understand and evaluate regime significance,
the agency–structure dynamic needs to better inform the conceptualisation of
regime theory and its analysis of regime compliance.
Knud-Â�Erik Jørgensen explores the major European foreign policy traditions
as a potential unifying factor in devising a more or less Common Foreign and
xx╇╇ General Preface
Security Policy. Jørgensen puts serious emphasis on horizontal relationships and
how they enable or constrain state actors, thus avoiding the policy-�oriented and
case dependent grounds for inference that is currently dominating the field. He
opens up for an ontology of the politics of foreign policy across all EU member
states. Helene Sjursen addresses the EU’s much debated ‘normative power’ and,
true to the themes of the volume, does so by re-�examining the concept as such.
Her suspicion is that there is a core to the argument that EU foreign and security
policy is different and does have a normative or ethical component that should
not be ignored. But due to poor conceptualisation, its proponents are running the
risk of having their baby thrown out with the bathwater of naïveté or cloaked
imperialism. Sjursen proposes the establishment of an empirical research agenda
that can see the normative aspect as one constituent part of the emergence of
Europe as a foreign policy actor.
Janne Haaland Matlary has a distinctly different approach to the EU as a
foreign policy actor. She describes, from her realist outlook, a political entity
with a dramatic internal asymmetry to its scope and tools of political power. By
charting the choppy waters of EU capacities and constraints, Matlary arrives at a
blueprint of the impact that the EU can muster in international relations. Pernille
Rieker continues the debate on EU capacities by striking a more positive tone in
that – when seen from a multi-Â�level governance perspective – the EU’s powers
are indeed mutually reinforcing. The dynamic interplay that has evolved between
the EU’s processes of integration and security is crucial for us to understand
what kind of actor the EU is, and correspondingly, what it can do. A combination of a security community perspective and a multi-�level governance perspective is crucial, she argues, for properly analysing this aspect of EU politics.
Fredrik Bynander discusses the problem of dealing with foreign policy value
conflicts under tense political conditions. How do ideas and values inform
foreign policy in times of uncertainty and high stakes? Using the British and
American decisions to justify an invasion of Iraq on the grounds of the proliferation of weapons of mass destruction, the chapter discusses how ideas inform the
internal deliberations over choice and the assessment of international repercussions of alternative action. A prevailing finding is that ideas are not necessarily
simple ‘roadmaps’ when material interest offers little guidance, or ‘stable equilibria’ are unattainable, but can be forceful harbingers for foreign policy action
in their own right and typically carry strong causal beliefs with their followers.
Thomas Risse takes on the importance of the governance perspective for international relations and its repercussions for the agency–structure debate. He
argues that governance holds an inherent compatibility with a sophisticated
understanding of the mutual constitution of agents and structures. Risse notes the
real possibility that the governance research agenda uncovers a decreasing exclusivity of the state in foreign policy analysis and the rise of non-�state actors,
which in turn opens up for new research questions that are not solely concerned
with hierarchical modes of steering.
With Deon Geldenhuys’ final chapter, we return to Carlsnaes’ youth and to
another of his favourite topics: South African foreign policy. Geldenhuys
General Preface╇╇ xxi
�
portrays
the ‘new’ South African foreign policy as one guided by a national role
conception as ‘the apostle’, initially pursuing a policy exclusively centred around
the promotion of universal human rights and democracy. In South Africa’s dealings with Zimbabwe, Sudan, Equatorial Guinea, and Myanmar, he notes the evolution of this strong principle, and how the African National Congress (ANC)
government has been forced to compromise between the dogmatic early ambitions and with what is feasible in a complex regional neighbourhood, thus sometimes being muted in spreading the gospel by other interests, low probabilities
for success, or preoccupation with other pressing needs.
The volume has thus followed Carlsnaes’ footpath, from the early conceptual
work to his theory of action and his study of foreign policy. We have been privileged to accompany him on different parts of this journey and offer this book to
return the favour.
Note
1 An earlier version of this Festschrift or Vennerbok (the golden book), offered to him at
his day of retirement from Uppsala University, included more chapters in Carlsnaes’
honour.
Abbreviations
ANC
ASP
AU
BBC
BISA
CESDP CFSP
CIA
COIN
COSI
CSDP
CWC
DG
DIRCO
DPA
EADRCC
ECHO
ECPR
EEAS
EJIR
ENP
EP
EPC
ESS
EU
EUISS
FPA
IAEA
ICANN
ICC
IGOs
INGOs
African National Congress
The Agent-�Structure Problem
African Union
British Broadcasting
British International Studies Association
Common European Security and Defense Policy
Common Foreign and Security Policy
Central Intelligence Agency
Counter-�Insurgency Operation
EU Internal Security Committee
Common Security and Defence Policy
Chemical Weapons Control Regime
Directorate General (EU)
Department of International Relations and Cooperation (South
Africa)
Darfur Peace Agreement
NATO Euro-�Atlantic Disaster Response Coordination Centre
European Community Humanitarian Aid department
European Consortium for Political Research
European External Action Service
European Journal of International Relations
European Neighborhood Policy
European Parliament
European Political Cooperation
European Security Strategy
European Union
EU Institute for Security Studies
Foreign Policy Analysis
International Atomic Energy Agency
The Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Number
International Criminal Court
Intergovern�ment�al Organ�izations
International Non-govern�mental Organizations
Abbreviations╇╇ xxiii
IO
International Organization
IR
International Relations
ISA
International Studies Association
ISAF
International Security Assistance Force
JAIR
Japan Association of International Relations
JEM
Justice and Equality Movement (Sudan)
JIC
Joint Intelligence Committee
KISAKorea International Studies Association
LSE
London School of Economics and Political Science
MI6
(SIS) Secret Intelligence Service, UK Foreign Intelligence
Organization
MICEU Monitoring and Information Center
MoD
Ministry of Defence
NATO
North Atlantic Treaty Organization
NGO
Non-�Governmental Organiza�tions
NLD
National League for Democracy (Myanmar)
NPT
Non-�Proliferation Treaty
OPCW
Organisation for the Prohibition of Chemical Weapons
OSCE
Organization for Security and Co-�operation in Europe
PPPs
Public Private Partnerships
SADC
Southern African Development Community
SLM
Sudan Liberation Movement
TMSA
Transformational Model of Social Activity
UN
United Nations
UNDAC
UN Disaster Assessment and Coordination
UNHCR
United Nations High Commissioner on Human Rights
UN-�OCHAUnited Nations Office for the Coordination of Humanitarian
Affairs
UNSC
United Nations Security Council
UNSCOM
United Nations Special Commission
USAIDUnited States Agency for International Development
VOC
The Dutch East-�India Company
WISC
World International Studies Committee
WMDs
Weapons of Mass Destruction
WTO
World Trade Organization
ZANUZimbabwe African National Union
Part I
Walter Carlsnaesâ•›.â•›.â•›.
1 In the beginning was
conceptualisation
Stefano Guzzini
Conceptual analysis never had it easy in International Relations. Annoyed by the
continuous need to defend such analysis – ‘it is not mere semantics’ (leaving
aside for the moment what this charge may precisely mean) – David Baldwin
(1979, 1980) bitterly and repeatedly complained about the systematic neglect of
the central role such analysis plays in the scientific enterprise. It seemed so self-�
evident, that being clear about the meaning of concepts would enhance and
indeed ensure any meaningful scientific communication to start with. Looking at
how concepts fitted into frameworks of analyses and theories would moreover
be fundamental for specifying the very building blocks of, and causal links in
our explanations. Not basing one’s analysis on a careful conceptual discussion
ran the risk of tautologies within the explanatory frameworks. Such a prior conceptual check was crucial to avoid the ‘garbage in – garbage out’ of empirical
analysis, where analysts faced with anomalies busily fine-�tune methods and
empirics, when the problem is already in their conceptual base (see the ‘wrecking exercise’ in Baldwin 1985). Surely, conceptual analysis as a first necessary
step of all explanations was to be a central concern of any social science. And
yetâ•›.â•›.â•›.
As it seems, conceptual analysis of this systematic kind was left orphaned
when political science bifurcated and divorced so-�called normative theory from
empirical theory. Spending much time on a concept, its meaning, its evolution
and the historical practices attached to it was to become the reserve of the historian of ideas. Erudite and multilingual, those scholars may inspire intellectual
awe, but have an ephemeral effect on empirical theory. Worse, in the increasing
divide between so-�called continental and analytical philosophy, the historian of
ideas was not even considered a proper philosopher. Central ‘issues’ in philosophy, so we are told, need to be addressed ‘head on’ with increasing mathematical logic, not with a sense of how historical practices and concepts interact.
And, as normative theory, they would address mainly issues of moral philosophy. Inversely, empirical theory, if it did see the need of conceptual analysis,
was reduced to a question of variable formation or operationalisation. Since all
we needed was a clean scientific language, the history and internal logic of concepts within the theories in which they appear was basically useless, their ‘value’
simply a question of definitional fiat.
4╇╇ S. Guzzini
Two things got lost in this bifurcation. First, the concern with the major issues
and problematiques of our discipline, such as ‘the state’, or indeed the origins of
‘order’, could no longer be treated in any way comparable to Ernst Cassirer’s
analysis of (political) ‘myth’ (Cassirer 1946). It simply does not fit the
libertarian-�liberal-communitarian-�radical divide in Anglo-�Saxon moral
philosophy-�cum-democratic theory and it does not provide us with a measurable
variable for testing hypotheses. Between political philosophy and empirical
theory, there was no place left for classical political theory.
Second, the move to empirical theory seemed to have been misunderstood
too. Max Weber had tried hard to establish a true empirical science about things
political (order, the state, power, legitimacy). Not content with his own legal
origins, where order was approached and understood in a formal way, he wanted
to base its understanding in real social action. It was almost as if he reversed the
logic of the lawyer: not how law makes order, but how social order makes law
possible. And so his methodological writings are a scathing attack on both the
formal logic of lawyers and the normative logic of philosophers. And yet, his
empirical sociology is the quintessential reference for conceptual analysis. His
magnum opus Economy and Society (1925) opens with an incredibly dense
section on ‘basic concepts’ which he succinctly develops and justifies, and on
which all his theory and analysis is based (Weber 1980 [1921–1922]). At the
same time, these conceptualisations were fundamental to this late book in his
career, but, in turn, were also the result of his previous studies. The formation of
concepts and the formation of theories are intrinsically connected, ‘interdependent’ as Carlsnaes (1981: 7) writes. For, as Bulmer (1979: 658) reminds us, ‘concepts such as the “protestant ethic” or “marginal utility” derive their meaning
from the part they play in the theory in which they are embedded, and from the
role in that theory itself↜’. And hence, a conceptual analysis which isolates one
concept necessarily slides into the task of assessing a whole theory. No empirical science can escape such a conceptualisation which goes far beyond mere
operationalisation.
Walter Carlsnaes’ (1981, 1986) early studies all focus on the issue of conceptualisation in this more comprehensive manner. This is truly pioneering given
the otherwise very scant attention in the discipline. In this context, my earlier
reference to Weber is not fortuitous. Max Weber appears prominently in Carlsnaes’ conceptual analysis, although not always as a main reference. He is the
inspiration for a style of conceptual analysis that is embedded in an interpretitivist understanding of the social sciences and therefore ultimately relies on a methodological individualist position, at least at the start (for this, below). And yet at
the same time, it is an empirical science which, just as for Weber, aims at causal
analysis and falsification. Concept formation will have to feed into this understanding and be consistent with it. Indeed, the main claim of this chapter is that
Carlsnaes’ early focus on conceptualisation is not only the logical start for a
Weberian-Â�inspired social science, but also the basis from which his later discussion of the agency–structure debate and his theory of foreign policy derive. In
the beginning was conceptualisation.
In the beginning was conceptualisation╇╇ 5
Conceptual analysis as theorising between history and meta-�
theory
When Carlsnaes embarks on his conceptual analyses at the earlier stages of his
career, he is not just interested in the better understanding of some terms. Instead,
analysing those terms is the condition for and is interdependent with his theorising.
Conceptual analysis thus prepares for, and is constitutive of, his theorising of foreign
policy which, in turn, reaches back to more conceptual analysis. This section will
elaborate the way he ‘does’ conceptualisation. As I will argue, Carlsnaes’ type of
analysis exposes some positivist tensions. Becoming aware of those, his approach
eventually allows for a vision of theory which concentrates on its constitutive functions, on the way social theory assumptions interact with conceptualisation and
actual explanatory theory. By the time, the agency–structure debate hits International
Relations, he is therefore not only well prepared, but can immediately use it to elaborate his approach to foreign policy (which will be covered in the next section).
Carlsnaes’ understanding of conceptual analysis is based on two crucial distinctions. It starts from the distinction between words and concepts. Whereas the
first are mere linguistic expressions (‘ordinary language’), the latter are constructions of the mind. The process of conceptualisation is therefore understood as
one ‘in which words and concepts constantly interact with each other, giving
meaning not only to specific phenomena but also to the relationships connecting
them’ (Carlsnaes 1986: 121). This means that conceptualisation is not primarily
about trying to find the ‘best’ or most ‘accurate’ definition, an (often impossible)
exercise in semantics as it were, but the delimitation of a meaning in view of its
place for an explanation. Hence, although ordinary language and the language of
scientific explanation meet, it is the latter which is his primary focus.
A second distinction derives from this. Carlsnaes insists quite heavily on the
distinction between the level of action and the level of observation. This seems
to be the effect of his commitment to Weberian-�Schutzian interpretivism and
also to the just mentioned more artificial language of observation, often supported by references to neo-�positivists like Oppenheim. Weberian interpretivism
imposes an obligatory passage point through the meaning-�world of the analysed
actor, whereas conceptualisation as a scientific enterprise is clearly located at the
level of observation. The two levels should not be confused. Indeed, one of his
repeated diatribes are different fallacies of reification, such as, for instance, conflating observational terms with the ones on the actor level (Carlsnaes 1981: 67,
81; 1986: 43–46). Only the latter can be actual motives for action, i.e. the base
for an empirical explanation.
This two-�fold distinction produces, in turn, two types of specification and also
tensions in his thought, one with history and one with meta-Â�theory. Carlsnaes’
Weberianism makes him say that it ‘is from the world [of the actor] that we have
to extrapolate “theoretically”, not to it that we can wilfully impute our own theoretical constructs’ (1986: 44). From here, it is only logical to insist that our conceptualisations need to be aware of the historical battles around words which are
connected to major political upheavals. He writes:
6╇╇ S. Guzzini
It is this factor that gives a term like ‘ideology’ its causal effectiveness qua
word in human discourse, an efficacy which, although it is patently emotive
in nature and thus has to be differentiated from the function of a term as a
technical designation in political analysis, nevertheless cannot be ignored
and evaded simply by stipulative fiat .â•›.â•›. [w]e cannot hope to defuse or neutralise such emotive associations by merely positing an arbitrary and purportedly value-Â�free definition of ‘ideology’.
(Carlsnaes 1981: 16)
This sensitivity to the historical context in which meanings of the word evolve
(see also Carlsnaes 1986: 137–144) and the need to conceptualise from the actor
to the observer level seems however to be betrayed in other places, as when, for
instance, Carlsnaes endorses Oppenheim’s position against Sartori (for the following, see the discussion in Carlsnaes 1986: 129ff.) Giovanni Sartori’s conceptual analysis, just as Carlsnaes’, is committed to the idea of explanatory theory.
But he keeps a far more direct link to conceptual history, or, rather to the way
concepts embody historical development and experience:
.â•›.â•›.â•›our understandings of meanings are not arbitrary stipulations but reminders of historical experience and experimentation. Most of our political concepts were shaped and acquired their meaning out of a survival of the fittest
process. .â•›.â•›. Thus, political scientists and sociologists – let alone the layman
– ignoring the authors of the past have freed themselves not only from the
constraints of etymology, but equally from the learning process of history.
(Sartori 2009 [1975]: 62, original italics)
For Sartori, it is therefore coherent to make his definitional work clearly start
from the actual (ordinary) usage of words which he classifies within the context
of statements and their relations (Sartori 1984). In contrast, Carlsnaes calls Sartori’s approach a version of ‘semantic inductivism’, which, according to him,
probably produces a richer understanding, yet one which is not really needed for
the purely explanatory purposes of conceptualisation. He prefers here Felix
Oppenheim’s (1981) approach which consistently adheres to the observational
context, checking concepts for their logico-�theoretical import. Oppenheim does
reserve some role to ordinary language, but only in a secondary fashion. Yet this
runs the very risk Carlsnaes identified earlier, namely, of indulging in the development of a private terminology divorced from the very reason for which we
may have been interested in the concept in the first place, including its historical
layers and developments.
This neo-�positivist tendency prompts also a second tension in his approach,
this time not with history, but with meta-�theory. On the one hand, he insists on
the theory-Â�dependence of concepts. According to him, it makes a major difference if a conceptualisation takes place in a structural-Â�functionalist or individualist setting. Therefore, he undertook the analysis of ‘ideology’ with regard to the
particular social theories of Marx, Lenin and Mannheim. By embedding them in
In the beginning was conceptualisation╇╇ 7
their theoretical context, one can unravel the exact nature of their conceptualisation, but also build up the theoretical critique for challenging them. And this
theory-�dependence is consequential. As long as we do not have a general social
theory, conceptual disputes are there to stay (Carlsnaes 1981: 15, 17); they are
not just an effect of our intellectual laziness or academic ambition for the niche-�
distinction.
On the other hand, Carlsnaes is not convinced about the idea of ‘essentially
contested concepts’. He reads it exclusively in terms of the value-Â�dependence of
explanations (as in the reception by Lukes 1974: 26; 1977: 4–6). He then rejects
it on the ground of a (Weberian) value–fact distinction, where, normative concerns may well intrude into a research design, but they do not produce non-Â�
objective explanations, let alone ‘incommensurable’ ones. For Carlsnaes,
incommensurability would imply conceptual relativism (1986: 125). And this, in
turn, can be shown to be wrong since the claim for relativism in itself would be
either relativistic itself and hence not persuasive, or, if not, self-�contradictory
(Carlsnaes 1981: 218; 1986: 127). Indeed, scientific process would no longer be
one of intellectual persuasion, but a mere ‘socio-Â�structural contest’ (Carlsnaes
1986: 126), here echoing Lakatos’ charge against Kuhn’s (1970 [1962]) analysis
of paradigmatic revolutions as resulting in a view of science as ‘mob-Â�
psychology’ (Lakatos 1970: 178). And so, for Carlsnaes, it is fair to work with
the ‘assumption that a fruitful explanatory concept is in principle always a normatively (or morally, or ethically) neutral concept’ (Carlsnaes 1986: 128).
But the necessary theory-�dependence of concepts (in the absence of a general
social theory) and the assumption of a neutral conceptualisation do not easily
meet. Or, rather, defending value-Â�neutrality does not really touch Kuhn’s neo-Â�
Kantian approach in terms of concepts as the condition for the possibility of
knowledge, i.e. of knowledge as an active enterprise, not a passive registration –
a statement Carlsnaes (1981: 32) seems to endorse. How can a conceptualisation
be theoretically (not ethically) neutral if concepts are theory-�dependent and we
lack a general theory?
One solution is traced by Oppenheim and seems to be endorsed by Carlsnaes
in 1986. Here, the proof is in the pudding: if one can construct a concept which
is explanatorily significant and yet does not exclude any other, that conceptualisation is neutral in its effect for empirical theory. Rather than assuming a solution to be impossible – something which is in itself impossible to prove – we
could use such conceptualisations to help build a more neutral solution. But this
will not do. Oppenheim’s conceptualisations were not neutral in this sense. As
one can show (Guzzini 1994: 50–53; 2005: 504–507), there is no way, for
instance, that an agent-Â�based concept of power such as Oppenheim’s could
accommodate a Luhmannian conceptualisation (Luhmann 1975). In fact this
solution only works if one can show the superiority of one social theory over all
the others, i.e. de facto assuming the existence of a general social theory. And
Carlsnaes seemed then often quite convinced that a widely-�conceived interpretivist and methodological individualist approach, one which does neither assume
Humean causality nor narrow utilitarian rationalism, could play that role.
8╇╇ S. Guzzini
Another solution – and the one which seems to underlie Carlsnaes’ later writings (e.g. 1992, 2002) consists of admitting the meta-Â�theoretical dependence of
theorisation and conceptualisation. Here, Carlsnaes classifies theories in a matrix
according to two major meta-�theoretical commitments, one ontological
(individualist-�holist), the other epistemological (naturalism-�interpretivism). This
categorisation had then been proposed in IR by Martin Hollis and Steve Smith
(1990), but also in the philosophy of science more generally (Sparti 1992; Hollis
1994). Yet, at the same time, as Carlsnaes would insist – and this is truly
Â�important to him – this does not exclude meta-Â�theoretical checks and the adjudication of competitive conceptualisations for being better or worse.
In doing so, I would argue, he resists the positivist blackmail mounted in
defence of a neutral language: either there is a common language (and hence no
incommensurable paradigms) or there is none (and then communication and
debate is thus impossible). In response, interpretivists have insisted that such
communication takes place in a type of ongoing mutual translation (Kuhn
1970a, 1970b), during which part of the worldview/theory may be lost, but
which are anyway made possible exactly by the human capacity to interpret. In
other words, the positivist blackmail only functions if one assumes a naturalist,
and not interpretivist theory of action (here used both at the level of the actor and
observer).
Hence, when the agency–structure debate hit IR in the late 1980s, Carlsnaes
was better prepared than most. It immediately allowed him to review his own
approach in its light. There seems to be little question that he still prefers the
individualist-�interpretivist corner (to this also later), but his resistance against
theoretical perspectivism, the acceptance of the possibly irreducible difference
between meta-�theories, has been weakened, because he could see that it would
not undermine a debate about the superiority of some approaches to others.
Whether or not there would be one general theory at the end – a vision which
does not exactly entice the pluralist liberal Popperian streak in Carlsnaes – some
meta-�theoretical commitments surely made less sense for conceptualisations if
applied to certain explanatory aims. Perspectivism did not mean relativism.
Trying to use conceptualisations in the give and take between explanatory
purpose and theoretical frames was still possible, indeed more necessary than
ever, since it now included also explicitly the meta-�theoretical frames. Systematic empirical analysis could do without only at its peril.
The study of foreign policy: from concepts as ideas to ideas
as a concept
Knowing Carlsnaes, one may be astonished to see that his first major work is
dedicated to the analysis of Marx, Lenin and Mannheim, materialists all of them.
And yet, there is a clear logic in his approach. Carlsnaes is interested in the
explanatory significance of a concept. From the start, his analysis ties concepts
to their role in explanations, which, in turn, are embedded in more general social
theoretical frameworks. And the three thinkers are, for him, the main references
In the beginning was conceptualisation╇╇ 9
for developing an explanatorily viable concept of ideology – albeit by critiquing
them. Moreover, by analysing the concept of ‘ideology’, Carlsnaes is able to
check materialist theories in the way they try to think the ideational components
of collective action. Through their critique, he will set the basis for his own
framework of analysis dealing with the role of ideas. At first sight his study is
about the concept of ideology. But it is much more. By looking at the interplay
between concept formation and theory formation it provides the background for
developing a theory of action that includes the role of shared ideas as instruments for action (political doctrines) and also, eventually, as factors that constitute the political process in the first place.
In fact, Carlsnaes’ analysis plays out in a hermeneutic circle. He uses conceptual analysis for making sense of ideology as an explanatory concept; making
sense of ideology as an explanatory concept, he touches on questions of epistemology and the sociology of knowledge which, in turn, help us to better see
the role of conceptual analysis. By looking at the role of ideas both for the
involved actor and the observer, the conceptualisation of ideology turns out to be
a central piece in the development of his meta-�theory, theory of action and, as
we will see here, foreign policy analysis. After having specified the role of conceptualisation as explanatory constructions (concepts as ideas), he can now move
to understand his empirical field where such constructions, both at the level of
the actor and observer, play a role (ideas as concepts).
In Foreign Policy Analysis (FPA), Carlsnaes’ main target is the attempt to
reduce the explanation of action to an input-�output scheme, in which either the
entire through-�put process is ignored (in the earlier behaviouralist manner) or, if
acknowledged, reduced to a series of objective or external factors, such as
bureaucratic politics, cognitive processes, or indeed (utilitarian) rational choice
which assumes and de facto objectifies the actors’ preferences formation. His
commitment to methodological individualism stands mainly for the role
‘meaning’ has in the analysis. He wishes to refocus FPA to the intentions of
actors which cannot be understood without the meaning they give to their environment and their own actions.
In his well-�known scheme, he conceives of this intentional dimension as the
core of the analysis. Choice and preferences are the base for explaining action in
a teleological sense (‘in order toâ•›.â•›.â•›.’, zweckgerichtet). But obviously, having criticised rationalist models for exogenising preference formation, the actual causal
component is only added when we move to his second, the dispositional dimension, including (individual) perceptions and (social) values, answering the question why a certain actor was cognitively pre-�disposed in a certain way. This, in
turn, is embedded within a situational (later: structural) dimension which refers
to both the general material and (social) institutional setting within which action
takes place. In his later elaboration of the agency–structure problematique, the
whole scheme is made dynamic by sequencing all actions for becoming inputs
into the structural and dispositional dimension of the next action. See Figure 1.1.
It is not too difficult to see how the role of ideas has become central in such
an ‘internalist’ analysis. And yet, as if he had opened a Pandora’s box of
10╇╇ S. Guzzini
3
Objective
conditions
Institutional
setting
Foreign
Policy
Action
2
1
Perceptions
Choice
Values
Preference
1 � Intentional dimension
2 � Dispositional dimension
3 � Structural dimension
Causal relationship
Teleological relationship
Figure 1.1╇ Explaining a foreign policy action (source: Carlsnaes (1992: 254)).
�
ideational
factors, his usage until his famous 1992 piece can be seen as too
limited. By concentrating so strongly on the individual for the understanding of
action, the pull for ideas does always come from the actors themselves. It is their
perception, their values and belief systems which predispose their preferences
and action. But by having such a strong commitment against holistic concepts or
dynamics of all sorts, it is as if we would study ideational structures, such as
belief systems, as being of a private sort. But there is no private language, no
atomistic cognition. And hence, even though he does not subscribe to an ontological individualism, the explanatory scheme does not allow for an ideational
structure to have some dynamic of its own, irreducible to the appropriations
made by individual actors.
It is as if Carlsnaes’ often scathing critique of those armchair scientists busily
substituting their own interpretations for the ones of the actors, and his empiricist doubt about holistic units of analysis ever too prone to going metaphysical,
would meet in an analysis which puts meaning at its core and yet ‘objectifies’
the structures within which they are formed, reducing this relation to a causal
and external one (for a related critique of regime theory, see Kratochwil and
Ruggie 1986). But also Carlsnaes’ interpretivism, precisely for its being interpretivism, will have to negotiate between an agential and a structural dynamic, if
the agency–structure debate is truly taken seriously.
Perhaps in a response to a similar critique of his book (Wæver 1990), Carlsnaes came to acknowledge the need to include a more autonomous ideational
In the beginning was conceptualisation╇╇ 11
component for making his own interpretivist scheme work. He now accepts that
there is ultimately a meta-�theoretical divide. Yet, so he says, even when starting
from an interpretivist-�individualist approach, this does not make it impossible to
include structural factors as causes of the explanation. This can be done through
the way they are understood by actors, i.e. by being thus ‘cognitively mediated’
(Carlsnaes 1993: 21). His real theoretical shift comes when he sees the interplay
between agency and structure being played out between ‘institutions’ (which he
adds to the structural dimension) and ‘discursive practices’ (in the dispositional
and hence for him ultimately agential dimension). In particular the latter allows
him now to conceptualise ideas not only as the passive channel for cognitive
mediation, but as ‘constitutive of policy processes’ (ibid.: 27). Rather than reducing the relationship between meaning systems and ideas to an external one,
driven by the purposeful actor, it becomes an internal one, which constitutes the
conditions for the possibility for action. With the reference to discursive practices, his dispositional dimension now includes an intersubjective component.
This does arguably complete his initial scheme rather than undermine it. For
it does not necessarily mean, as he seems to have feared earlier on, that the focus
on the actor’s meanings and intentions is lost. It only pushes the initial inspiration of the dispositional level a logical step further: if we wish to understand
how cognition was predisposed, there is not only a pull from the purposeful
actor, but also a push from the social practices and shared understandings in
which he devises them. A study which has as its explanandum the understanding
of foreign policy action may be well served by concentrating on the pull effect in
the first place, but now integrating the intersubjective component from the start.
Whether it makes sense to conceptualise this as part of agency rather than structure is debatable, since ‘intersubjective’ is not strictly speaking agential. But that
is perhaps less important. The significant implication is, however, that a study
cannot stop at the intentional dimension as he had earlier said: taking agency and
structure seriously means that all dimensions have to be taken into account even
if the focus remains on the intentional one.
Being hence consistent to the spirit of his earlier analysis, or so I would argue,
this solution may also provide a return to a more truly Weberian understanding of
social action. After all, even though Weber’s analysis of the origins of capitalism
passes through the understandings of the actors, it is their social practices which
are the focus of the analysis and not what each individual did, whose behaviour
may have resulted from different reasons (equifinality). And that social practice,
in turn, is informed by an ideational structure (e.g. protestant ethics) which is
intersubjective, not just subjective, and which is constitutive of their practices.
And this, in turn, is used to understand the origins of practices (e.g. capitalism)
which corresponds to the structural effect of such social practices, surely not in
any sense intended, or indeed even part of the meaning system of the actor. I
think it would take little effort to re-�phrase this analysis as the interplay between
social institutions (such as a market economy) and discursive practices.
This conceptualisation of ideas has also implications for Carlsnaes’ place
within the field of foreign policy analysis. By his acknowledgement of the need
12╇╇ S. Guzzini
for combining different theoretical layers for the task of conceptualisation, by
his pluralism in seeing the different frames within which it can be done, he
becomes an obvious defender of an interpretivist and theory-�oriented understanding of FPA (Carlsnaes 2002). That puts him at odds with other equally
actor-�oriented analysis, which tends again to underplay the role of meaning and
proposes a single theoretical analysis of policy processes centred around elite
actors (which is one of the possible readings of the programmatic statement in
Hudson 2005).
It also allows him to become the more individualist reminder of discursive
analysis in constructivist FPA. In a sense, there is almost a division of labour: on
the one hand, constructivist studies on FPA analysing the shared practices and
understandings of the foreign policy actors (Carlsnaes’ dispositional dimension),
but explicitly stopping short from making an analysis of the actual choice and
action (see, e.g. Hopf 2002; Wæver 2004), and his own analysis concentrating
on the actors themselves and their meaningful action in context (closer, in this
regard, to e.g. Risse 2000). Only rarely have the two been combined (Weldes
1999).
Finally, having conceptualised the role of ideas in foreign policy action in
such a manner has methodological implications. Although he clearly endorses
comparative analysis, that will have to be case-�centred, not variable-�centred.
Concentrating on the role of ideas and individual understandings makes historically sensitive single or small-�n case studies the rule, contingent empirical
�generalisations the aim (Carlsnaes 1992: 267). It would indeed ask for a form of
(comparative) process-�tracing in a more interpretivist way than, for example, in
George and Bennett (2005), since it features prominently discursive practices
and elite intentions.
And hence, what started as the conceptualisation of ideology eventually – but
logically and systematically – became a distinct theory of foreign policy action
straddling the interpretivist Weberian and more discursive approach. Indeed,
without that conceptualisation, he could not have reached it, nor defend it, in
such a systematic manner.
Conclusion
The assumption and also lesson of Walter Carlsnaes’ conceptual work is that
empirical science cannot be made at the expense of political theory, and political theory not divorced from our attempt to empirically explain and understand. Rather than reducing one to the other (in either direction), they have to
be thought in parallel, their interaction explored. Language is not just a neutral
medium of representation, but a historical deposit of ideational fights, thus
empirics in itself. The philosophical roots of conceptions shed a light on how
we can use them within our explanatory frameworks; their meta-�theoretical
dependence imposes coherence in their use and empirical operationalisation.
For Carlsnaes, we cannot do without comprehensive conceptualisation, i.e. conceptual history and meta-�theory, not despite but because of our interest in an
In the beginning was conceptualisation╇╇ 13
empirical science. Having that end in mind, it is with conceptualisation that we
have to start.
References
Baldwin, David A. (1979). Power analysis and world politics: New trends versus old tendencies. World Politics, 31, 161–194.
Baldwin, David A. (1980). Interdependence and power: A conceptual analysis. International Organization, 34(4), 471–506.
Baldwin, David A. (1985). Economic statecraft. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Bulmer, Martin (1979). Concepts in the analysis of qualitative data. Sociological Review,
27(4), 651– 677.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1981). The concept of ideology and political analysis: A critical examination of its usage by Marx, Lenin, and Mannheim. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1986). Ideology and foreign policy: Problems of comparative conceptualization. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36(3), 245–270.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1993). On analysing the dynamic of foreign policy change: A critique
and reconceptualization. Cooperation and Conflict, 28(1), 5–30.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2002). Foreign Policy. In Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse and Beth
A. Simmons (eds), Handbook of International Relations (pp.€331–349). London: Sage.
Cassirer, Ernst (1946). The myth of the state. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
George, Alexander and Bennett, Andrew (2005). Case studies and theory development in
the social sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Guzzini, Stefano (1994). Power analysis as a critique of power politics: Understanding
power and governance in the second Gulf War. Florence: European University Institute.
Guzzini, Stefano (2005). The concept of power: A constructivist analysis. Millennium:
Journal of International Studies, 33(3), 495–522.
Hollis, Martin (1994). The philosophy of social science: An introduction. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Hollis, Martin and Smith, Steve (1990). Explaining and understanding international relations. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hopf, Ted (2002). Social construction of international politics: Identities and foreign policies, Moscow, 1955 and 1999. Ithaca, NJ: Cornell University Press.
Hudson, Valerie M. (2005). Foreign policy analysis: Actor-�specific theory and the ground
of International Relations. Foreign Policy Analysis, 1(1), 1–30.
Kratochwil, Friedrich and Ruggie, John Gerard (1986). International organization: A state
of the art on an art of the state. International Organization, 40(4), 753–775.
Kuhn, Thomas (1970a). Logic of discovery or psychology of research? In Imre Lakatos
and Alan Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp.€ 1–23). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kuhn, Thomas (1970b). Reflections on my critics. In Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave
(eds), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp.€ 231–278). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kuhn, Thomas (1970 [1962]). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
14╇╇ S. Guzzini
Lakatos, Imre (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the growth of
knowledge (pp.€91–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Luhmann, Niklas (1975). Macht. Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke Verlag.
Lukes, Steven (1974). Power: A radical view. London: Macmillan.
Lukes, Steven (1977). Power and structure. In Steven Lukes (ed.), Essays in social theory
(pp.€3–29). New York: Columbia University Press.
Oppenheim, Felix E. (1981). Political concepts: A reconstruction. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Risse, Thomas (2000). ‘Let’s argue!’ Communicative action in world politics. International Organization, 54(1), 1–39.
Sartori, Giovanni (1984). Guidelines for concept analysis. In Giovanni Sartori (ed.) Social
science concepts: A systematic analysis (pp.€15–88). London: Sage,
Sartori, Giovanni (2009 [1975]). The tower of Babel. In David Collier and John Gerring
(eds), Concepts and method in social science: The tradition of Giovanni Sartori
(pp.€61–96). London: Routledge.
Sparti, Davide (1992). Se un leone potesse parlare. Indagine sul comprendere e lo spiegare. Firenze: Sansoni.
Wæver, Ole (1990). The Language of Foreign Policy. Journal of Peace Research, 27(3),
335–343.
Wæver, Ole (2004). European integration and security: Analysing French and German
discourses on state, nation, and Europe. In David R. Howarth and Jacob Torfing (eds),
Discourse theory in European politics: Identity, policy and governance (pp.€ 33–67).
Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.
Weber, Max (1980 [1921–22]). Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriss der verstehenden
Soziologie. Tübingen: J.€C.€B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).
Weldes, Jutta (1999). Constructing national interests: The United States and the Cuban
missile crisis. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
2 Coming to terms with the ‘Other’
Towards IR going global
A.J.R. Groom
Introduction
Walter Carlsnaes has made an extraordinary contribution to the study of international relations and not only in his particular area of expertise. Much of his
writing has been in the relatively unfashionable area of foreign policy analysis.
His work has been illuminating and has carried forward a subject area which
was, in many ways, in the doldrums. In addition Carlsnaes is also a man of great
scholarship, which can be seen in the contributions he has made to various handbooks on IR theory and, in particular, as the founding editor of the European
Journal of International Relations. Thus Carlsnaes’ contribution has been not
only in the traditional academic terms of research and scholarship, but also in the
form of institution building, which has had a significant effect on the study of
international relations, not only in Europe but also in North America. Moreover,
his experience is relevant for International Relations as it aspires to go global.
In plotting the evolution of IR as it begins to go global we are engaging in an
endeavour which is not merely an intellectual history, but also an analysis of
sociological and political trends. Where we have come from explains more than
a little of what we are. Moreover, memory is a guide for the future, since we can
draw upon its lessons, not only from our past failures but also from our past successes. In plotting this evolution a number of way stages can be identified.
However, most great events, which may be signified by a particular act or period,
are in fact part of a larger process. There is room for agency in bringing about
particular acts, but there is also a need for a cognisant awareness of the structure
of the greater process within which the agent acts. The work of Carlsnaes, both
in foreign policy analysis and in the building of professional organisations, illustrates both the agency and the structure. He has contributed mightily to both. Our
purpose is first to take some ‘snap-Â�shots’ of the structure in evolution and then to
look at agency in the form of Carlsnaes’ contribution to institution building
before drawing some lessons for IR as it begins to go global.
An encounter with the ‘Other’
One way stage that I would like to identify is 2 January 1492, because it is a
watershed between the notion of Europe, and that of the Other. In 1492 the
16╇╇ A.J.R. Groom
�
conquest
of the Americas by the Iberians was about to get underway and at the
same time Granada fell to the Iberians thus ending 700 years of Muslim governance, culture, science and philosophy in Western Europe. Of course, the influence of the Muslims in Europe did not end there because as they were pushed
out of Europe at one extremity geographically, they were entering Europe at the
other extremity of the continent by establishing themselves in Anatolia and the
Balkans to the extent that they were eventually rebuffed from the gates of
Vienna in 1689. Nevertheless, since Europe was not tolerant of others, especially
Muslims, they were perceived as Other.
International Relations emerged to analyse a world in which notions of sovereignty increasingly took root. Sovereignty involved the idea of sameness and of
equality and it became the basis of the Westphalian system. Muslims were
beyond this system and not allowed to take part in it. Thus the idea of being the
same was not applied to the new world of the Americas, nor to the old world of
the Muslims as their home in Europe switched from Iberia to the Balkans. In this
sense we can say that IR grew out of a stratified European world. The ‘world’
was Europe and the rest was Other. IR therefore developed within a system
where primacy was with the European sovereign state. Europeans asserted their
supremacy, the superiority of their civilisation, their right to exercise their manifest destiny, to bear the white man’s burden, to engage in a mission civilisatrice
and to pillage the world. While relations between European states were hierarchical, because of their differing capacities, this stratification was nothing when
compared to that between the European-�centric world and the Other.
Speaking with many tongues
What we speak has a significant influence on what and how we think. Galtung
(1981) suggests that, in so far as IR is concerned, there were four approaches
to which I wish to add a fifth. Galtung’s four worlds are Gallic, Nipponic, Teutonic and Saxonic, and to these I would add a Russian or Eurasian approach.
The importance of language and the significance of the structural dominance of
English as it replaced French as the language of both the conduct of international relations and its study needs to be stressed. He points out that English
has had its successes, not only by dint of the fact that it is the language of the
last two global leaders, the United Kingdom and the United States, but also
because its simple linear argument stresses clarity. Short sentences with few
sub-�clauses exemplify its style, however, while English can express a linear
argument clearly, other languages, such as German, are better for expressing
complexity. Indeed, it is interesting to speculate what might have been the
development of IR if its principal language had been German or French.
However, the collapse of German as an international medium for science in the
Nazi period left French more exposed and less able to compete with English.
Such a consideration is not merely an indulgence in thinking about what might
have been, but may well prepare us for what might be, as other languages, such
as Mandarin, Spanish, Japanese or Arabic come to play a more important role
Towards IR going global╇╇ 17
at the global level. They will also surely have an impact on the conduct, conceptions and the study of IR.
In considering these five linguistic-�structural approaches, we can see that the
Gallic approach gives great emphasis to the notion of a state and therefore to the
theory and practice of power, both as pouvoir and puissance, and administration.
While the Gallic tradition is concerned with law, it has also developed a strong
tradition of conceptualised area studies drawing on a wide interdisciplinary base,
not only in the Social Sciences, but also beyond. The Nipponic tradition is one
that is based on political philosophy, and it is interesting to note the linkages
between German and Japanese philosophers in the 1920s in the area of international political theory. Moreover, the Nipponic tradition of that period also
brought the tentative development of a particular niche in the area of peace
research. The Teutonic approach also stresses philosophy, hence the linkages in
the 1920s and, like the Japanese, Germany became an early centre for peace
research in the 1960s. The Saxonic approach, however, gives much more attention to empirical research and is often conceived, at least in the United States, in
terms of political science, whereas international history is the predominant root
in the UK tradition. To these should be added a Russian or Eurasian tradition in
which stratification, particularly in terms of class within states, stratification due
to the spread of global capitalism and geopolitics were given salience. Along
with the Ottomans, were the Russians part of Europe or were they part of the
Other? For some the question is still pertinent.
Three great traditions
As Europe began to conceptualise international relations it did so in a framework
which reflected not only these five cultural approaches but also three great traditions of political thought concerning intergroup relations. These go back beyond
the Westphalian system to the ancient European world, and indeed, they go
beyond Europe to other parts of the world, such as China and India, through
thinkers such as Sun Tsu and Emperor Ashoka. Martin Wight (1991) summed
up these three traditions as that of the realist, the rationalist and the revolutionary. Michael Banks (1985) suggested a similar division, which he called realists,
world society approaches and structuralists. We can quickly see that thinkers
such as Hobbes and Machiavelli fall into the realist tradition, whereas Grotius
and Kant reflect a more pluralist philosophy. If we think in terms of structuralists, then the name of Karl Marx immediately comes to the fore. It is often the
case nowadays that this third tradition of structuralists is ignored to be replaced
by that of constructivists. However, it would be short sighted to drop the structuralist tradition and the constructivist approach can be seen as being more about
method than a tradition of thought.
In the nineteenth century all three of these traditions were evident as international relations was emerging as a social science. A realist framework could be
seen through the operation of the balance of power and its institutionalisation in
the concert system. It was an approach that was state-�centric, which saw power
18╇╇ A.J.R. Groom
politics as the main medium of influence and exhibited an overriding concern
with the security dilemma. At the same time, it was also possible to identify a
more rationalist, progressive and pluralist approach in the development of international public unions, the early attempts at arms control through the Hague
Peace Conferences, the growth of arbitration and international courts, the
humanitarian development of human rights and the involvement of civil society
in such questions as the establishment of the International Committee of the Red
Cross, the abolition of the slave trade and then, eventually, of slavery itself. The
revolutionary or structural approach in the nineteenth century manifested itself
in the analysis of Marx and others about the growth, evolution and ultimate
downfall of capitalism, which was associated, in their eyes, with imperialism.
Indeed, Lenin (1964) wrote a pamphlet entitled ‘Imperialism: the Highest Form
of Capitalism’ during the Great War, which was his contribution to a debate
involving others, such as Hobson and Schumpeter, about the relationship
between capitalism and imperialism. This was not the only concern of structuralist analysis, since geopolitics, which had its early roots in Sweden, had become a
major structural approach. It could be seen in the writings of Mahan and Mackinder, and later in the academic writings of Haushofer and others in Munich, in
its twisted use as a ‘scientific’ base for racist expansion by Hitlerite Germany.
The First World War, rightly called The Great War, was a catastrophe for the
Euro-�centric world. It was a world-�wide European civil war. Pride comes before
a fall, and the Europeans were undoubtedly arrogant to an almost unbelievable
extent in their utter conviction of their racial and religious superiority, their
advanced social and economic organisation and of their greater force of arms.
The fall was equally great, as those who thought themselves as bringing civilisation to the world, destroyed their own civilisation in the Fields of Flanders, in
the Dolomites, in the Levant and Near East and on the Great Steppes of Central
and Eastern Europe. This catastrophe could not but give food for thought, and
the question arose as to how such another collapse of civilisation could be prevented. It was in this atmosphere that the academic discipline of International
Relations was founded.
The agenda was clear: there were two fundamental questions, namely, what
are the causes of war, and what are the bases of a stable, long-�term peace? Of the
three traditions to which we have just made reference, two were, in fact, out of
the running, in the sense that the balance of power system of power politics had
failed in 1914, and the consequences of this failure were evident to all. On the
other hand, structuralist approaches were, in their economic form at least, taken
up by a revolutionary state, namely, the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics
(USSR), which sought to eliminate the bourgeoisie and bourgeois states elsewhere in the world, but especially in Western Europe. The potential victims were
not amused. For them, this left the tradition of rational, progressive thought, of
large-�scale social engineering. Under the aegis of many groups in civil society,
through such forms as the League of Nations Union, a grand attempt was made
to create a new world order which would bring out the natural harmony of interests between peoples who could have no interest in the conduct of wars which
Towards IR going global╇╇ 19
were essentially dynastic. States which were democratic and nations which
became states were deemed likely to be of the liberal internationalist way of
thinking. They could settle their differences peacefully if there were created, at
the same time, an organisation of a universal nature. It could promote not only
functional integration, but also establish a regime of international peace and
security. This organisation was the League of Nations.
Founding an academic discipline
Thus International Relations grew out of the experience of the nineteenth century
and reflected a long tradition of thought. The first Chair of International Relations was established at the University of Wales in Aberystwyth, a small seaside
town on the Welsh coast, and this was followed quite quickly by Chairs at the
London School of Economics (LSE) and at Oxford. At the same time, what later
became the Royal Institute of International Affairs (Chatham House) was also
founded. All of them were concerned with what was deemed to be the scientific
study of the causes of war, and the conditions for permanent peace. Similar institutions followed quickly in the United States (US). The tradition in the United
Kingdom (UK) grew out of a concern with international political history,
whereas that in the United States was much more influenced by international law
and the recently established political science. Both in the US and in the UK the
state was not given the salience that was evident in continental countries. Indeed,
the reference was usually to the government rather than to the state. There was
no strong notion of l’État with a republican tradition, such as predominates in
France and in many other continental countries. From the beginning, IR was
essentially Anglo-�American, but not exclusively so. The Graduate Institute of
International Studies in Geneva, established in 1927, was a case in point. As the
League of Nations developed in areas beyond that of collective security, it established groups, such as the Institute for Intellectual Cooperation, which in turn
organised many academic conferences in the 1920s and 1930s. These attracted
academics in the newly established field of International Relations and also those
from International Law and International History.
This collegiality involved scholars from many of the independent states of the
world, which at that time were essentially European, North American, the British
Dominions and Latin American, with a few additions. It was broken by the rise
of the Nazis in Germany, and more generally of Fascism and Social Darwinism
in much of continental Europe. At the same time it brought an emigration of
leading IR scholars, who brought a continental input of a more philosophical sort
to the essentially empirical or historical analysis, which then pertained in Britain
and the United States. The scholars included Georg Schwarzenberger in the UK
and Hans Morgenthau, Ernst Haas, Arnold Wolfers and Karl Deutsch in the US.
They quickly made their contribution along with the existing leaders of the field
who included E.H. Carr, Sir Charles Webster, Sir Alfred Zimmern and David
Mitrany in the UK, and Quincy Wright, William and Annette Fox, Norman
Palmer, Pitman Potter and George Kennan in the US. Thus, while on the
20╇╇ A.J.R. Groom
�
continent
there was little development in terms of professorial positions, departments and the like, nevertheless, the continental voice was heard in the Anglo-�
American domain.
This phase of the continentalisation of IR in the US is now over. Global IR is
perhaps the worse for it, since there are disturbing elements of hegemony and
insularity leading to an ever greater parochialism in some aspects of academic
life in the US. There is now little or no European influence on US scholarship
and research, which may be because Europe has nothing to say. But it could also
be because the US is increasingly parochial and in particular because many US
scholars are not able to read that which is written in other languages. Translation
often loses the subtleties of thought of the original.
As IR became more heavily concentrated in the US, at least in terms of
quantity, and as IR risked becoming, as some alleged it had already become, an
American Social Science, then the study reflected the world as seen by a super
Power and its clones. However, there were challenges to such approaches in the
US, for example by Karl Deutsch and James Rosenau in the 1960s, and also in
the writings of John Burton and David Mitrany in the UK, which circulated
quite widely in North America. These writers began to regard the question of
units of analysis, whether states or systems of transactions, and levels of
analysis, with pluralist views of world society, as being of greater significance
than was usually attributed to them in the US. Other new voices began to be
heard, for example, in foreign policy analysis, where Indian scholars developed
notions of non-�alignment, while structural theories of a centre-�periphery nature
emanated from Latin America. The original ‘English’ school flourished in the
UK, with Martin Wight, Herbert Butterfield, C.A.W. Manning and, later,
Hedley Bull, Adam Watson, Richard Little and Barry Buzan. Moreover, historical sociology was not neglected in the writings of Michael Mann. However
strangely, a key American enterprise was the development of integration theory,
particularly when applied to the empirical case of the European Union. The
Europeans paid scant attention conceptually to what was happening on their
own doorstep, at least initially.
The famous article An American Social Science: International Relations by
Stanley Hoffmann (1977), who had received much of his training in France, but
who was, nevertheless, a leading figure in IR in the US, suggested that IR was an
American Social Science. There is no doubt, that in terms of quantity and
quality, the US produced much that was excellent, but there was also work of
lesser quality. In most of the main areas, or sub-�fields, of International Relations,
the European contribution was considerable and independent of that of the US,
whether in International Political Theory, Conflict Studies, Strategic Studies,
International Political Economy, Political Geography and the like. Indeed, it
could be said that there was a greater variety of high quality work in Europe than
in the US, but while the Europeans were very aware of what was happening in
North America, the reverse was not true, to the detriment of both. Only in
rational choice theory was there a gross asymmetry. Where whole schools of
rational choice theorists flourished in the US, only a few, rather isolated adepts
Towards IR going global╇╇ 21
of this approach existed in Europe. So where are the major centres of International Relations as a discipline as we advance into the twenty-�first century?
It is quite clear that there has been a significant contribution in the US, the
UK, France, Germany, Russia, Scandinavia, Japan and Australia. On the other
hand, the contribution from other areas, where it might have been expected, was
less than anticipated, such as from Canada, the Indian sub-�Continent, South East
Asia, Brazil, China, Korea, Italy and Spain. However, many of these are likely
to make a significant contribution in the future, as will Turkey, but there still
remain arid regions, such as Africa, the Levant and the Middle East and, to a
large degree, South East Asia. This evolution of a discipline has been and will be
carried forward by individuals, creating and reacting within a professionalised
framework. They are the agents acting within and creating the structure bit by
bit. One such individual is Walter Carlsnaes.
Carlsnaes’ contribution
The many contributions that Walter Carlsnaes has made to the study of international relations, and in particular, to foreign policy analysis, are the subject of
other essays in this volume. I shall therefore, concentrate on his contribution to
the professionalisation and Europeanisation of IR as an academic discipline, and
the contribution that he has made to an even wider world, as the founding editor
of the European Journal of International Relations. Indeed, Carlsnaes has left a
lasting mark as the first editor and the journal is now established as one of the
leading journals in IR in the world. However, it was not always thus.
In various parts of Europe during the 1950s and 1960s there gradually
emerged centres where IR studies were to some degree institutionalised in the
form of departments or research institutes. Examples of this can be found in
Britain, France, the Netherlands and in the Scandinavian countries. These centres
clearly made a contribution of great importance to the subject world-�wide in the
fields of International Political Economy, Conflict Studies, Strategic Studies,
International History, International Law, and the conceptualised study of geographical regions, particularly in the developing world. For example, the phrase
tiers-�monde is an indicator that Third World Studies began in the framework of
French Social Science. At the same time, there was the original English School,
which was formed by a number of scholars with an historical and philosophical
background, who shared, for the most part, a Christian ideology and who put
international political theory, back on to the agenda. Likewise, political geography was a subject that was strong in France.
Nevertheless, International Relations, as an academic subject, was spread
around Europe in penny packets, sometimes in the Humanities, in Social Science
or in Law, and at other times attached to departments of Political Science, Economics, Political Economy or History depending on national traditions and conceptions. There were few departments or Chairs, and very few research institutes,
although there were some academic think-�tanks, such as Chatham House and its
equivalents in countries such as Belgium, the Netherlands, the Scandinavian
22╇╇ A.J.R. Groom
countries and Germany, not forgetting the Academy of Science Institutes in the
Soviet sphere. There were very few professional associations. In short, except in
the UK, there was no critical mass, and this remains to some degree the case in
various countries in Europe and beyond, such as India.
However, two professional associations began to give a degree of coherence to
work in the field on both sides of the Atlantic. The first occurred in the US with
the setting up of the International Studies Association (ISA) in the 1960s, which
was initially based on the West coast, and then spread throughout North America,
and indeed, beyond, so that it is now a North American organisation with an international membership. A little later, in 1974, the British International Studies Association (BISA) was founded in the UK. It grew out of something called the Bailey
Conference, which in its turn was a hangover from meetings organised under
League of Nations’ auspices between national groups in the inter-Â�war period. To
give an indication of the growth in size in Britain, a Bailey Conference in 1966
had, from memory, 27 participants, and that represented grosso modo the academic field of IR. It was small, and concentrated in very few centres such as
London, Aberystwyth and, to a lesser degree, small centres in places such as Aberdeen. However, in the decade that followed there was an expansion of posts so
that it made sense to create BISA, and this was done by the leading professorial
figures in the UK at that time, such as Alistair Buchan, Susan Strange, Philip Reynolds, David Wightman, Jack Spence and a few others. The rite de passage for
graduate studies in IR still remained in the US, although some graduate students
from the Commonwealth and the Continent came to the UK, as did Walter Carlsnaes. But this was all to change, and a European dimension was in the offing.
The stimulus for building beyond national associations towards creating a
European dimension for the study of international relations was a joint conference to be organised by BISA and ISA in London in 1989. At that time ISA was
in a phase of what can only be called imperialistic expansion. It had aspirations
to become not the national association in the US or regionally in North America,
but to become a global hegemonic organisation under US leadership, finance and
mentoring, and it saw, or so it seemed to people in BISA, that the proposed
London conference would be an opportunity for ISA to establish itself in Europe,
and for Europe to be a regional body of the ISA in a traditional centre–periphery
structure. The planning for the conference on the BISA side was undertaken by a
committee led by the chairpersons or vice-�chairpersons of BISA, who in the
period 1986–1992 were Jack Spence, Barry Buzan and A.J.R. Groom. It was
Groom, in fact, who raised the issue of ISA incorporating Europe into its framework and expressed the view that if Europe was to organise it should be done by
Europeans, and not done for Europeans by an American association – benevolent or otherwise. The inevitable followed, since if an issue is raised in a Committee, those who raise the issue are normally told to get on with the job, and
Groom set about doing this, with the aid of John Roper from Chatham House,
and Bob O’Neill, from the International Institute for Strategic Studies (IISS).
Both Jack Spence and Barry Buzan gave very strong support in alerting their
academic networks.
Towards IR going global╇╇ 23
It soon became evident that there was a market for some form of European
dimension for the study of IR. Informal meetings were held at BISA conferences, and also at European Committee for Political Research (ECPR) Joint Sessions, which led eventually in 1989 to a Workshop on International Relations
and Europe in the Paris Joint Sessions of ECPR. Many of the participants in that
workshop then formed an informal committee to take the matter further, and
Walter Carlsnaes was to become an important figure in that committee. They
were a group of individuals who had imagination, commitment and the willingness to work hard. They were not put off by predictions of failure and they were
careful not to turn anybody away, whether because of their nationality or their
approach. Indeed, the aspiration was clearly to be pan-�European and it was a
good moment in the sense that establishing ties with the Central and East European countries began to be easier with the end of the Cold War.
The committee used a number of building blocks. One was to ensure that
there was a strong French participation, because that would be a gate to participation by scholars in Mediterranean countries, such as Spain and Italy. At the
other end of Europe was the Scandinavian group which already had ties amongst
themselves, and there were particular strengths in the Netherlands, Germany and
Russia, where the vice rectors of the Moscow State Institute of International
Relations (MGIMO) were enthusiastic in playing a role. This process then culminated in the First Pan-�European International Relations Conference, which
was organised at the University of Heidelberg in 1992 by Frank Pfetsch and
Groom. Something approaching 500 scholars from all parts of Europe attended,
as did a sprinkling of leaders in the field from North America. Indeed, by now
the leadership and attitude of ISA towards Europe had changed radically from
being that of incorporating the periphery to one of a welcome consensual and
co-�operative collaboration. So what was to be the next step?
It was now evident that there was a clear demand, and that some form of
association needed to be created. There were two options. The first was to
accept the notion of leadership from the ISA, and to become a regional body in
ISA, and this was rejected on the basis that if Europeans were to be organised
they must organise themselves, and not lean unduly on the ISA, valuable
though its support and experience turned out to be. The second option was to
be an independent body, but this raised financial questions, especially the
establishment of a secretariat, which also raised the issue of membership and
given that the aim was to be pan-�European, it was extremely difficult in those
days for any individuals or institutions from East and Central Europe to pay
dues in hard currency. A solution was found in the framework of the European
Consortium for Political Research (ECPR), which had been set up in 1970 on
the same basis as the IR organisation, namely, to create a European dimension
so that Europeans did not have to go to North America to talk to each other.
ECPR was therefore able to provide a legal framework, in the sense that it is a
charity registered in England, under English law, and it had sub-�groupings
which were known as Standing Groups of which the IR Committee became
one. In other words, the ECPR provided a broad framework within which a
24╇╇ A.J.R. Groom
largely autonomous International Relations association on a European scale
found a home, and there, happily, it remains.
The Standing Group Committee had ambitions to go beyond that of simply
holding a pan-�European conference every three years, of which the seventh was
held in Stockholm in September 2010. The idea was quickly expressed that
Europe needed a European journal and negotiations were started with publishers
to investigate the possibilities. In those days the establishment of a journal was
not easy, and most journals were associated with the membership dues of a particular association. Because the Standing Group did not have individual membership since it was open to all, without membership fees, although fees were
charged for specific activities such as conferences, this option was not available.
Thus it was necessary to find a publisher who would be willing to accept the risk
of a journal which was not tied to a specific fee-�paying membership. In a sense
the Conference at Heidelberg and the subsequent one in Paris in 1995 were very
important because they revealed that there was a body of scholars who were
easily accessible numbering 500 or more who might be interested in individual
subscriptions, as well as the normal institutional subscriptions. Groom and Wolf�Dieter Eberwein canvassed publishers and came up with two possibilities, Sage
and Frank Cass, they eventually recommended that the contract offered by Sage
was the most advantageous for the European dimension. The Standing Group
had now established a journal, so it was then necessary to choose an editor, and
the committee used various networks to elicit the names of those who might be
interested, and indeed, several candidates came forward.
The Standing Group Committee chose Walter Carlsnaes as the first editor,
and he in his turn was able to negotiate with Uppsala University a very generous
arrangement in which his teaching load was lightened and he was given strong
support by the university. Not only was the university generous, but so was
Walter Carlsnaes – of his time, of his effort, and he made ample use of his connections in Scandinavia, in Britain, in various other parts of Europe, as well as in
North America. He was also an editor, not only of high scholarly standing, but
one with a catholic approach. Above all, he was an intensely professional editor.
He set standards which were at the highest international level and would not
break them in any substantive fashion. He was an editor of commitment, flair
and reliability with an exemplary integrity. Occasionally explosive by nature, he
would subsequently come down to earth feet first and well planted in good sense.
He set out his philosophy for the new journal in the first issue, which was in
March 1995. The attitude of the Standing Group Committee, the Editorial Board
as well as its Advisory Council, was that, once having made a careful choice of
editor, it was, within reason, the editor’s job to establish the journal as he saw fit.
In short, we had confidence in Carlsnaes, and that confidence was amply repaid.
In his 1995 editorial on the publication of the first issue of the new journal
Carlsnaes saw it as ‘the obvious occasion to give voice to the intended intellectual timbre of a new journal, and to articulate its ambitions vis-Â�à-vis the research
and scholarly community for which it has been created.’ Carlsnaes then went on
to explain what he meant by European, by commenting that ‘although European
Towards IR going global╇╇ 25
in terms of its genesis, governance and title, our aim is to make this a truly international journal in its intellectual scope and geographic reach. Since its purpose
is to stimulate and disseminate research and scholarship in international relations
throughout the global academic community, it should hence in no way be construed to be mainly a journal for Europeans writing about Europe.’ Carlsnaes felt
‘no concomitant need to impose a “European” point of view – either philosophically, methodologically or geographically – on its contents’. He added that ‘if
there is a distinct advantage in being a European scholar (rather than, say, an
American one), it is, perhaps, that we frequently have to cross geographic, linguistic and institutional boundaries in order to perform well as researchers and
academic teachers. Paradoxical as it may sound, residing mainly within small or
medium-�sized countries and academic milieus may very well function as a built�in antidote to parochialism; and to the extent that this is the case, I hope that this
will be reflected in the pages of this journal.’Carlsnaes posed the question as to
what sort of contributions the journal should publish, and he stated firmly that he
was ‘equally open to submissions which are either typically mainstream or
which .â•›.â•›. emanate from the more critical or dissident margins of International
Relations, wherever these may be located. What matters in this respect is the
quality of the argumentation being presented, not the intellectual domicile of the
author(s).’ There was nevertheless a priority given ‘to issues of general theoretical concern over issues with a narrow empirical or policy import’. Moreover,
the journal was ‘to facilitate ties with cognate disciplines within and outside the
social sciences’. Carlsnaes reminded himself and others that
the only effective way to produce an excellent journal is to attract the very
best scholarship available; but to do so the journal must be made to be intellectually attractive in the first place, which is no mean feat and which certainly will not be accomplished simply by proclaiming lofty aspirations.
He then went on to express the hope that he had struck ‘a responsive chord
within both reader and prospective author, in whose hands the future of this
venture ultimately lies’ (Carlsnaes 1995). In a word, he was successful, beyond
our wildest dreams.
Carlsnaes succeeded unequivocally in creating an International Relations
journal that is the equal of any in Europe or North America, and which is widely
acknowledged as such. He provided the foundation for the journal and much of
the structure. Nevertheless, the European Journal of International Relations
(EJIR) is a journal which does not reflect the Other. It is a journal of the centre
which is essentially in Europe and North America, so the time is becoming ripe
for a further step to embrace, not only the centre, but also the Other.
Going global?
IR is in the process of going global, not through a process of cloning, but by
aspiring to the genuine opening of mind, spirit and research to the Other and to
26╇╇ A.J.R. Groom
the agenda of the Other. In East Asia, Japan has had an independent voice in the
field since the 1920s, although it was essentially a discussion in international
political theory. India and China are now developing professional associations,
and Brazil is well on its way to having a very vibrant critical mass in the field of
IR. Just as the Pan-�European conferences brought the notion of a European IR
community into embryonic being, then such a global community may also be in
its embryonic stage. Over a 15-year period, first Buzan, and then Groom, acted
as Chairpersons of the World International Studies Committee (WISC). WISC
has a membership of over 20 International Studies Associations of a national or
regional character from all over the world, including major bodies such as ISA,
BISA, Japanese Association of International Relations (JAIR) and Korea International Studies Association (KISA). It has already held two global conferences,
each with an attendance of around 1000 scholars, including the limited participation of scholars from areas of the world such as Central Asia, who normally do
not participate in such affairs.
The third such conference was held in Oporto in August 2011. The aim is to
bring a more global perspective, in terms of participation and agenda, to the
study of International Relations. In other words, it is to embrace the Other in a
manner acceptable to all. At the moment there are areas with poor participation
in terms of numbers from Africa, the Arab world, South East Asia and the sub-�
Continent. Fortunately, there has been a growing and increasingly vibrant contribution from Latin America. But no national association, no regional association
can act in a fully global manner from its own base. It must create a new base,
and one that is acceptable to all – in short a global base. What the Standing
Group did for Europe needs to be done for global IR. At the present time WISC
is a potential vehicle for this, and individual scholars, such as Tickner and
Wæver (2009), are undertaking very helpful and illuminating mapping exercises
of International Relations all over the world. If the new generation adopts the
openness, the commitment and the integrity of the generation of Walter Carlsnaes, then IR will be going global to the benefit of all.
References
Banks, Michael (1985). The inter-�paradigm debate. In Margot Light and A.J.R. Groom
(eds), International relations: A handbook of current theory (pp.€ 7–26). London:
Frances Pinter.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1995). Editorial. European Journal of International Relations, 1(1), 5–7.
Galtung, Johan (1981). Structure, culture, and intellectual style: An essay comparing
Saxonic, Teutonic, Gallic and Nipponic approaches. Social Science Information/sur les
sciences sociales, 20(6), 817–856.
Hoffmann, Stanley (1977). An American social science: International Relations. Daedalus,
106(3), 41–60.
Lenin, Vladimir I. (1964). Imperialism, the highest stage of capitalism. In Collected
Works (Vol. 22). London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Tickner, Arlene B. and Wæver, Ole (eds) (2009). International relations scholarship
around the world. London: Routledge.
Towards IR going global╇╇ 27
Waever, Ole (1981) The sociology of a not so international discipline. International
Organization, 53(3), 695.
Wight, Martin (1991). International theory: The three traditions (edited by Gabriele
Wight and Brian Porter). London: Leicester University Press.
Part II
The agency–structure
problemâ•›.â•›.â•›.
3 Agency, structure, international
relations and foreign policy
Colin Wight
Introduction
Discussions of the agent–structure problem (ASP) in International Relations (IR)
invariably begin with Alexander Wendt’s 1987 piece on the issue.
There is some justification to this, and although scholars prior to Wendt’s
seminal article had addressed the issue, it is Wendt who most clearly states the
problem and gives it a form of enduring resonance to IR theorists. Since the publication of Wendt’s article a small cottage industry surrounding the ASP has
�developed and it is rare to find a theoretical piece that does not make at least a
passing reference to it. Hence it is not surprising that the debate has seeped into
all areas of the field, including of course, foreign policy analysis. Yet despite the
prominence of Wendt’s structurationist approach to the issue his solution is not
without its problems, particularly the commitment to the ‘mutually constitutive’
nature of the agent–structure relationship; a position that has become something
of a leitmotif for most non-�rationalist approaches when addressing the issue. The
problem with ‘mutually constitutive’ is that it seems to say everything and
nothing. Moreover, it is not clear how such a relationship can be specified and
unpacked in empirical research and as such, the methodological issues surrounding a structurationist ontology have yet to be fully explored.
One notable exception to this neglect of the methodological dimensions is
Walter Carlsnaes’ excellent 1992 piece on the subject: The Agency–Structure
Problem in Foreign Policy Analysis. Anthony Giddens, who developed the
structurationist model at the heart of Wendt’s treatment of the issue, said little
about the methodological implications of his approach, other than that at some
point one would have to ‘methodologically bracket’ either agents or structures in
order to get research underway (Giddens 1984). But the choice of which (agents
or structures) forms the starting point is left to the preferences of the individual
researcher. Those of a more structuralist persuasion would inevitably begin with
structures; those more inclined towards agential accounts would begin with
agency. A related problem concerns how we interpret the ‘mutual’ aspect of
mutually constitutive. Do both agents and structures play an equal role in the
production of all outcomes, or might the complex interplay of both vary over
time and space? Again, Wendt provides little guidance on this issue, although
32╇╇ C. Wight
my view is that this is primarily an empirical question, since it is possible to conceive of social structural complexes that provide little room for the exercise of
agency, or those that facilitate increased agential possibilities (Wight 2006:
99–102). And of course, in terms of any form of emancipatory politics understanding these differences is essential.1
My aim in this chapter is to engage with Carlsnaes’ important discussion of
the agent–structure problem in relation to foreign policy analysis and explore his
use of Margaret Archer’s (1985, 1990, 1995) morphogenetic framework as a
means of reintroducing time into the agent–structure relationship. However, the
reintroduction of time, whilst important, is only one aspect of Carlsanes’
approach to the problem and he innovatively uses the agent–structure problem in
three interrelated ways: first, through the introduction of Archer’s morphogenetic
approach he provides a methodological counterpoint to Wendt’s more ontologically orientated approach; second, as an organising device to understand the
various ways of addressing foreign policy in IR, thus providing a useful resource
aimed at generating a dialogue among differing approaches; and third, as a way
of problematising any easy separation between foreign policy and IR. In this
chapter, I will briefly examine how these three aspects of the problem relate to
one another, and then suggest a reformulation of the levels-�of-analysis issue that
can help strengthen Carlsnaes’ approach to all three of these issues.
Carlsnaes and the agent–structure problem
Although it is possible to read the agent–structure problem back into almost any
theoretical approach, it is Alexander Wendt who takes the problem and gives it
an explicit form and salience relevant to IR. The starting point for Wendt was, of
course, Kenneth Waltz’s development of structural realism in 1979. In many
respects, Wendt picked up on Richard Ashley’s (1984) deep critique (itself
largely a development of E.P. Thompson’s (1978) critique of Althusser) of
Waltz’s structuralism and using resources drawn from social theory developed
an alternative ‘structurationist’ model. Over time, Wendt’s model of the
Â�agent–structure relationship has changed from one of ‘mutual-Â�constitution’ to
‘supervienence’ (Wendt 1999: 155). However, the difference between a
‘mutually-Â�constitutive’ relationship and a ‘supervenient’ one is not clear, and
both imply that a change in one element must necessitate a change in the other.
Hence despite this terminological change Wendt’s model of the agent–structure
relationship seems remarkably resilient.
According to Wendt, any solution to the agent–structure problem must begin
with a meta-�theoretical specification of the relationship between agents and
structures that avoids the reduction of one to the other. A conception that can
allow, ‘that the capacities and even existence of human agents are in some way
necessarily related to a social structural context – that they are inseparable from
human sociality’ (Wendt 1987: 355). Rejecting individualist and structuralist
accounts of social inquiry, Wendt’s chosen meta-Â�theoretical stance is that of
Giddens’ structuration theory underpinned by scientific realist philosophy of
Agency, structure, IR and foreign policy╇╇ 33
science. Structuration theory is ‘a conceptual framework or meta-Â�theory for
thinking about real world social systems’ (Wendt 1987: 355). Such an approach,
argues Wendt, ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›tries to avoid what I shall argue are the negative consequences
of individualism and structuralism by giving agents and structures equal ontological status’ (Wendt 1987: 339). Structuration theory then presents us with a
radically different social ontology from that articulated in individualist or structuralist accounts because as Wendt puts it, ‘this conceptualisation forces us to
rethink the fundamental properties of (state) agents and system structures’
(ibid.).
The idea of ‘rethinking the fundamental properties’ of the constitutive elements of the relationship makes it clear that Wendt sees the ASP as primarily
ontological in form. In terms of methodology he suggests that the consequence
of adopting a structurationist ontology, and giving equal ontological status to
both agents and structures, will necessarily involve two differing but complementary forms of explanation. The first is a question of ‘how is action X possible?’ the second ‘Why did X happen rather than Y?’ ‘How’ questions are
concerned with what could happen (the possible), whereas ‘Why’ questions are
concerned with what does happen (the actual). ‘How’ questions are essentially
structural in form; ‘Why’ questions historical; Structural analysis explains the
possible; Historical analysis explains the actual (Wendt 1987: 363). These different kinds of question can also be linked to Wendt’s understanding of the difference between constitutive (structural) and explanatory (historical) theory
(Wendt 1998).
Although Wendt wants to preserve the distinctions between structural and
historical explanations, he believes not only that they can, but that they must, be
combined in any adequate social theory. This combination is to be effected
through what Wendt calls ‘structural-Â�historical’ or ‘dialectical’ analysis. The
method by which ‘structural-Â�historical’ analysis advances is to ‘bracket-Â�off↜’ first
one mode and then the other, ‘that is, taking social structures and agents in turn
as temporarily given in order to examine the explanatory effects of the other’
(Wendt 1987: 364–365). Hence for Wendt, the methodological issues are derived
from the ontological ones. ‘Bracketing’ is only necessary if both agents and
structures are be theorised in one account.
Carslnaes’ (1992) contribution to the agent–structure debate is predicated not
only on his dissatisfaction with both the conventional individualist and structuralist accounts but also with the solution proposed by Wendt, and his belief that a
comprehensive understanding of the problem can be of major benefit to foreign
policy analysis. Like Wendt, Carlsnaes warns against simplistic solutions that
give primacy to either agents or structures. However, Carlsnaes also draws an
explicit link to the issue of naturalism (the question of whether the social sciences can be considered to be sciences in the same manner as the natural sciences) and rejects those approaches that adhere to either strict explanatory or
interpretive accounts. Thus Carlsnaes explicitly rejects the Martin Hollis and
Steve Smith argument that ‘explanation’ and ‘understanding’ are two irreconcilable approaches to the study of social phenomena (Carlsnaes 2002: 342). Unlike
34╇╇ C. Wight
Wendt, however, Carlsnaes does not turn to Giddens as an answer to the issue
because, as he suggests, Wendt ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›is proposing a starting point that at least
Giddens’ conceptualisation of structuration theory arguably cannot accommodate’ (Carlsnaes 1992: 258). Carlsnaes’ position on this is derived from Margaret Archer, who had argued that Giddens’ ‘central conflation’, or concept of
‘duality’, precludes the possibility of analysing the empirical interplay between
agents and structure over time. In short, ‘central conflation’ rules out the possibility of conducting the kind of ‘historical analysis’ suggested by Wendt,
because such a conflation is unable to incorporate the ‘dynamic interplay’
between agents and structures over time. Giddens, argues Carlsnaes:
cannot incorporate the notion – quintessentially historical – that structure
and action work on different time intervals .â•›.â•›. Giddens’s conception of
duality is crucial here .â•›.â•›. his use of this notion leads him to preclude the
possibility of analyzing the empirical interplay between action and structure,
since the notions of action and structure ontologically presuppose each other
.â•›.â•›. [and] the problem with collapsing action into structure and structure into
action a la Giddens – of giving neither explanatory autonomy – is that it
precludes a realistic possibility of conducting historical analyses along the
lines proposed by Wendt.
(1992: 258)
Carlsnaes attempts to move beyond this impasse and provide a methodological
framework that can account for the ‘dynamic synthesis of structural and agential
factors in the explanation of change’ (ibid.: 247). Whilst there are clear similarities between Archer’s approach and that of Giddens, she suggests that there is a
crucial difference. As she puts it, ‘where they [morphogenesis and structuration
theory] differ profoundly is in how they conceptualise .â•›.â•›. the structuring (and
restructuring) of social systems’ (Archer 1990: 74). For Archer, what is missing
from the ‘structurationist’, approach is the ability to incorporate the distinction
between synchronic and diachronic structural and agential effects and/or influences (1985, 1990, 1995).
Morphogenesis denotes both the inner and outer form of a ‘thing’ or structure
and also a process or developmental aspect of that same ‘thing’ or structure.
Hence, claims Archer, ‘morphogenesis is also a process, referring to the complex
interchanges that produce change in a system’s given form, structure or state’
(Archer 1990: 75). Such an approach allows for the introduction of an end
product, ‘structural elaboration’, which differs from Giddens’ notion of a ‘visible
pattern’. For Giddens, these ‘visible patterns’ can best be analysed as recurrent
social practices and have, at best, a ‘virtual status’, whereas Archer’s ‘elaborated
structure’ has properties which cannot be reduced to practices alone. Archer’s
point is that ‘analytical dualisms’ cannot simply, and programmatically, be
replaced by a ‘duality’, insofar as socio-Â�cultural systems imply discontinuity
between initial interactions and their product – the elaborated structure, or
complex system. Hence, the dualisms – voluntarism and determinism, synchrony
Agency, structure, IR and foreign policy╇╇ 35
and diachrony, individual and society – Giddens is keen to overcome, are essential elements of social practice and must be theorised.
Following Archer, Carlsnaes, suggests that explanations of foreign policy
should proceed on the basis of ‘morphogenetic cycles’, which can be analytically broken down into intervals in order to penetrate the dynamic interplay, or
relations, between structure and action over time. In this perspective, actions are
not only causally affected by structures, but subsequently affect them; indicating
a mutually dynamic relationship between the two over time. Such an approach,
he concludes, accommodates an institutional qua structural perspective towards
foreign policy analysis, whilst at the same time incorporating an interpretive epistemology (Carlsnaes 1992: 267).2 Indeed, Carlsnaes suggests that this approach
allows him to combine ‘explanation’ and ‘understanding’ and as such it should
be viewed ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›as an attempt to not only resolve the agency–structure issue’ but
also a means of providing a ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›metatheoretical foundation for such a methodological reorientation of the field’ (ibid.). This is an ambitious set of claims, but
one that is not, I think, without merit. What is important to note here is the
explicit acknowledgment by Carlsnaes that the ontological problem of object
conceptualisation needs to be separated from the methodological problem of
how to study this reconceptualised object.
Whilst intuitively a plausible solution to the methodological issue, and one I
have advocated myself, Carlsnaes’ use of Archer’s framework is not without its
problems. Most importantly are questions surrounding the underlying ontology
that grounds morphogenesis. For if it is the case that Giddens’ structuration
theory cannot accommodate the historical dimension advocated by Wendt, then
what is the underlying ontology that makes it possible? When Archer initially
developed her morphogentic approach she claimed that a realist ontology was
not a requirement for morphogenesis. Her position on this has now radically
changed and she has come to see the necessity, not only of a realist social ontology, but also a realist meta-Â�theoretical framework and metaphysics for morphogenesis.3 To this end, Archer has tied morphogenesis specifically to Bhaskar’s
account of social science and attempted to disentangle Bhaskar’s resolution of
the agent–structure problem from that Giddens proposed. In effect, Archer now
sees Bhaskar’s model of society – the TMSA (Transformational Model of Social
Activity) – as a complex social ontology to which is to be wedded to ‘morphogenesis’ as an explanatory social methodology (Archer 1995: 15–16).
Of course, writing in 1992 Carlsnaes could not have been expected to anticipate this development in Archer’s thinking given that it only became clear to
Archer in 1995. And in many respects he could legitimately claim to have realised this before Archer, since he does at times suggest his work is underpinned
by a commitment to scientific realism (Carlsnaes 1992). Nonetheless, without an
appropriate reconsideration of an alternative ontology to that proposed by
Giddens it is not clear how morphogenesis can be put into practice. This issue
becomes most apparent in Carlsnaes’ treatment of agency. Given his commitment to incorporating elements of an interpretive approach into his framework it
is important that Carlsnaes has a robust account of agency such that beliefs and
36╇╇ C. Wight
intentions can be allotted a fundamental role. However, despite claiming that his
ambition ‘is to put forward a framework for analyzing foreign policy actions in
terms of a dynamic account of the ways in which such actions are continually
being constrained and enabled by contextually defined structures, and how these
in turn are affected by human agency’ (ibid.: 263), he often uses agency to refer
to collective social forms, such as the state. Such a move from human agency to
social agency might be admissible, but it would require substantial theorising.
Wendt recognised this problem and came to argue that states possess the same
properties as human individuals; ‘states are people too’ (Wendt 1999: 215–223).
It is not clear in Carlsnaes’ treatment of the issue if he would agree with Wendt
on this or not.
Foreign policy vs international politics
The issue of agency is fundamental to Carlsnaes’ understanding of foreign policy
analysis. He is adamant that foreign policy belongs in the academic domain of
International Relations rather than the policy sciences (Carlsnaes 2002: 331).
Moreover, he rejects the view that international politics and foreign policy analysis
are two distinct realms of inquiry (ibid.: 332). The idea that international politics
and foreign policy are separate realms of inquiry is most forcefully articulated by
Kenneth Waltz (1996), although it also accepted by Wendt (1999:€11). According
to Carlsnaes, the source of this separation of the two domains is the move towards
systemic theories that occurred after Waltz published his Theory of International
Politics (Carlsnaes 2002: 332). Foreign policy suffered in this structuralist environment because its focus is more on unit level factors driving state behaviour than
the system forces advocated by Waltz. Yet, he argues, that following the end of the
Cold War there has been a move towards a view of international politics more in
line with the basic presuppositions of foreign policy (ibid.).
Waltz (1996) had identified five main reasons why a theory of international
politics is not and cannot be a theory of foreign policy. The most important of
these in relation to Carlsnaes’ position is Waltz’s deep critique of reductionism.
IR theory, as Waltz, understands it should be based primarily at the level of the
system. As such, systemic theories explain similarities in the behaviour of states,
despite varying individual or unit-�level properties. Foreign policy, on the other
hand relies on unit-�level differences among states to explain why they pursue
different foreign policies, despite similar structural positions. When viewed from
the perspective of the agent–structure problem however, this distinction seems
problematic. It is a distinction that only makes sense if a strong structuralist
ontology can be defended. Carlsnaes, of course, rejects this structuralist position
and embraces an ontology that attempts to give both agents and structures due
weight in terms of explanatory power. Hence for Carlsnaes, and as a direct result
of his position on the agent structure problem, foreign policy and international
politics cannot be separated in any easy manner. Indeed, although not explicitly
stated, it must be the case that Carlsnaes would agree with James Fearon who
claims:
Agency, structure, IR and foreign policy╇╇ 37
There is a straightforward and important sense in which neorealist and other
systemic theories are indeed theories of foreign policy. Namely, the things
that structural realist theory seeks to explain, such as balancing, the prob�
ability of major power war, or a general disposition to competitive interstate
relations are either foreign policies or the direct (if sometimes unintended)
result of foreign policies. .â•›.â•›. In this natural sense, then, systemic and neorealist theories emphatically are theories of foreign policy.
(1998: 292–293)
Yet this position has implications for any account of the unit-�level factors that
might help explain foreign policy, and when allied to Carlsanes’ claim to
embrace elements of an interpretive epistemology it will require some theoretical location where intentions, beliefs and motivations can be specified. To my
mind, this can only logically be achieved at the level of human agents, albeit
agents deeply embedded within and constituted by the structural contexts they
inhabit. Or, as Carlsnaes himself puts it, ‘action is always a combination of purposive behaviour, cognitive-Â�psychological factors and the various structural phenomena characterising societies and their environments’ (2002: 342).
From levels-�of-analysis to foreign policy
One barrier to such an integrated approach within IR, however, is the level of
analysis problem, which is clearly closely related to the ASP. Indeed, at one
point during the debate with Hollis and Smith on the ASP Wendt complains that
Hollis and Smith ‘reduce the agent–structure problem to one of the levels of
analysis’ (Wendt 1992: 181). Carlsnaes’ position on this issue is interesting
because it seems that he can only be advocating a position on the level-�ofanalysis issue that is very similar to my own; although admittedly he has not
articulated this explicitly. In short, I believe Carlsnaes’ position on the agent–
structure problem, when combined with his commitment to elements of an interpretive epistemology, and his view of foreign policy, require a fundamental
reconfiguration of the levels-�of-analysis issue along the lines indicated in my
book Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology
(2006).
There is no doubt that thinking about IR in terms of levels is deeply ingrained
in the disciplinary psyche. David Singer’s (1961) influential piece on this issue is
rightly considered a landmark in the theoretical development of the discipline.4
According to R.B.J. Walker, this way of thinking about the discipline is ‘all pervasive’ (1993: 131). Moreover, for Walker all talk of levels may be seriously misleading since it implies a vertical ordering of the relations between individuals,
states and system, whereas these might be better grasped as horizontal relationships (ibid.: 134). I think, however, that it is possible to defend a vertical yet non-�
hierarchical (in the sense of an a priori privileging of one level over another)
account of levels whilst accepting and expanding on Walker’s horizontal point. In
effect, the image we need is one of vertical levels spread horizontally.
38╇╇ C. Wight
Singer takes the behaviour of states as his unit-�of-analysis and posits two
levels at which explanation of this unit might be based; that of the international
system and of the nation state itself. Although Singer suggests only two levels
his discussion opens up the possibility of a third level below that of the nation
state; that of individuals. Singer’s recognition of a level-Â�of-explanation below
that of the nation state is predicated on an unthematised social ontology; a social
ontology within which Singer can view individuals as only fulfilling roles
defined in terms of state interests. Thus, in an argument that is similar Wendt’s
treatment of the state, Singer can argue that ‘nations may be said to be goal-Â�
seeking organisms which exhibit purposive behaviour’ (Singer1961: 84–85).
Insofar as individuals feature in this approach they can be considered as state
agents who resemble ‘cultural dopes’ fulfilling predefined roles in the maintenance of national interests. This is not a position Carlsnaes can embrace given
his position on the agent–structure problem.
Although Singer only posited two levels, most treatments of the level-Â�ofanalysis problem on the discipline follow Waltz’s three level typology and add
extra levels as required (Waltz 1959). Hollis and Smith (1990: 197) provide a
good example of how the discipline typically conceives of these levels (see
Figure 3.1).
On this treatment of the level-�of-analysis problem, the levels are related as
agents to structures, hence Wendt’s argument that they were conflating the two
problems is generally sound. This formulation of the issue forces/allows the relocation of agency at every move up or down the levels, so that what appears as a
structure on one level becomes an agent on another. Hence, at what Hollis and
Smith call the first debate, the international system plays the role of structure
with the nation state as an agent. At the level of the second debate, the nation
state appears as a structure with the role of agent now played by bureaucracies.
Individuals only appear on this model at the level of the third debate, where
bureaucracies now constitute the structure and individuals play the role of
agents. What appears as a structure at one level becomes an agent at another
level.
International system
Level of analysis: first debate
vs
Nation-state
Level of analysis: second debate
vs
Bureaucracy
Level of analysis: third debate
vs
Individual
Figure 3.1╇ The dominant view of levels in IR.
Agency, structure, IR and foreign policy╇╇ 39
Underlying this account is a particular view of what it means to be an agent;
an account of agency that is, that can allow that properties and powers attributed
to one theoretical entity can be attributed to others. This treatment of the level-�
of-analysis problem takes the relocation of agency as unproblematic and it
cannot be consistent with Carlsnaes’ position on the agent–structure problem.
Hence a reconfigured position on the agent–structure problem will require a
rethinking of the issue of levels.
Nicholas Onuf (1989) has suggested that we treat the levels identified by
Singer as ‘levels-Â�of-being’ that require further disaggregating into their component parts (Figure 3.2 should help clarify what I mean here).
The first thing to note is that a reformulation of the issue invites us to ask:
‘levels of what?’ Figure 3.2 relates to levels of political organisation, but could
be amended to cover other aspects of the social field; legal, economic, social and
cultural for example. In each of these examples the form, number and type of the
levels may differ since there is no need to assume that one levels scheme fits all.
Notice also, that on this understanding of levels there is no need for a distinct
individual level beneath that of the state since individuals feature in every level
and are tied into their social contexts. The location of individuals at every level
is important since it highlights the fact that it is through the differing ‘positioning’ of individuals that the various levels interact. In effect, this way of thinking
of the issue links micro and macro phenomena.
The levels indicated here are merely suggestive and they should not be understood as an exhaustive typology. The components included in the levels are
derived from categories developed by Derek Layder (1994) and are likewise
merely meant to be suggestive. What is important to convey is the idea that each
and every level includes individuals and some account of their various structural
contexts; but also the manner in which these structural contexts are dynamic and
interact with each other. Structural contexts are ‘products-Â�in-process’ as well as
‘processes-Â�in-production’.
International/global
Context
Setting
Situated activity
Self/agent
Nation-state
Context
Setting
Situated activity
Self/agent
Bureaucracies
Context
Setting
Situated activity
Self/agent
Figure 3.2╇ An alternative conceptualisation of levels in IR.
40╇╇ C. Wight
Equally, researchers should feel free to focus their attention on any particular
component. As with all such synoptic devices when it comes to their application
in concrete research it is a matter of emphasis as to which element has the
primary focus. Moreover, it needs to be stressed that the elements of this diagrammatic representation of the realm of international relations shade into and
interweave with each other; or what Heikki Patomäki’s refers to as ‘interpenetration’ (1996). This is an important point, for although it may be necessary to give
more emphasis to one element, it is vital to understand that they are all bound
together in the ongoing flux of social life; hence the pictorial demonstration of a
context that all levels share in common. In this respect, part of the context for
each of the levels is the other levels. The point is that this kind of selective
focusing of research should be seen as deliberate and selective and related to the
research question and not as a result of an a priori theoretical tendency to see one
aspect as more important than any other.
The self, or agent, seems self-�evident but must be treated with care. Of
course, selves cannot easily be separated from the social situations in which they
are routinely embedded and researchers will have hard decisions to make about
which aspects of agency to privilege. The powers of human agents to act in the
world are derived more from their social positioning than any biological factors
they may possess; hence social positionality is internally related to agency. Even
though agents are always structurally embedded it is important to distinguish
between differing levels of agency since it helps direct attention to the way individuals are empowered, respond to, and are affected by, their social involvements. The notion of self, then, refers to an individual’s sense of identity,
personality and perception of the social world as these things are experienced
and/or influenced by her, or his, social experience. Selves, however, are ongoing
social constructions and we should reject extreme psychological explanations
that view the individual as a separate unit possessing a fixed inner core or
essence; the human self is socially constitued.
Situated activity shifts the focus away from a concern with the individual’s
response to various kinds of social situations towards a concern with the dynamics of interaction itself. Such a focus on the dynamics of interaction directs our
attention to the manner in which gatherings of, or encounters between, several
individuals can tend to produce outcomes and properties that are a result of the
interchange of communication between the group as whole rather than the behaviour of the individuals viewed singly. That is to say, situated activity displays
emergent properties that are the result of the way in which individuals interact
and coalesce and which could never have been predicted through an analysis of
the individuals themselves. Thus, there are two aspects of situated activity: first,
the involvement of the individuals concerned is such that each occurrence of
similar activity will bear the unique imprint of the particular configuration of
individuals involved; and, second, the ongoing dynamic nature of the interactional process itself reacts back upon those individuals in unforeseen ways. Thus,
for example, a group of diplomats coming together to discuss a particular issue
can develop a group identity which helps facilitate, or impede, the outcome of
Agency, structure, IR and foreign policy╇╇ 41
the deliberation. A change in membership of the group might dramatically alter
the dynamics of the group, but equally if the group identity has become deeply
embedded it may be the case that small changes in membership have little or no
effect on the group.
Setting highlights the manner in way the nature of the setting within which
situated activity takes place will make a difference to the manner in which those
individuals interact. The incorporation of the setting of situated activity highlights the impossibility of writing out the materiality of the social world or the
reduction of it to a dependent variable. A good example of the role of setting in
producing outcomes might be that of the Reagan/Gorbachev fireside summit in
Geneva 1985. But consider also, the difference between a one-�off encounter
between diplomatic colleagues in a formal meeting and the interaction between
those same colleagues in a social setting such as a restaurant. In both examples,
the kind of setting in which such interaction takes place is significant to the
activity itself. In this respect, certain activities vary according to the extent to
which they tend to be limited to specific settings and specific individuals. Thus,
the setting has a set of properties that cannot be reduced to little more than particular patterns of activity. Settings, that is, have a set of properties that are identifiable apart from specific instances of situated activity. However, it is important
to stress that these properties are dependent on the more general activities that
constitute the setting in the first place and thus setting is linked to context.
Context highlights the manner in which selves, situated activity and settings
exist within a structurally organised context. For example, the concept of a diplomatic exchange presupposes that there is a larger organisational context that
makes diplomatic exchange possible. Moreover, we also assume that this structure would persist irrespective of those particular participants and their specific
routines and rituals. That is to say, that if two diplomats, or state leaders, retire,
it may be the case that certain routines and rituals might disappear along with
them (although perhaps to be replaced by other state leaders who replace them).
However, it would also be true to say that organisational structure of the state
system remains despite a change in personnel.
Whilst settings and situated activity are always and only sustained insofar as
they are reproduced and/or transformed by the social activities of agents, from
the point of view of specific participants entering these settings, they are experienced as already established forms of organisation, with which they have to
contend in various ways. Moreover, all social reproduction and/or transformation takes place under conditions inherited from the past; in effect the logic of
morphogenesis. These conditions represent the already established quality of
social forms that have been reproduced and/or transformed in the past and which
confront new generations of individuals as objective structural contexts which
reward certain forms of behaviour and punish others. As such, these structural
contexts entail historically embedded forms of power and authority that decisively influence social activity in these settings and contexts.
Context, as was the case with self, situated activity and setting has to be
viewed as a stratified concept, thus there are many contextual layers. The
42╇╇ C. Wight
�
gendered
nature of state occupations, such as the army, for example, has to be
seen in the wider context of gender social relations that locate women in certain
kinds of occupation. Moreover, as this example makes clear, the question
becomes not one of how to integrate agents and structures into one coherent
account, but of how it could ever be possible to consider methodological individualism, or methodological structuralism as viable alternatives. That is, that at
certain junctures, it becomes difficult, if not impossible, to separate out the
effects of the immediate setting and the more macro variables such as patriarchal
power relations, or class relations. Similarly, it is impossible to understand the
way in which these wider, macro structures are reproduced over time unless we
understand how more micro processes feed into them. In this sense, macro pro�
cesses feed into activity and in some way make it possible, while the micro
activity itself reproduces these wider social relations.
In general terms, thinking of the levels in this disaggregated manner will help
facilitate research that aims to integrate agents and structures in a manner that is
consistent with Carlsnaes’ treatment of the issue. Equally, the reformulated
levels-�of-analysis problem highlights the erroneous nature of exclusively structural approaches to research that tend to deny or undervalue the importance of
agential attributes and the interpretative element of all social analysis. In this
regard, structural phenomena make no sense unless they are related to the social
activities of individuals who reproduce them over time. Conversely, agential
phenomena cannot be fully understood by exclusive reference to their internal
dynamics; they have to be seen as conditioned by circumstances inherited from
the past, as well as driven by beliefs about potential futures.
In other words, agential actions have to be understood in relation to the influence of the structural contexts and settings that provide the wider social context
and vice versa as well as in terms of the unfolding structural dynamic that occurs
as interaction takes place. Thus, agential and structural contexts are inextricably
bound together through the medium of social activity. Moreover, this reconfigured approach to the levels-�of-analysis issue avoids the any notion of reification
that often accompanies structural theorising. As I have described them structural
phenomena are clearly the outcome of human activity and hence the fear of reification is unwarranted and exaggerated.
Conclusion
Walter Carlsnaes’ contribution to the agent–structure debate is a valuable methodological corrective to the way the issue has been debated thus far. His
approach is a sophisticated attempt to provide a methodological counterpoint to
the ontological framing of the issue. In going back over these issues however, I
have come to recognise something else about Carlsnaes’ approach that I had previously missed. Underpinning all his work in this area is a deep commitment to
theoretical and methodological pluralism and a willingness to ensure that those
working in IR, and foreign policy, engage in a sincere attempt to understand and
take seriously alternative positions. This, I think underpins all his work. He
Agency, structure, IR and foreign policy╇╇ 43
rejects purely individualist or structuralist accounts of social inquiry in favour of
an account of the agent–structure relationship that sees both related in an
�on-�going dynamic social process. He also rejects any attempt to set interpretive
and explanatory approaches as somehow opposed. And he likewise rejects any
attempt to compartmentalise the discipline into separate areas with few links
between them. In this respect Carlsnaes is an eclectic and synthesising thinker.
Some might find this problematic. I think it should be admired and encouraged.
Notes
1 Insofar as social contexts enable some outcomes and constrain others, there are always
going to be limits to the forms that emancipation can take. Thus emancipation can only
be understood as the transition from an unwanted, unnecessary and oppressive situation
to a wanted and/or needed situation (Bhaskar 1989: 6). This puts knowledge, and in
particular social scientific knowledge at the heart of any form of emancipatory politics.
2 I am using the term ‘epistemology’ here because it is Carlsnaes’ chosen term and one
that resonates in the discipline. However, my own view is that interpretivism is more
correctly understood as a methodology (see Wight 2006: 255–289).
3 Archer argues,
if the adoption of a realist ontology is the litmus test, I leave it to the reader to
apply it to the theory of structuration. It is not really a palm coveted by the morphogenetic perspective, which is based on neo-�Kantian rationalist foundations.
(1990: 88)
Her recognition of the need for a realist social ontology and metaphysical framework
forms the rationale behind most of her realist inspired work (Archer 1995, 2000).
4 This typology is normally attributed to Singer (1961), although Singer derived his
account largely from Waltz (1959).
References
Archer, Margaret (1985). Structuration versus morphogenesis. British Journal of Sociology, 33(4), 455–483.
Archer, Margaret (1990). Human agency and social structure: A critique of Giddens. In
Margaret S. Archer (ed.), Realist social theory: The Morphogenetic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ashley, Richard. (1984) The poverty of neorealism. International Organization, 38(2),
225–286.
Bhaskar, Roy (1986). Scientific realism and human emancipation. London: Verso.
Bhaskar, Roy (1989). Reclaiming reality: A critical introduction to contemporary philosophy. London: Verso.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agent–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36(3), 245–270.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2002). Foreign policy. In W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse-�Kappen and B.A.
Simmons (eds), Handbook of International Relations (pp. 331–349). London; Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Clark, Jon, Modgil, Celia and Modgil, Sohan (eds) (1990) Anthony Giddens: Consensus
and controversy. Basingstoke: Falmer Press.
Fearon, James D. (1998). Domestic politics, foreign policy, and theories of international
relations. Annual Review of Political Science, 1(1), 289–313.
44╇╇ C. Wight
Hollis, Martin, and Smith, Steve (1990). Explaining and understanding international
relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Giddens, Anthony (1984). The constitution of society. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Layder, Derek (1994). Understanding social theory. London: Sage.
Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood (1989). World of our making: Rules and rule in social theory
and international relations. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.
Patomäki, Heikki (1996). How to tell better stories about world politics. European
Journal of International Relations, 2(1), 105-133.
Singer, J. David. (1961). The level-�of-analysis problem in international relations. In K.
Knorr and S. Verba (eds), The international system: Theoretical essays (pp.€ 77–92).
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Thompson, Edward P. (1978). The poverty of theory and other essays. London: Merlin
Press.
Walker, R.B.J. (1993). Inside/Outside: International Relations as political theory. Cambridge Studies in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1959). Man the state and war: A theoretical analysis. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Waltz, Kenneth (1979). Theory of International Politics. Reading, MA: Addison-�Wesley.
Waltz, Kenneth. (1996). International politics is not foreign policy. Security Studies, 6,
54–57.
Wendt, Alexander E. (1987). The agent–structure problem in International Relations
theory. International Organization, 41(3), 335–370.
Wendt, Alexander (1992). Anarchy is what states make of it: The social construction of
power politics. International Organization, 46(2), 391–425.
Wendt, Alexander E. (1998). On constitution and causation in international relations.
Review of International Studies, 24(Special Issue), 101–117.
Wendt, Alexander E. (1999). Social theory of international politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wight, Colin (2006). Agents, structures and international relations: Politics as ontology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
4 Agency, structures and time
From atemporal ontologies to explicit
geo-�historical hypotheses and
anticipation of global democracy
Heikki Patomäki
Introduction
Following Richard Ashley’s (1984) and Alexander Wendt’s (1987) seminal contributions, Walter Carlsnaes helped to awaken IR theory from its dogmatic
slumber and redirect scholars’ attention to a critical issue in the philosophy of
social sciences: what is the relationship between agency and structures? In a
series of papers, Carlsnaes (1992, 1993, 1994) discusses the agency–structure
problematic in the context of foreign policy analysis. Carlsnaes’ intent to enrich
foreign policy analysis through explicating a plausible social ontology (in line
with Giddens 1979 and Archer 1985), he (Carlsnaes 1993: 13) talks about the
‘interplay over time which exists between agency and structure’. He argues that
decision-�makers make choices and, through their actions, take part in the�
(re)production of structures the results of which, in turn, enable and constrain
their subsequent actions. Furthermore, Carlsnaes stresses the importance of historical time for understanding foreign policy: ‘since neither structures nor actors
remain constant over time, a social theory worth its salt must be able to account
not only for particular changes but also for social change itself as an inherently
dynamic phenomenon’ (1992: 246).
In this chapter, I explore further the temporality of agency and structures.
Carlsnaes’ Giddensian and Archerian social ontology presupposes that actors are
self-�consciously knowledgeable social beings producing and reproducing society
on the basis of practical reason. I agree with this assumption. However, we
should not take knowledgeable and capable actors as given but study the geo-�
historical conditions for their existence. It is possible to gain new insights into
the nature and transformative possibilities of agency and structures by asking
this deceptively simple question: when and how did the powers and liabilities
now associated with agency emerge?
Evidence suggests that the capacity to reflect upon and choose self-�
consciously between alternative courses of action, by means of complex metaphors of time and self, developed alongside with complex society. This process
can be best understood as collective learning. There is no reason to assume that
human learning would have come to an end. Learning is an on-�going process.
By studying the logic of collective learning, it is possible to anticipate future
46╇╇ H. Patomäki
forms of agency, power and authority in world politics. I conclude by outlining a
few hypotheses about possible and likely planetary transformations of social
beings and relations in the course of the twenty-�first century, and beyond.
Historicising social ontology
Giddens (1979: 64) defines structures as ‘structural properties [.â•›.â•›.â•›which] can be
understood as rules and resources’. He recognises the existence of: (i) knowledge – as memory traces – of ‘how things are to be done’ on the part of social
actors (i.e. actors must be competent); (ii) social (and positioned) practices
organised through the recursive mobilisation of that knowledge; and (iii) the
transformative capabilities, i.e. power, that the production of those practices presupposes. Although Archer (1985; see also 1995) criticises Giddens for conflating agents and structures, her morphogenetic approach, too, presupposes
knowledgeable and competent actors. Carlsnaes draws on these two approaches
and applies them to foreign policy analysis. In a parallel manner, I have
(Patomäki 1991, 1996, 2002) specified the essential components of social world
by developing the notion of causal complex, involving
1
2
3
4
5
historically constructed and positioned corporeal actors (AR);
meaningful, historically structured, and reasoned actions (AN);
regulative and constitutive rules implicated in every action and constitution
of actors (RU);
resources as competencies and facilities (RE); and
relational and positioned practices (PRA).
Causal complex K = {AR, RU, RE, PRA, AN} is an internally and externally
related and open-�systemic whole. However, a key problem with all these conceptualisations of agency structures is that while the substance of the elements is
understood as historical, the historicity of the elements themselves is left at least
partly implicit. This is true even when it is acknowledged that in order to grasp
thoroughly the relationship between action and structures it is not possible to
stay at a metaâ•‚level. ‘No general, transhistorical or purely philosophical resolution of these problems is possible’ (Bhaskar 1983: 87). Modes of social agency
and types of action are historically generated. However, where do the competent,
knowledgeable, rule-�following but also improvising actors, who have the self-�
reflective capacity to do otherwise, come from? Are these capacities universal
human powers, part of our species-�being?
Precisely what kinds of powers do social agency and actions presuppose?
First, actors must be capable of assuming causal, moral and legal responsibility
for their actions. In order to take responsibility and to be knowingly able to act
otherwise, there must be reflective consciousness capable of remembering and
interpreting the past and anticipating the future. Second, the power to reflect
upon non-�actual action possibilities implies that actors are capable of thinking
abstractly, i.e. that they can reason in terms of complex metaphors (cf. Lakoff
Agency, structures and time╇╇ 47
and Johnson 1999). Third, with the help of metaphors, actors can imagine an ‘I’
and self that can move about within spatialised time; or they can fix their self
and see time as something that flows. Spatialised time can be linear and abstract,
rather than just cyclical and tied to repetitive natural rhythms, making future-�
oriented reflectivity possible.
When and how did these human powers (Harré and Secord 1972) emerge? In
the light of available evidence, it is striking how slowly the human genetic
potential resulted in new cultural achievements. Anatomically modern humans
first appeared in Sub-�Saharan Africa roughly 200,000 years ago. In the next
190,000 years, our African ancestors and their Eurasian, Australian and American offspring did not leave any traces of history, religion, arts, architecture,
science or philosophy. For most of this time, the way of life of homo (sapiens)
sapiens seems to have been similar to its human predecessors. It continued to
use roughly made stone weapons and tools but otherwise to live in nature, following a biologically determined way of life, with hardly any signs of cultural or
technical changes. How can we explain the gradual shift from biological to the
much more rapid cultural pace of time?
Clearly, although the genetic constitution of homo sapiens was necessary for
what was to come, it was insufficient for the rapid release of the potential for
human creativity and all those things we associate with human culture. The
process of development was slow and fragile and must have involved something
other than genes. But what else could have played a role? Julian Jaynes’ (2000;
also Kuijsten 2006) theory of the development of human consciousness provides
a plausible explanation of the gradual shift from biological to cultural time.
Jaynes’ theory is based on the systematic assessment of the available archaeological and written evidence.
Jaynes argues that the key to full human capabilities lies in the development
of language. The first humans in Africa did not have complex verbal language,
although – like other hominids before them – they could sustain various techniques and social expectations with a combination of imitation, visual images,
body language, facial expressions and oral sounds and signals. The development
of language was very slow (in terms of cultural-�historical scales of time) but
started, step by step, to accelerate.1 Each new stage of linguistic learning created
new perceptions and attentions, resulting in important cultural changes, which
are reflected in the available archaeological record. Full sentences became possible probably sometime between 25,000 and 15,000 B.C.E. The first cave paintings of animals paralleled the appearance of nouns for animals; people can
imagine and draw something for which they have a concept. The thing-�nouns
begot new things such as pottery, pendants, ornaments and barbed harpoons and
spearheads.
The new functions of language and gradual acceleration of cultural learning
also transformed the human brain – the brain is a highly connected and interconnected organ, in which connections and their activations are constantly shifting –
and thus evolved the language hemispheres in human brain. Jaynes (2000: 134)
maintains that language had important side effects. With complex oral language
48╇╇ H. Patomäki
humans can continue activities over time and concentrate on working on something; clearly a benefit for survival and likely cause of population growth among
those groups that adopted complex language. Moreover, once nouns were carried
over to names of individuals who could be remembered and thus also missed
also when they were absent and also after they had died. This cultural innovation
led to the increasingly common practice of ceremonial graves from 10,000â•›bce
onwards.
On the other hand, there was yet no subject or self that could sustain enduring
activities by conscious effort. Rather, commands and memories coming from
within the individual resembled what we would today call verbal hallucinations.
Because of the development of language, people started to hear ‘external’ voices
telling them what to do. Jaynes claims that this phenomenon also had a physiological basis. The language involved only one side of the brain in order to leave
the other side free for the language of these voices, or gods, as humans came to
think of them. The bicameral mind enabled a form of social control that made it
possible for humans to establish a complex society and move from small hunter-�
gatherer groups to large agricultural communities. Hence, with the development
of bicameral mind, agricultural civilisations became possible, although the materialisation of this possibility was a slow and contingent process (see Jaynes 2000,
Chs 4 and 5; and on the economics of early farming, Diamond 1999, 104–113).
Auditory hallucinations involved the voice of the leader of the community –
the chief or king – also in his absence, including after his death. This explains
why people treated their dead kings as if they were still living for a long period
after they died; later the decaying or mummified bodies were replaced with
functionally similar posts and statues. The resulting hierarchical civilisations
were literally built around god-�houses visible to everyone in the village or
town. This meant increased division of labour, efficiency and in effect also
population growth that was rapid when compared to earlier eras. While from
70,000–10,000â•›bce, human population had grown very slowly from perhaps
mere 20,000 to something like one million, by the year 5000â•›bce, the number of
humans had suddenly grown to five million and there were a few towns numbering a few thousand inhabitants each. In 2000â•›bce world population was
already at 27 million and major cities had emerged; for example Lagash
(80,000), Memphis (50,000), Uruk (50,000), Harappa (50,000) and Mohenjo-�
Daro (50,000).
A new level of complexity and social learning was reached. The emergent
human civilisations invented or adopted writing, money and mathematics, and
engaged in gift-�exchange, trade and wars with other communities, thus gradually
paving the way to the burst of reflective consciousness. It is around this time that
the capacity to articulate one’s own individual plans of action assumed such a
level as to make rudimentary forms of individual moral/legal responsibility possible. With the Code of Hammurabi (c.1760â•›bce) and similar codes of law in the
Near East, the general principle of justice was born as a rudimentary moral
accounting of equivalents (an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth). The emergence
of writing had far-�reaching consequences:
Agency, structures and time╇╇ 49
The [role] of writing in the breakdown of the bicameral voices is tremendously important. What had to be spoken is now silent and carved upon a
stone to be taken in visually.
(Jaynes 2000: 302)2
Reflective consciousness and all its consequences occur through language, especially through written language and metaphors, which make abstract thinking,
linear narratisation and self-�reflection possible. At the dawn of the reflective consciousness, in the early first millennium bce, bodily things such as breath, blood,
lungs, heart and head were turned into metaphors and started to denote psyche,
spirit, soul, life, emotions, intelligence and self. The repertoire of simple affects
that we share with other mammals was transformed into complex human emotions: fear became anxiety, shame was translated into guilt and mating was
turned into sex. These and many other conscious emotions were made possible
by analogues and metaphors, which were subsequently used to debate and theorise justice, goodness, morality, emotions and the meaning of human existence.
According to Jaynes (2000: 65–66; cf. Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 139–161,
235–289), metaphor generates consciousness by creating a space in which the ‘I’
can move and ‘do’ things that we are not actually doing, constructs the ‘me’ that
we can imagine and see doing things that we may or may not be actually doing;
and tell stories where the ‘I’ and ‘me’ moves in spatialised time. The spatialised
time, in which events and experiences can now be located, remembered and
anticipated, makes also social agency, morality, law and politics possibility.
Actors know that they can act otherwise and thus become reflective (even reflexive) about some of their doings. They can also learn that others may be equally
conscious beings. Once they have fully learnt this, however, it then becomes difficult to imagine a succession of thousands of generations of genetically indistinguishable human beings without consciousness in the reflective sense of the
term.
Individual and collective learning
In order to become competent and knowledgeable actors, each biological individual has to learn, in a very short period of time, many of those things that it
took such a long time for humanity as a whole to develop. In The Language and
Thought of the Child, Piaget (2002) explores how children progressively enrich
their understanding of things by acting on and reflecting on the effects of their
own previous knowledge. On the basis of their practical actions and reflective
experiences, they are capable of organising their knowledge in increasingly
complex and abstract structures. Piaget (2002: 240–241, 272–286) argues that
the sequence of cognitive stages is conceptual-�logical rather than just empirically
correct, which also explains the spontaneity of reaching higher stages in sufficiently enabling context. The child learns by engaging in imitation and playing
for their own sake, at first monologically and ego-�centrically (for Piaget, the
child’s egocentrism is an illusion of perspective that stems from the incapacity to
50╇╇ H. Patomäki
differentiate one’s self, others and external world). Communication for instru-Â�
mental reasons – for instance to get something the child wants – remains limited
and is often subsumed under magical discourse and hallucinatory experiences in
which words substitute for reality. In this sense, every child seems to go through
a phase that is reminiscent of the bicameral-�mind stage of the past civilizations.3
Gradually, with advancements towards more complex and abstract thinking,
it becomes possible for a child to assume the perspective of others and have
genuine dialogue with them. At the same time, his or her capacity to differentiate between things, categories and aspects of reality increases; and also causal
why-�questions become possible. As the child starts to communicate his or her
thoughts to other people, and listen to others, an individual person emerges from
the process of learning through actions and language (for Piaget, action usually
comes before reflective thought4), following the order of logically sequential
cognitive stages.
In his 1932 book, The Moral Judgment of the Child (1977), Piaget applies
similar ideas to moral learning. How do children form ideas about right and
wrong, and fair and unfair? According to Piaget, the essential aspect of morality
is the tendency to accept and follow a system of rules which regulate interpersonal behaviour. Piaget (ibid.: 23) studied these questions empirically and concluded that there are three major stages of the practice of rules in children’s
games such as marbles. In the egocentric stage children do not grasp or follow
the rules, but insist that they do (each plays his own parallel game even when
they play ‘together’). In the stage of incipient cooperation, mastery of the rules
has improved and rule-�following has become a practice, but as the rules are
grasped incompletely, there are often difficulties and conflicts. Finally, in the
stage of genuine cooperation and codification of rules, children not only know
the rules well but also enjoy reflecting and elaborating upon them.
The collective rule is at first something external to the individual and consequently sacred to him; then, as he gradually makes it his own, it comes to
that extent be felt as the free product of mutual agreement and an auto�
nomous conscience. And with regard to the practical use, it is only natural that
a mystical respect for laws should be accompanied by a rudimentary knowledge and application of their contents, while a rational and well-�founded
respect is accompanied by an effective application of each rule in detail.
(ibid.: 24–25)
In the earlier stages children’s moral judgements are based on the objective
external consequences of actions, independently of intentions and circumstances.
At the same time, rules are taken literally and authoritatively. With advancements towards more differentiated and cooperative thinking, children start to
understand others’ intentions and their relevance, and be capable of distinguishing the spirit or purpose of a rule from its literal meaning (ibid.: 68–69).
In the democratic Switzerland of the 1920s and 1930s, children learnt, by
the€age of 12–13, that law emanates ‘from the sovereign people and no longer
Agency, structures and time╇╇ 51
[mystically from the God or] from the tradition by the Elders’ (ibid.: 67). These
children had realised that people are autonomous and can revise their own rules
and laws; and that the purpose of rules and laws is to enable mutually enjoyable
and beneficial co-�operation and to avoid and resolve social conflicts. Piaget
(ibid.: 71, 194, 219, 257) stressed, however, that various stages of reasoning
always overlap both in individuals and society. Like older children, adults, too,
often practice lower stages moral reasoning and make underdeveloped moral
judgements, often to conform to authority and institutional expectations.
Stages of advancement?
The agency–structure problematic seems to open up the Pandora’s box of thinking about human history in terms of stages of advancement. Most social scientists and philosophers avoid explicit theorisation of collective advancement,
except in relativistic terms, or in local scales of time. Notions such as universal
moral learning, cultural evolution, and ethico-�political progress have been
widely seen as dubious at best – and potentially dangerous. Already the founders
of sociology such as Emile Durkheim, Max Weber and Edward Westermarck
tended to reduce values to culturally conditioned instinctive emotions, historical
traditions, or particular social formations. Although in practice remaining ambivalent and even positive about the moral worth of modernisation, they verged on
denying the possibility of collective ethico-�political learning.5
Anthropologists have been especially vocal in their opposition to the idea of
universal stages of moral learning, an idea they have associated with the ‘white
man’s burden’, ‘civilizing mission’ and other nineteenth-Â�century ideologies of
imperialism. The self-�inflicted horrors of the First World War degraded the
moral status of the West and made cultural and moral relativism popular among
intellectuals and, in particular, anthropologists (who were also responding to the
particular problems of the US society).6 Moreover, the ensuing catastrophes of
the twentieth century, including Stalin’s purges, deepened the sense of nihilism
among leftist social theorists especially in Europe. Theodor Adorno’s and Max
Horkheimer’s (1979) pessimistic criticism of the Enlightenment legacy; Karl
Popper’s (1960) widely read liberal attack on historicism and Marxism; and
Michel Foucault’s (1984, 2001) sceptical studies on truth, normality and power
strengthened the conviction that – as Jean-Â�Francois Lyotard (1984: 37) put it –
the grand emancipatory narrative has lost its credibility.
When pressed, few sceptics of cultural evolution or progress would deny that
the Rawlsian notion of justice (or any relevant twentieth-�century conception) is
not only more sophisticated and complex but also better than the one codified in
the Code of Hammurabi. Yet most critical social scientists and philosophers
seem reluctant to theorise collective human learning, cultural evolution and
moral progress. But there have been exceptions.
Building on Piaget’s work, as well as on Socrates, Kant and Dewey,
Â�Kohlberg’s 3â•›×â•›2 stages were first outlined in his 1958 doctoral dissertation.7
They were further refined over a twenty-�year period of empirical research and
52╇╇ H. Patomäki
verification, including a large amount of cross-�cultural research that went beyond
Piaget’s rather limited setting of empirical observations. Kohlberg died in 1987,
but subsequent research has confirmed, method-�independently, the existence of
common scheme of development of cognitive and moral reasoning and judgement, and related social perspective-�taking, across a variety of cultural and
politico-�economic contexts (Boom et al. 2007; Dawson 2002; Gibbs et al. 2007;
see also Robinson 2007). The contents of moral reasoning are culturally specific
and contextual, but the stages of cognitive-�conceptual schemes are universal.
These studies show the existing potential for human reasoning and judgements,
not their role in actual practices.8
For a political scientist, ethico-�political judgements and principles are especially interesting. According to Kohlberg (1971, 1973), they are human constructions, but are in no way arbitrary. Rather they make increasingly more
generalisable, differentiated and ‘equilibriated’ solutions possible. At stage (1)
humans can only obey the powerful and claim simple rewards and retributive
justice. At stage (2) reasoning is hedonistic and takes into account, in addition to
authoritarian stage one considerations, only limited forms of reciprocity. Stage (3)
actors are explicitly moral, but mostly only in a sense of recognising morality as
conformity to the prevailing expectations. Stage (3) actors are, however, capable
of differentiating between intentions and results of actions and, for instance, do not
anymore demand punishments for non-�intentional actions or outcomes.
Stage (4) is a step more abstract and general, based on the explicit recognition
of the value of the community, its relations of authority, and one’s duty to it.
However, pure stage (4) does not enable law-�making in any rational sense as
there are no extra-�conventional reasons to draw on. At stage (5), utilitarian and
contractual considerations become possible, and finally at stage (6), right is
defined by the decision of conscience in accord with the self-�chosen ethical principles. Stage (6) corresponds to the Rawlsian principles of democratic justice.
Jürgen Habermas (1979) has built on Kohlberg and added a seventh level.
When Habermas first proposed a new stage (7) to complement Kohlberg’s
account of moral learning, he was responding to a major problem of Kantian
ethics. Kant’s categorical imperative denies the relevance of ego and its needs,
emotions, interests and happiness to morality. It demands the submission of ego
to whatever commands cognitive reason may generate. It also sees the categorical imperative in monological terms, thus denying any need for an intersubjective dialogue about moral rules and principles. On the basis of his criticism of
monological reasoning, Habermas formulates the basic principles of discourse
ethics, including ‘only those norms can claim to be valid that meet (or could
meet) with the approval of all affected in their capacity as participants in a practical discourse’ (Habermas 1990a: 197). Further, Habermas argues that what is
also required for a successful normative discourse is openness to learning. ‘Even
those interpretations in which the individual identifies needs that are most peculiarly her own are open to a revision process’ (Habermas 1990b: 49). This openness notwithstanding, no-Â�one can replace individual’s own assessment of
normative validity. Habermas also maintains that successful normative discourse
Agency, structures and time╇╇ 53
requires some minimal solidarity, i.e. concern for others’ welfare and empathy
for their situation. Universal discourse ethics is thus entwined with the basics of
ethics of care; and, by implication, it must also presuppose something akin to
Rawls’ difference principle in order to sustain the socio-Â�economic and educational preconditions for free discourse.
Habermas (1979: 89) argues that while stage (5) still somehow manages to
limit applicability to legal associates (citizens of a state), at stage (6) the domain
of validity of ethico-�political principles must include all humans at least as
private persons. At the discourse-�ethical stage (7) all human beings are seen as
members of an imagined world society, as world citizens. Thus cognitive stages
(6) and (7) and stages beyond9 imply cosmopolitan principles of inclusion. While
Kant still wanted to limit the public rights of world citizens to hospitality, his
categorical imperative did not stop at state-�borders; for Kant, moral reasoning
concerns all human beings. In discourse ethics, the all in ‘only those norms can
claim to be valid that meet (or could meet) with the approval of all affected in
their capacity as participants in a practical discourse’ refers potentially to every
human being, depending of course also on who in fact affected. Similarly,
Bhaskar’s (1994) principle ‘free flourishing of each is the condition of free flourishing of all’ is universalist and cosmopolitan.
Consistent stages (6) and (7) reasoning thus question the moral relevance of
state-�borders and other partitions, and anticipate a future planetary society. This
is a conceptual-�logical consequence of moving to higher stages. Higher stage
reasoning is both more differentiated (implying a nuanced understanding of
social and cultural realities) and more integrated (implying symmetry and consistence) than prior stages. Therefore, further learning at the critical-�reflective
stage implies cosmopolitanism. From stage (6) onwards, moral principles must
concern universally all of humanity, for otherwise the symmetry and consistence
of those principles would be undermined, or directly violated.
Conclusion: in anticipation of a planetary ethico-�political
community
Social structures are concept- and action-�dependent. Society is both the ever-�
present condition and the continually reproduced outcome of human agency (see
Bhaskar 1979: 43). The mechanism generating the outcome that internal relations, social practices and systems transcend time, place and, also, the biological
existence of human beings, is language, communication and learning. The
actions of several actors are linked to one another by means of the enabling and
regulative mechanism of reaching understanding. (cf. Habermas 1984: 274–275).
This indicates that the structures of individual and collective learning are homologous and intertwined; yet they are not the same. The mechanisms and processes
of collective learning through institutional transformations are dissimilar from
those of the growth of an individual (cf. Habermas 1979: 102–103).
The complications of institutional changes notwithstanding, involving relations of direct and structural power and many other conditions, actors’ further
54╇╇ H. Patomäki
advances in learning tend to change the social context. Knowledgeable and competent actors are not genetically determined beings, but results of a slow shift
from predominantly biological to increasingly cultural time. Actors’ construction follows the conceptual and practical logic inherent in human culture.
Complex language has not only made agency possible but also facilitated further
stages of learning, gradually changing the prevailing types of action and modes
of agency. This process is of course contingent upon many particular geo-�
historical conditions and, therefore, temporary and contextual reversals are
clearly possible, but as a real tendency, collective learning is moving us towards
a cosmopolitan direction. From a future-�oriented perspective in world politics,
foreign policy-Â�making is thus unlikely to remain the central focus of agency–
structure dialectics. Rather, my analysis suggests that the shape of things to
come will be determined in struggles over establishing global-�democratic public
spheres and institutions.
Notes
1 Gilles Fauconnier and Mark Turner (2002: 171–177) claim that there is no evidence of
a gradual evolutionary development of language: ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›we can point to no simple languages, or even ones that are simpler than oursâ•›.â•›.â•›.; we have no evidence of intermediate, simpler forms of language’. First, there is now evidence for such a language; see
Everett (2008). Second, developments in language are highly contagious through learning. Over a few thousands of years, linguistic and grammatical innovations can easily
move across Eurasia and Africa. Whereas the gradual development of complex verbal
language seems to have taken tens of thousands of years. Third, because linguistic
complexity enabled new techniques and forms of cooperation, human population
growth has concentrated almost exclusively in those groups that have successfully
adopted complex verbal language (while many other groups may have faced physical
extinction or cultural conversion or adoption). Fourth, because the stages of learning
are logically and conceptually connected, there is no reason why a group of humans
isolated from the rest since, say, 40,000â•›bce would not have made some progress on its
own (e.g. aboriginals of Australia). No part of humanity has been isolated for more
than 40,000 years; and we should only expect the isolated groups to have developed
more slowly, not to lack all progress.
2 This is not only compatible with Jacques Derrida’s (1997) ‘science of grammatology’
but also gives it historical substance. Derrida maintains that our self-�conscious existence is possible only because of language and, more precisely (arch-) writing. Writing
comes before subjectivity. What many political theories such as liberalism take for
granted – self-Â�conscious individual actors – is an effect of language/writing. The formative context for consciousness and subjectivity evolved from the time-Â�consuming
process of gradual cognitive and related technical (and later also artistic) developments
in the long pre-�history of homo sapiens.
3 To what extent would it be possible to explain some of the phenomena Jaynes links
with the special effects of the ‘bicameral mind’ in ordinary cognitive terms? Piaget
(1977: 104–189) maintains that egocentrism, as a cognitive illusion of perspective and
related incapacity to distinguish properly between self, community/society and nature,
is essentially connected with heteronomy, which involves a literal/‘realist’ respect for
the authority of the rules and their reified origin. It is true that – just like children hallucinate in contemporary societies – many ancient people did, and some contemporary
people do, hallucinate ancestors and gods. Nonetheless, perhaps the hierarchical structures of these societies can be explained, to a degree, in terms of egocentric stage of
Agency, structures and time╇╇ 55
reasoning, rather than in terms of particular structuration of the brain? As Piaget (129)
writes, at the egocentric stage ‘[.â•›.â•›.â•›rules] acquire the value of ritual necessities, and the
forbidden things take on the significance of taboos. Moral realism would thus seem to
be the fruit of constraint and of the primitive forms of unilateral respect.’ Similarly,
‘dreams, for example, even when the child already knows that they are deceptive, are,
till about 7–8, systematically considered as an objective reality’ (180).
4 ‘We have often noted that in the intellectual field the child’s verbal thinking consists of
a progressive coming into consciousness, or conscious realization, of schemas that
have been built up by action. In such cases verbal thought simply lags behind concrete
thought, since the former has to reconstruct symbolically, and on a new plane operations that have already taken place on the preceding level’ (Piaget 1977: 112).
5 Despite his social relativism about values, Durkheim argued that moral and legal individualism is uniquely suitable to modern conditions of social solidarity, thus presuming
both linear history and historical inevitability in a sense that comes close to the standard modernisation thesis (Cotterrell 1999: Chs 7–9). Weber maintained that ultimate
values are arbitrary and modern individuals can see the tragedy of this irreversible condition of humanity living in a godless and disenchanted world (Lassman 2004:
256–261); yet Weber also theorised world-Â�historical rationalisation, especially on its
technical, institutional and voluntaristic dimensions, implying western superiority
(Blaut 2000: 19–30). In a like manner, Westermarck believed simultaneously in (1) relativist emotivism and (2) progress understood as an increasingly logical-Â�reflective attitude towards moral rules and principles (Swabey 1942).
6 This used to be the constitutive idea of anthropology since the founding works of Franz
Boas and others until the late twentieth century. It was articulated knowingly against
the imperialist policies of European and North American states and against the attitudes prevailing in those state/societies. Michael E. Brown (2008) argues, however,
that since the late 1980s most anthropologists have been trying to reconcile cultural
relativism with universal human rights and other normative notions, rather than adhering to relativism.
7 Kohlberg’s stages should be understood as revisable models about the conceptual-Â�
logical sequence of learning normative rules and principles, subsequently more adequate for enabling co-�operation and resolving conflicts. Models of stages of learning
are double-�hermeneutical in two ways. At the first level, these models concern a pre-�
interpreted world of lay meanings and can be, in part, checked against them; and
second, they are necessarily moving between abstract normative theories of morality,
justice and democracy, each of which enables one to perceive somewhat different
things.
8 This is the criticism of Dennis L. Krebs and Kathy Denton (2006) of some of the recent
studies confirming Kohlberg’s theory of moral stages. This criticism is pertinent only
to the extent that Kohlberg’s stages are taken to determine actual conduct in social
practices and institutions rather than indicate learning and cognitive capacity for moral
reasoning and judgement.
9 In contrast to Habermas, Karl-Â�Otto Apel (1978: 82–84) starts his normative theorising
from the late twentieth-�century global conditions of overpopulation, shortage of energy
resources, ecological crisis, including global warming and ‘the enormous enlargement
of the risks involved in human activities and conflicts’. On that basis Apel (1991, 1992,
2001) articulates a new philosophically grounded political ethics, what he calls ‘planetary macroethics’. Arguably, it is a new, higher stage in the cultural evolution of
humankind, corresponding to requirements of a common and joint responsibility for
the global consequences of human activities (Apel 1991: 261). Apel’s planetary macroethics is built on stage-Â�7 discourse ethics but goes beyond in its eco-Â�planetary future-Â�
orientation. In addition, further levels are also possible, as indicated by Kohlberg’s
(1981: 311–372) reflections on a cosmic perspective and how it can ultimately ground
ethics and give life a meaning.
56╇╇ H. Patomäki
References
Adorno, Theodor and Horkheimer, Max (1979). Dialectic of Enlightenment (translated by
J. Cumming). London: Verso (original work published 1944).
Apel, Karl-�Otto (1978). The conflicts of our time and the problems of political ethics. In
F. Dallmayr (ed.), From contract to community: Political theory at the crossroads
(pp.€81–101). New York: Dekker.
Apel, Karl-Â�Otto (1991). A planetary macroethics for humankind: The need, the apparent difficulty, and the eventual possibility. In E. Deutsch (ed.), Culture and modernity: East–
West philosophic perspectives (pp.€261–278). Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Apel, Karl-Â�Otto (1992). The ecological crisis as a problem for discourse ethics. In A.Øfsti
(ed.), Ecology and ethics: A report from the Melbu conference, 18–23 July 1990
(pp.€219–260). Rondheim: Nordland Akademi for Kunst og Vitenskap.
Apel, Karl-�Otto (2001). The response of discourse ethics to the moral challenge of the
human situation as such and especially today. Leuven: Peeters.
Archer, Margaret (1985). Structuration vs. morphogenesis. In S.N. Eisenstadt and H.J.
Helle (eds), Macro-�sociological theory: Perspectives on sociological theory (Vol. 1).
London: Sage.
Archer, Margaret (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ashley, Richard (1984). The poverty of neorealism, International Organization, 38(2),
225–286.
Bhaskar, Roy (1979). The possibility of naturalism: A philosophical critique of contemporary human sciences. Brighton: Harvester Press.
Bhaskar, Roy (1983). Beef, structure and place: Notes from a critical naturalist perspective. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 13,€82–95.
Bhaskar, Roy (1994). Plato etc: The problems of philosophy and their resolution.
London: Verso.
Blaut, J.M. (2000). Eight Eurocentric historians. New York: Guilford Press.
Boom, Jan, Wouters, Hans and Keller, Monika (2007). A cross-�cultural validation of
stage development: A rasch re-�analysis of longitudinal socio-�moral reasoning data.
Cognitive Development, 22, 213–229.
Brown, Michael F. (2008). Cultural relativism 2.0. Current Anthropology,
49(3),€363–383.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36(1),€245–270.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1993). On analysing the dynamics of foreign policy change: A critique
and reconceptualization. Cooperation and Conflict, 28(5),€5–30.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1994). In lieu of a conclusion: Compatibility and the agency–structure
issue in foreign policy analysis. In W. Carlsnaes and S. Smith (eds), European foreign
policy: The EC and changing perspectives in Europe (pp.€274–287). London: Sage,
Cotterrell, Roger (1999). Emile Durkheim: Law in a moral domain. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Dawson, Theo Linda (2002). New tools, new insights: Kohlberg’s moral judgement
stages revisited. International Journal of Behavioural Development, 26(2), 154–166.
Derrida, Jacques (1997). Of grammatology, revised edition (translated by G. Spivak).
Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Diamond, Jared (1999). Guns, germs, and steel: The fates of human societies. New York:
W.W. Norton.
Agency, structures and time╇╇ 57
Everett, Daniel (2008). Don’t sleep, there are snakes: Life and language in the Amazonian jungle. London: Profile Books.
Fauconnier, Gilles and Turner, Mark (2002). The way we think: Conceptual blending and
the mind’s hidden complexities. New York: Basic Books.
Foucault, Michel (1984). Nietzsche, genealogy, history (translated by D. Bouchard and S.
Simon). In P. Rabinow (ed.), The Foucault reader (pp.€76–100). London: Penguin.
Foucault, Michel (2001). Madness and civilization (translated by D. Cooper). London:
Routledge (original work published 1961).
Gibbs, John C., Basinger, Karen S., Grime, Rebecca L. and Snarey, John R. (2007).
Moral judgment development across cultures: Revisiting Kohlberg’s universality
claims. Developmental Review, 27,€443–500.
Giddens, Anthony (1979). Central problems in social theory. Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Habermas, Jürgen (1979). Communication and the evolution of society (translated by T.
McCarthy). Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Habermas, Jürgen (1984). The theory of communicative action, Vol. 1 (translated by T.
McCarthy). London: Heinemann.
Habermas, Jürgen (1990a). Moral consciousness and communicative action (translated by
C. Lenhardt and S. Weber Nicholsen). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Habermas, Jürgen (1990b). Justice and solidarity: On the discussions concerning Stage 6.
In M. Kelly (ed.), Hermeneutics and critical theory in ethics and politics (pp.€32–52).
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Harré, Rom and Secord, P. (1972). The explanation of social behaviour. Oxford: Blackwell.
Jaynes, Julian (2000). The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral
mind. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Kohlberg, Lawrence (1971). From Is to Ought: How to commit the Naturalistic Fallacy
and get away with it in the study of moral development’. In T. Mischel (ed.), Cognitive
Development and Epistemology (pp.€151–235). New York: Academic Press.
Kohlberg, Lawrence (1973). The claim to moral adequacy of a highest stage of moral
judgment. Journal of Philosophy, 70(18), 630–646.
Kohlberg, Lawrence (1981). The philosophy of moral development: Moral stages and the
idea of justice. Essays on moral development, Vol. 1. San Francisco, CA: Harper &
Row.
Krebs, Dennis L. and Denton, Kathy (2006). Explanatory limitations of cognitive-�
developmental approaches to morality. Psychological Review, 113(3),€672–675.
Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). (2006). Reflections on the dawn of consciousness: Julian Jaynes’s
Bicameral Mind Theory revisited. Henderson, NV: Julian Jaynes Society.
Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark (1999). Philosophy in the flesh. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Lassman, Peter (2004). Political theory in an age of disenchantment. Max Weber Studies,
4(2),€253–271.
Lyotard, Jean-Â�François (1984). The postmodern condition: A report on knowledge (translated by G. Bennington and B. Massumi). Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Patomäki, Heikki (1991). Concepts of ‘action’, ‘structure’ and ‘power’ in ‘critical social
realism’: A positive and reconnstructive critique. Journal for the Theory of Social
Behaviour, 21(2),€221–250.
Patomäki, Heikki (1996). How to tell better stories about world politics? European
Journal of International Relations, 2(1), 105–133.
58╇╇ H. Patomäki
Patomäki, Heikki (2002). After International Relations: Critical realism and the (re)construction of world politics. London: Routledge.
Piaget, Jean (1977). The moral judgement of the child (translated by M. Gabain). Harmondsworth: Penguin (original work published 1932).
Piaget, Jean (2002). The language and thought of the child (translated by M. and R.
Gabain). London: Routledge (original work published 1923).
Popper, Karl (1960). The poverty of historicism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Robinson, Paul H. (2007). The origins of shared institutions of justice. Vanderbilt Law
Review, 60(6),€1633–1688.
Swabey, William C. (1942). Westermarckian relativity. Ethics, 52 (2), 222–230.
Wendt, Alexander (1987). The agent–structure problem in international relations theory.
International Organization, 41(3),€335–370.
5 Theories, truisms and tools in
international relations
Kjell Goldmann
In this chapter I shall argue first that leading theorists of power in international relations qualify their theories so as to render their assertions near-�truistic, second that
we are more likely to go wrong in the future-�oriented analysis of foreign policy by
limiting ourselves to such theory than by avoiding theory altogether, but third that
other kinds of theoretical tools are useful for the exploration of international relations and foreign policy, including both pre-�theory in the sense of eclectic frameworks of analysis and meta-�theory in the sense of theory about pre-�theory.
The theory of international power
By 1898 Eduard Bernstein had concluded that Marx would be better served by
revising his theory than by stretching it to explain everything. Developments in
Europe had proven to be the opposite of what the theory of historical materialism had predicted, but this, Bernstein argued, did not mean that Marx had been
wrong. When a new theory is proposed it is necessary to exaggerate and be one-�
sided, but ‘of course’ Marx had not overlooked the role of politics and ideology
(Bernstein 1898, 1899; Carsten 2003). Bernstein thus reduced a seemingly deterministic economic theory of society to an assertion that the economy is essential.
In his effort to make Marxist theory compatible with the evidence he made historical materialism more truism than theory.
An analogue in the discipline of International Relations (IR) is the theory that
power is decisive.1 Governments seek to justify their actions in terms of legal or
moral principles but, according to this theory, their real concern is power. This is
not because they are narrow-�minded or immoral but because they must accept
reality. A country whose government ignores the objective reality of power will
suffer dire consequences.
This theory is paradoxical. Politics is ruled by objective facts, and yet it
matters what politicians decide. The actions of others are determined by the
necessity of power, but the decisions of our own government may go in any
direction if we don’t watch out. The way out is to admit that there is no necessity
and that power is one factor among several.
This is what power theorists do, however deterministically they express themselves. Three features of Thucydides’ The Peloponnesian War, often considered
60╇╇ K. Goldmann
the foundational work of IR, combine to form a theory of power: (1) the view
that what had happened to Hellas would, ‘at some time or other and in much the
same ways, be repeated in the future’ because of ‘human nature’,2 (2) the contention that the ‘real reason’ for the war was disguised by an argument about the
complaints of the parties and was in fact ‘the growth of Athenian power and the
fear which this caused in Sparta’, and (3) the assertion, made by Thucydides’
own Athenians in the Melian Dialogue, that ‘our opinion of the gods and our
knowledge of men lead us to conclude that it is a general and necessary law of
nature to rule wherever one can’ (Thucydides 1954: 24–25, 363).3
It is a common observation, however, that Thucydides’ account of the war is
cast in a non-�deterministic form. Time and again Thucydides has the actors
debate options, none of which is pictured as obvious or necessary. As put by
Morrison (2006), history is contingent in Thucydides’ thought. This is the
opposite of necessity. Power does decide, but not only power, and not in a way
that can be predicted. This is more truism than theory.
Hans Morgenthau opens Politics among Nations (1961 [1948]) with the
assumption that politics and society are ‘governed by objective laws that have
their roots in human nature’. The ‘main signpost’ of political realism, he asserts,
is ‘the concept of interest defined in terms of power’. A ‘realist theory of international politics’ will guard against two fallacies: ‘the concern with motives and
the concern with ideological preferences’. Such theory, however, is merely a
theory of ‘the rational essence to be found in experience, without the contingent
deviations from rationality which are also found in experience’. What is more, in
addition to interest defined as power there is ‘the moral significance of political
action’: the ‘supreme virtue’ is not to pursue interest defined as power but to
show ‘prudence – the weighing of the consequences of political action’ (Morgenthau 1961: 4–10). Morgenthau’s biographer Christoph Frei, as a matter of
fact, shows Morgenthau to have been both realist and idealist throughout (Frei
2001).
Kenneth Waltz’s style is more assertive that Morgenthau’s, but in Theory of
International Politics the reader is told from the beginning that a theory is
merely an indication that ‘some factors are more important than others’. The task
is to find ‘the central tendency among a confusion of tendencies’, ‘the propelling
principle even though other principles operate’, ‘the essential factors where
innumerable factors are present’. A theory of international politics is not a theory
of foreign policy, to cite one more of Waltz’s cautionary reminders (Waltz 1979:
8, 10, 72). When replying to his critics, Waltz adds that explanations are indeterminate because ‘both unit-Â�level and structural causes are in play’. Systemic
theory has ‘bothersome limitations’ arising from the difficulty of weighing unit-Â�
level and structural causes. This is a ‘serious, and seemingly inescapable, limitation of systems theories of international politics’ (Waltz 1986: 343). We are left
with a theory asserting that the power structure of the system of states is essential. This does not take us far beyond the obvious.
Bold assertion combined with cautioning reminder is a common feature
among theorists of international power. To cite a further example, according to
Theories, truisms and tools in IR╇╇ 61
Mearsheimer’s theory of offensive realism, states are compelled to maximise
power, and this makes power competition unavoidable and the threat of inter-�
state violence incessant. Mearsheimer, however, mixes deterministic and non-�
deterministic phrasing and admits that there are ‘many possible causes of
aggression, and no state can be sure that another state is not motivated by one
of€them’ (2001: 31). He also shares with other theorists of power the paradox of
regarding his theory as deterministic and normative at the same time.4
The theory of power, from Thucydides to Mearsheimer, is structural in the
sense of purporting to explain agency in terms of features assumed to be independent of individual actors.5 The calculations of agents are presumed to be uniformly determined by ‘objective’ (Morgenthau) or ‘structural’ (Waltz) features.
The contribution of such theory to the explanation of agency is modest, however,
since its explanatory power is not even remotely specified. There is little beyond
caveats about what other factors need to be taken into account and how they
relate to each other and to the international power structure.
What is more, there is little or nothing about how the implications of international power may change over time. Ideas about how to modify the international
system along the lines of liberal internationalism are not taken into consideration
or are simply asserted to be unworkable. Hence this theory is of limited usefulness for the consideration of what change is likely to produce what long-�term
effect on international politics.
It is a valid question as to why so much attention in IR discourse has been
devoted to this combination of pretensions and caveats. The manifest function of
scholarly debate is to separate the wheat from the chaff. Scholars are expected to
place substantive knowledge claims before the academic community, whose critical scrutiny will decide what must be rejected and what may provisionally be
retained. This institution of quality control, crucial for academic life, presumes
that the claims put forward are strong enough to be valid. This is not the case
with theories embedded in caveats. The concern with such theory within IR suggests that IR discourse performs functions beyond the critical analysis of knowledge claims. I shall suggest two such functions: ideology and identity.
From a social scientific point of view it is not very meaningful to debate
whether, for example, power is more important than other factors for developments in society or whether ideas are more important. It is different from the
point of view of ideology. In conservative thought, human nature is seen as
imperfect both morally and intellectually; history and tradition have made the
sovereign nation-�state the foundation of political thought; it is meaningless if not
dangerous to attempt to change this condition by innovative institution building.
In the liberal tradition, in contrast, man is presumed to be both good and rational;
no historical necessity obtains; breaking with tradition and turning international
relations in a new direction is the core of liberal internationalism. This disagreement has been a feature of western politics for two centuries, and the debate
within IR has been a variation on this theme. A work such as Theory of Interna­
tional Politics can be seen as an academic justification of conservative thought,
and the intensity with which it has been criticised can be understood as a defence
62╇╇ K. Goldmann
of liberal internationalism against this attack. In ideological debate, of course,
indeterminacy may be a virtue just as much as a vice.
Furthermore, practitioners within a field of study seem to need a collective
identity in the sense of a perception of community, of common aims, and of a
common understanding of what the field is like.6 In IR, the focus on power has
probably been enhanced by disagreement typical of an emerging field in need of
common identity but lacking in common aims and understandings. As pointed
out by Thies (2002), the theory of power has been promoted as a distinct IR
identity which, very usefully, can be traced all the way back to classical antiquity. This helps explain not only the respect with which the theory of power has
been treated within the profession but also the intensity with which it has been
criticised. Some in IR have evidently felt it necessary to take up arms to prevent
their identity from being defined by realism à la Morgenthau or Waltz. Some
outside IR, moreover, have found Morgenthauian and maybe Waltzian realism
useful as a significant other. Debating a truism appears useful for identity
construction.
Hedgehogs and foxes
It is a standard response to prediction failure in the social sciences that prediction never was the aim. The matter was brought to a head by the financial crisis
of 2008: soul-�searching among economists, to cite David Brooks (2010), made
them rediscover the ‘humility of an earlier time’. The yearnings of human beings
are not reducible to universal laws, Brooks wrote, and once this was accepted
‘economics would again be reduced to a subsection of history and moral
philosophy’.
This was as when the Cold War ended in a way that was not only unpredicted
but unpredictable on the basis of IR theory, an event that demonstrated, among
other things, the weakness of the theory of power.7 According to Robert
Keohane, criticising IR for having failed in this regard ‘misunderstands what
students of international relations can do’. We don’t have ‘recipes for foreign
policy success’ and have a ‘manifest inability to predict complex events. .â•›.â•›. The
model of science as increasingly successful prediction based on increasing
numbers of validated generalizations is not appropriate for our field’ (1996:
463–464).
I do not share Keohane’s view of the essential irrelevance of IR theory for
policy considerations.8 However, so far as the theory of power is concerned the
step is short to Isaiah Berlin’s famous distinction between hedgehogs and foxes.
Berlin begins his essay about Tolstoy with a line from Archilochus: ‘The fox
knows many things, but the hedgehog knows one big thing.’ There is a chasm,
according to Berlin, between those who ‘relate everything to a single central
vision’ or ‘universal, organizing principle’ and those whose ideas are ‘centrifugal rather than centripetal’ and whose thought is ‘scattered and diffused, moving
on many levels, seizing upon the essence of a vast variety of experiences and
objects for what they are in themselves’, without seeking to fit them into any
Theories, truisms and tools in IR╇╇ 63
Â� embracing ‘unitary inner vision’ (1953: 2). The distinction, rephrased by a
all-�
psychologist, is between those who ‘toil devotedly within one tradition, and
reach for formulaic solutions to ill-Â�defined problems’, and those who ‘draw from
an eclectic array of traditions, and accept ambiguity and contradiction as inevit�
able features of life’ (Tetlock 2005: 2).
Berlin thinks that there is a difference of this kind between political science
and statesmanship: the statesman must be able to comprehend a unique situation
in its full complexity, and all the political scientist can offer are simplifying
�generalisations (1996). The theory of power would seem to be an outstanding
example.
In 2007, Berlin’s student Michael Ignatieff, prominent in politics as well as
research, published a remorseful op-�ed piece in the New York Times headlined
‘Getting Iraq Wrong’. Ignatieff quoted Berlin to the effect that the trouble with
academics is that they care more about whether ideas are interesting than
whether they are true. I have learned that good judgement in politics looks different from good judgement in intellectual life, he wrote. ‘Among intellectuals,
judgment is about generalizing and interpreting particular facts as instances of
some big idea. In politics, everything is what it is and not another thing. Specifics matter more than generalities. Theory gets in the way.’ He added, apparently
referring to his own Harvard and similar places, that a sense of reality ‘doesn’t
always flourish in elite institutions’, and political science ‘promises more than it
can deliver’ (Ignatieff 2007).
Psychological research confirms that fox-Â�like insight makes for better predictions of political matters than hedgehog-Â�type theory (Tetlock 2005: 21–23,
passim). Hedgehog commitment to a single theory as if it were deterministic
thus makes for bad judgement. This would seem to be a risk inherent in the
central position of the theory of power in IR, as it has been in the Marxist commitment of some other scholars.
Foxes, to repeat, draw from a variety of traditions when puzzling together an
assessment of a situation. This suggests that the maintenance of controversy
between contending approaches is a way for IR scholarship to contribute to
statesmanship. The theory of power, of questionable utility in itself, may contribute to insight if combined with rival theories of other orientations. A plurality
of truisms may make for good foxness. From this perspective, IR discourse is to
be seen as insight-�giving conversation rather than as a striving for systematic
knowledge. Teaching students about realist theory and its critics may help
improving their judgement, even if this debate differs from the academic ideal of
the critical analysis of knowledge claims.
Theorising in IR comprises more than the contention between near-�truistic
generalisations, however. There is a different kind of theoretical activity that is
useful for the academic analysis of events in international relations as well as for
considerations of foreign policy in spite of, or because of, not representing an
ideological or identity-�related commitment to a particular point of view. This is
theorising to which many of us have contributed, but one that is more properly
called pre-�theory and sometimes meta-�theory.
64╇╇ K. Goldmann
Theories as tools
The theory of power in international relations aims at being comparable, if not to
theory in the natural sciences at least to the theory of economics; the parallel
between economic theory and Waltz’s Theory of International Politics is often
drawn. Other theoretical constructs in IR abstain from claiming to identify ‘political laws’ (Morgenthau) or ‘central tendencies’ (Waltz). Their justification is the
more modest one of improving our tools for explanation and maybe forecasting.
From the point of view of hedgehogs, such constructs offer toolboxes that should
prove useful for the further development of their central visions – for specifying
the interaction between power and other concerns in the making of foreign
policy, for example. From the point of view of foxes, their utility lies in their
structuring and systematising insights brought together from various approaches.
While the theory of power is better for ideological and identity-�related purposes,
more modest theoretical constructs may be better tools for research and thinking.
The term pre-�theory, appropriate for such constructs, was made common
property in IR by James Rosenau (1964). I take it for granted that it is impossible for foxes to do without such tools, even if they leave them implicit. Making
them explicit opens the way for scrutiny and hence improvement. The logical
scrutiny of pre-�theories may be called meta-�theoretical.
The characteristic feature of a pre-Â�theory – or conceptual framework, or
model – is that it defines variables and outlines relations between them without
claiming to specify the effect on one variable of a particular change in another.
A simple early example is Ole Holsti’s (1962) model of an individual’s decision
resulting from information filtered though his or her belief system. No specifics
can be derived from this model, but Holsti provides a tool for hedgehogs intending to dig deeper as well as for foxes considering an immediate issue. A more
complex, early example is Snyder and associates’ outline of ‘state X as actor in a
situation’, which brings together into a single diagram fifteen different phenomena and their relations with each other as well as with the interaction between
decision making and action and between the internal and the external setting
(Snyder et al. 1962). No specific conclusion about anybody’s action follows
from specific assumptions about any of the fifteen phenomena included in the
model; this is not a theory proper of foreign policy decision or action but an
elaborate suggestion of what to take into account when exploring decisions or
actions. Rosenau’s (1964) pre-Â�theory, of course, is a third example in arguing
that the analysis of a country’s foreign policy needs to integrate five sets of
sources, namely, individual, role, governmental, societal, and systemic.
In the half-Â�century since these works were published, there has been a proliferation of such frameworks – simple or complex, verbal or mathematical, true to
a single approach or bringing together elements from various approaches, resulting from theoretical thought or inferred from empirical findings.
It is a reasonable question whether the pretentious theories of power I have
found truistic are not better seen as pre-�theories and thus as mere tools. As a
matter of fact, Mearsheimer’s theory of offensive realism has been used in
Theories, truisms and tools in IR╇╇ 65
�
precisely
this fashion in a dissertation about US policy after 9/11. The author,
Johannes Rø, translates offensive realism into a number of ‘mechanisms’ and
goes on to examine to what extent there is evidence of each of these in the White
House and what other ‘mechanisms’, not derived from offensive realism, also
need to be considered (2011).
A pre-�theory may be strong or weak depending both on the quality of its concepts and on the degree to which its hypothesised relationships are supported by
evidence. Applying it empirically may give insights that can be fed back to the
original model or framework. A discovery likely to be made is that some of the
concepts fail to be operational; learning more about how to operationalise key
concepts is a likely experience from the empirical application of a pre-�theory.
The empirical application of a pre-�theory, furthermore, may provide insights into
what concepts need to be refined, differentiated, substituted or added. It may be
seen as trial and error for the purpose of making the pre-�theory more similar to
theory proper.
The main point of making one’s pre-Â�theory explicit, however, is to make it
available for critical examination. Since it is a feature of good scholarship to
facilitate the scrutiny of one’s work, putting one’s theoretical assumptions on the
table should be routine. A pre-�theory may be examined from the point of view of
precision, comprehensiveness, and empirical evidence. However, since useful
pre-Â�theory is often eclectic – not least Rosenau’s – it is important to scrutinise
not only its details but also its logic.
A scholar devoting himself to this task is Walter Carlsnaes. Even though
Carlsnaes casts his oft-Â�cited consideration of the agency–structure problem in
foreign policy analysis (1992) in the form of a consideration of fundamental
issues in political theory and social science philosophy, his analysis is also, if
not predominantly, a comment on the implications of some of the pre-�theories
the rest of us have used as tools. Much of Carlsnaes’ work can be read as a demonstration of the utility of examining the logic of eclectic pre-Â�theoretical frameworks. In works such as his, those using theoretical frameworks as tools for
analysis can find the tools needed for improving their own.
Carlsnaes, among other things, has indicated a way of combining the examination of the role of structure for agency with the exploration of the role of
agency for structure. I have argued that the largely truistic theory of power in
international relations is weak on both accounts. Many have contributed pre-�
theoretical pieces to these interrelated puzzles. Carlsnaes’ meta-Â�theory indicates
the logic of integrating them to a more coherent picture.
Bismarck is Isaiah Berlin’s favourite example of a statesman whom he contrasts with political scientists. True, a Bismarck may not be helped by a political
scientist telling him about the ‘rational essence’ (Morgenthau) or the ‘propelling
principle’ (Waltz). He may however benefit from a good pre-Â�theory or maybe
even meta-�theory to bring order to his intuitions.
66╇╇ K. Goldmann
Notes
1 What is called the theory of power in this paper is the general theory of relations of
power as determinant of political action. I am not going into power theories of more
limited scope. Nor will I consider the very concept of power (for a suggestion about
how to make it less ambiguous, see Goldmann 1979).
2 Thucydides is commonly translated in this way, but Zagorin (2005), who discusses the
matter in detail, maintains that ‘given the human condition’ is a more appropriate translation. There is a difference between ‘human nature’ and ‘the human condition’ paralleling the difference between the power theories of Morgenthau and Waltz to be
discussed in what follows.
3 In classical antiquity, the same thought was expressed by the Roman-�Jewish historian
Flavius Josephus. There is, according to Josephus, ‘an immutable and unchallenged
law among beasts and men alike, that all must submit to the stronger, and that power
belong[s] to those in arms’ (Josephus 1981: 317). Josephus, however, confuses the
issue by also explaining matters in terms of God’s will.
4 This is pointed out by Rø (2010: 14, fn€3), whose perusal of offensive realism I have
found quite helpful.
5 Much has been made of the difference between Waltz’s argument, which departs from
the structure of the international system, and Morgenthau’s reference to ‘human nature’
as the root of international politics. However, the ‘objective laws’ which, according to
Morgenthau, determine international politics may not differ much from structure in the
sense of recurrent social arrangements, just as Waltz’s structure may ultimately be
explained by what is akin to Morgenthau’s ‘human nature’.
6 This essentially is the concept of collective identity as I have defined it elsewhere
(Goldmann 2008).
7 The relation between the end of the Cold War and IR theory is considered in Allan and
Goldmann (1991), based on an ECPR workshop that was quite topical at the time it
was held. The implications for the theory of power are considered in my own contribution to the volume.
8 Neither Morgenthau nor Waltz hesitated to provide such advice. Morgenthau, among
other things, was a prominent critic of US warfare in Vietnam (Morgenthau 1965), and
Waltz argued, on the basis of his theory of international politics, against invading Iraq
(Kreisler 2003).
References
Allan, Pierre and Goldmann, Kjell (eds) (1992). The end of the Cold War: Evaluating
theories of international relations. The Hague: Kluwer Law International.
Berlin, Isaiah (1953). The hedgehog and the fox: An essay on Tolstoy’s view of history.
London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Berlin, Isaiah (1996). On political judgment. New York Review of Books, 43(15),
26–30.
Bernstein, Eduard (1898). Erklärung an den Parteitag der Sozialdemokratischen Partei
Deutschlands (retrieved from marxistsfr.org/deutsch/referenz/bernstein/1898/10/
erklaerung.htm).
Bernstein, Eduard (1899). Die Voraussetzungen des Sozialismus und die Aufgaben der
Sozialdemokratie. Stuttgart: J.€H.€W. Dietz, nachf.
Brooks, David (2010). The return of history. New York Times, 26 March (retrieved from
nytimes.com).
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. Inter­
national Studies Quarterly, 36, 245–270.
Theories, truisms and tools in IR╇╇ 67
Carsten, Francis L. (1993). Eduard Bernstein, 1850−1932: Eine politische Biographie.
München: Beck.
Flavius Josephus (1981 [c.75]). The Jewish War. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Frei, Christoph (2001). Hans J. Morgenthau: An intellectual biography. Baton Rouge,
LA: Louisiana State University Press.
Goldmann, Kjell (1979). The international power structure: Traditional theory and new
reality. In Kjell Goldmann and Gunnar Sjöstedt (eds), Power, capabilities, inter­
dependence: Problems in the study of international influence. London: Sage.
Goldmann, Kjell (2008). Identitet och politik: nationellt, övernationellt, semi-Â�nationellt.
Stockholm: SNS Förlag.
Holsti, Ole R. (1962). The belief system and national images: A case study. Journal of
Conflict Resolution, 6, 244–252.
Ignatieff, Michael (2007). Getting Iraq wrong. New York Times, 5 August (retrieved from
nytimes.com.).
Keohane, Robert O. (1996), International relations: Old and new. In Robert E.
Goodin and Dieter-�Klingemann, Hans (eds), A new handbook of political science
(pp.€462–478). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kreisler, Harry (2003). Theory and international politics: Conversation with Kenneth N.
Waltz (retrieved from globetrotter.berkeley.edu/people3/Waltz/waltz-�con0.htm).
Mearsheimer, John J. (2001). The tragedy of great power politics. New York: Norton.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (1961 [1948]). Politics among nations: The struggle for power and
peace, 3rd edn. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (1965). Vietnam and the United States. Washington, DC: Public
Affairs Press.
Morrison, James V. (2006). Reading Thucydides. Columbus, OH: Ohio State University
Press.
Rø, Johannes F. (2011). Inside the black box: Offensive realism and the U.S. response to
9/11. Oslo: University of Oslo.
Rosenau, James N. (1964). Pre-�theories and theories of foreign policy. In R. Barry Farrell
(ed.), Approaches in comparative and international politics. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press.
Snyder, R.C., Bruck, H.W. and Sapin, Burton (eds) (1962). Foreign policy decision-�
making: An approach to the study of international politics. New York: Free Press.
Tetlock, Philip (2005). Expert political judgment: How good is it? How can we know?
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Thies, Cameron T. (2002). Progress, history and identity in international relations theory:
The case of the idealist–realist debate. European Journal of International Relations, 8,
147–185.
Thucydides (1954 [c.411â•›bc]). History of the Peloponnesian War (translated by Rex
Warner). Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1979). Theory of international politics. New York: McGraw-�Hill.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1986). A response to my critics. In Robert O. Keohane (ed.), Neo­
realism and its critics (pp. 332–346). New York: Columbia University Press.
Zagorin, Perez (2005). Thucydides: An introduction for the common reader. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
6 The ritual/performance problem
in foreign policy analysis
European diplomats at the Chinese
court
Erik Ringmar
‘But where does culture go?’ Walter Carlsnaes leaned across the table and
looked me straight in the eyes. ‘You’re saying there is something missing from
my boxes? You want me to include “culture”? But where, Erik, does it go?’ I
must admit I was flustered. Our meeting had been going well up to this point. I
had just read his ‘agency and structure’ paper, fresh in print with International
Studies Quarterly (ISQ), and I believed I had found a problem with it (Carlsnaes
1992). Finding problems with your supervisor’s arguments, especially the ones
published in prestigious journals, is exhilarating. It allows you to try out a new
voice, the voice of a fellow colleague. Leaving my student identity behind for a
moment, I was going to assert my independence. If only I had a good answer.
‘Well,’ I cleared my throat, ‘it should probably go somewhere here.’ I pointed to
one of the blank corners on the graph before us, but as I pointed I could feel my
self-�confidence dissipating. There was no place for culture in that graph and I
knew it. Walter looked at me straight again. ‘Perhaps you’d better think this over
until our next meeting,’ he said with a faintly ironic smile. ‘Yes,’ I said, ‘perhaps
I’d better.’
That next meeting never took place. I saw Walter Carlsnaes on a number of
occasions, but never again formally, as a supervisor. I got my PhD from the
United States in the end and he was on the committee, but we never had a chance
to return to our topic. I never explained to him where culture goes. I’ve thought
about this problem for about 20 years now, and I think I finally know the answer.
The agency–structure problem, as other contributions to this book explain, is the
question of how to theorise the relationship between human actions and the
environment in which they occur. This is the hen-�and-egg problem of whether
structures determine agents or agents structures. The obvious solution is to say
that structures and agents determine each other, yet sensible as this solution
sounds, it provides surprisingly little help when it comes to research design. We
already know that ‘everything depends on everything else’, but what we do not
know is which factors that are the most important. After all, it is only by keeping
some things fixed that we can study how other things vary. The suggestion that
we first should look at the structure, then at the agent, then at the structure again
and so on, is not very helpful as long as we lack a more general framework which
can integrate the two and explain the logic of their relationship. By refusing to
The ritual and performance problem╇╇ 69
opt for one side or the other of the agent–structure divide, we are back where we
started – with the trite statement that eggs produce hens and hens eggs.
Although the agency–structure problem has been extensively discussed by
theorists of all stripes, what has received less attention is the fact that members
of society too face the same problem. They too ask themselves what they can do
given structural constraints and how those constraints could be re-�imagined or
altered. Reflections on the structure/agency problem is a persistent theme of
social life, including its treatment in novels, movies, arts and drama. In fact, the
social scientists’ reflections on the problem are best understood not as the
concern of scientists observing life in a test tube, but as part and parcel of this
modern, more general, preoccupation. Social scientists pondering the agency–
structure problem are only doing what everyone else, in some form or another,
does. Since this is the case, the problem can be investigated not only as a matter
of theoretical reflection but also empirically – by studying the publicly available
reflections on how it can be addressed.
This is true for a study of international relations too. The international system
of states which emerged in Europe in the late Renaissance is often described as
‘anarchic’, and as such it constitutes a structural constraint on action (Dessler
1989; Wendt 1987; Carlsnaes 1992). What anarchy means, however, is not self-�
evident but instead to be determined through the actions of states and other international actors, and the interpretations they provide (Wendt 1992). The topic to
be investigated below concerns how such interpretations happen. Anarchy may
be what states make of it, but to say as much still begs the question of how that
which states make of it was made. There is a pragmatics to the interpretation
which needs to be further elucidated. Specifying how meanings are made, we
will argue, ‘culture’ can be reintroduced into our analyses. Indeed, a study of
culture provides a way to investigate the inter-�relationship between agents and
structures which explains the logic of their relationship. Eggs will still produce
hens and hens eggs but we will have a better means of studying this process of
production.
European diplomats at the Chinese court
In order to better understand how anarchy was made in Europe, let’s consider
how anarchy was made in East Asia. There, before the middle of the nineteenth
century, international relations were organised in a radically different fashion
(Fairbank 1973; Zhang 2009; Ringmar 2012). The system was hierarchical and
ordered and the units were explicitly unequal. The metaphor of a solar-�system is
sometimes used, with China as the sun around which other political entities of
varying sizes circled in increasingly distant orbits. Or, more commonly, we can
talk about a tribute system where the subordinate states would bring gifts to the
imperial Chinese court, usually some form of ‘native produce’. In Beijing the
visitors were wined and dined and received in an audience with the emperor who
treated them kindly, if condescendingly, affirming the social bonds that tied the
system together. In this way order and peace was maintained, the Chinese
70╇╇ E. Ringmar
�
confirmed
in their world-�view, and the visitors recognised by the emperor of
China as legitimate rulers. In addition the visitors took the opportunity to trade
with the Chinese.
Although the Europeans were outsiders to this system, trade and colonialism
brought them into it, and as a result they too had to present themselves at the
imperial court. From the beginning of the Qing dynasty until the system was
abandoned in the wake of the Opium Wars, some 27 separate diplomatic missions showed up in Beijing: four Portuguese, four Dutch, twelve Russian, three
delegations from Rome, three British and one American. At the imperial court
the Europeans, much like visitors from East Asia, were required to follow a specific ritual which notoriously included the koutou, the full-�length prostration
before the imperial throne.1 The koutou confirmed the paternalistic relationship
which connected the tribute-�bearers to the Qing emperor. By koutou-�ing the visitors accepted their subordinate positions while the emperor agreed to take them
into his benevolent care. There were solid utilitarian reasons why the Europeans
should go through with this ritual – the merchants wanted access to Chinese consumers and the missionaries wanted access to Chinese souls – and yet they
regarded it as profoundly humiliating. From a European point of view, a full-�
length prostration was what slaves performed before a master, or a worshipper
before a god, but before a political ruler – including their own kings – a European would at most go down on one knee. Only East Asian rulers, the Europeans
decided, were despotic enough to insist on this ritual, and only East Asian subjects were submissive enough to go along with it. See Table 6.1.
The question is how this pattern best should be explained. Why did some
European visitors always koutou, some never koutou-�ed, and some koutou-�ed
only some of the time? The question is puzzling since they all faced the same
opportunities and the same constraints: they all wanted concessions from the
Chinese. Moreover, once the embassy arrived in Beijing they had already
invested a lot in its success and it would seem foolish to jeopardise the outcome
by not following the required protocol. Yet some countries always did, some
never did, and some did it only some of the time. Let us consider this as a
problem of foreign policy: there were actions, there were structures, but there
also seems to be ‘something cultural’ going on.
Action and the pragmatics of discourse
One particularly striking feature of the diplomatic interaction between China and
the rest of the world during the Qing dynasty is its theatrical quality. The Europeans presenting themselves at the imperial court found themselves the actors in
an elaborate state ritual, and it was the terms on which they appeared in this
ritual that the conflict concerned. For scholars used to analysing action in terms
of rational choices, this is bound to be puzzling. To them, rituals are ‘mere
rituals’ and as such at best examples of ‘expressive behaviour’ (see, for example,
Hamlin and Jennings 2011). Yet as the ritualism of the Chinese court reminds
us, rational actions are only one of several kinds of behaviour in which states,
Portugal
Papacy
Holland
United States
Great Britain
Russia
Koutou
1656, 1670, 1676, 1693–1694, 1716–1717, 1720–1721, 9
1721–1722, 1725–1727, 1757, 1763, 1767–1768, 1806
1670, 1678, 1727, 1753
4
1705–1706, 1720–1721, 1725
2
1656, 1667, 1685–1686, 1795
4
1859
0
1793, 1816, 1860
0
Visits
Table 6.1╇ Responses of the diplomatic missions
0
0
0
1
2
2
Refused to koutou,
no audience
0
1
0
0
1
1
Refused to koutou,
audience
100
67
100
0
0
75
Koutou/visits
(%)
72╇╇ E. Ringmar
and their representatives, engage. Ritualistic and theatrical behaviour are not
simply actions that are insufficiently rational, but behaviour of an entirely different kind. As a result we need a different way to explain them.
An action, lets remind ourselves, is the result of an actor interpreting a situation in a certain fashion, identifying the options available and considering
which option that is most likely to bring most benefit. The process of rational
deliberation thus understood, when brought before one’s mind at the appropriate
moment, results in a rational action. Actions, that is, serve the desires of the
persons carrying them out. Yet, since our desires typically are thought of as
unlimited, the environment in which we act will never properly satisfy us. We
always want more and the fact that everyone else wants more too means that we
have to behave strategically in our interactions with others – to make sure that
we get what we want before someone else gets it. Conditions of scarcity and
competition mean that both the physical and the social environment – both
‘structures’ – are understood as constraints.
Consider the place of culture in this process of rational deliberation. Rational
actions, we said, rely on interpretations. Before we act, we need to define our
interests, define the options available to us, define the situation we are in – and
these definitions all pre-�suppose a world which is meaningful. Sense is never
made by individuals alone but instead always together with other members of
our society and by the people who preceded us. Obviously, all societies have
several competing ways of making sense of things, and this gives us the option
of choosing between them (see, for example, Swidler 2003). Equally obviously,
we do not have to agree with the established interpretations. Even when we dis�
agree, however, we have to disagree in a meaningful way. All in all, we take
things to be the kinds of things that people in our society take things to be; we
want the kinds of things that others want; we are the kinds of people that others
are. As a result we come to incorporate a social element into even the most
selfish of our desires.
These ready-�made meanings make up an important part of the culture of our
societies.2 Meanings form a vast system of interrelated, although disparate and
not necessarily coherent, terms which together constitute what we could call a
‘discourse.’ A discourse can be understood as a vast imaginary dictionary, specific to our society, where various terms are defined in some particular, if not
necessarily coherent, fashion. Actions are thus simultaneously real – meaning
physiological and material – and discursive, meaning meaningful.
We rely on a discourse in putting together the narratives through which we
make sense of our lives (see, for example, Johnstone 2004). Narratives put
meanings into action, as it were: a story identifies a protagonist who is located in
a certain situation which includes other people but also the material, economic
and social circumstances of their lives. The situation has some basic problem or
tension which is worked out, scene by scene, through the actions in which the
protagonists engage. In its telling, the story comes to provide an account of the
relationship between agency and structure. Moreover, this relationship is no
longer an endless succession of hens and eggs, but it is plotted in a certain
The ritual and performance problem╇╇ 73
fashion. The story has a beginning, a middle and an end, and agency is related to
structure, and structure to agency, by means of a plot. When the story comes to
an end, the tension between agency and structure is resolved.
In addition to the problem of what something means, we said, there is the
problem of how something means. Discourse has no social life; it is mute, like a
book on a shelf before somebody reads it. Although this may be good enough
for literary theorists who study texts, social scientists are in addition interested in
how something came to be interpreted a certain fashion; how, that is, the book
was read and received. There must be some process, in other words, through
which discourse came to be activated and made available for public as well as
individual deliberation (cf. Walker 2006). We could refer to this process as the
‘pragmatics’ of discourse. Such a pragmatics can take many forms, but two are
particularly important for our purposes: rituals and what we will refer to as
‘social performances.’
Rituals are associated with particular times and places in the life of a person
or a society.3 Rituals are established responses to an environment which is uncertain, risky, or in a state of change; rituals are associated with comings and
goings, passages and turning-�points, transitions and transformations. Rituals take
place in their own space, a location and an occasion removed from the ordinary
stream of life, which you enter and leave – often by means of a ritual. Engaging
with the ritual, we subject ourselves to the requirements of a script which specifies the use of particular movements, words and assorted paraphernalia; that is,
we subject ourselves to a tradition of which our society is the custodian and perpetuator. Rituals, as a result, are social occasions, they are usually carried out
together with others, and even when we carry them out alone, rituals necessarily
make reference to a larger community – of believers, for example, co-Â�nationals
or fellow party-�members. Yet rituals require no particular skill and they are not
performed in the sense that they require a personal interpretation or expression;
rituals can often be carried out without your hearts or minds being engaged.
But not all performances are ritualistic. In addition to rituals there are plays,
that is, theatrical performances (cf. Alexander 2006). Plays are staged in much
the same fashion as rituals; they unfold in a confined space, dedicated to the
purpose, which is set off from the continuity and flow of ordinary life. Yet theatrical performances, in contrast to rituals, have pretensions to verisimilitude; they
are at the same time a presentation and a re-�presentation. The actions presented
on the stage are representing life outside the stage – above all the lives of individuals and the social and material conditions in which they find themselves.
The play has a narrative structure and a plot which turns on the actions carried
out by the actors.4 Plays, in contrast to rituals, have an audience. The purpose of
the performance is to show the audience something, to demonstrate or teach
something, to convey emotions and experiences.5
Thus understood, performances are not only taking place in theatres but elsewhere in society too. A ‘social performance’ is a staged and narrated event, performed by actors in front of an audience, which takes a social, political or
economic issue as its topic.6 Social performances also have plots that unfold
74╇╇ E. Ringmar
through the actions of actors, and the aim, just as in a theatrical performance, is
to show or teach something, to convey emotions and experiences. Examples of
social performances include extravagant displays of royal opulence, staged
debates between presidential candidates, the destruction of a palace during a
war, mass demonstrations, victory parades, state funerals, a revolutionary fête,
the ‘cult’ of a political leader, and acts of terrorism.
This is how societies conceptualise the agency–structure problem. In rituals
and social performances the external world is internalised. The external environment is transformed into a known and far more easily graspable environment
which belongs to the performance itself.7 Rituals, we said, are particularly
common during times of transitions and transformations, that is, at moments
when agency is badly defined, social structures uncertain, and the relationship
between agency and structure unclear. The ritual replaces this external uncertainty with an internal certainty and helps ease the move from the one state to
the other. The ritual re-�inserts the individual both into the unfolding context of
her own life and into society as a whole. In this way the ritual provides a means
of coping with a situation with which we could not have coped, or not coped as
well, on our own.
Social performances add verisimilitude and audience participation to these
ritualistic representations. On the stage a world is created which has its own
agents, structures, and relationship between them. The constraints set by this
�internal environment, and the actions in which individuals engage on stage, are
determined by what we regard as meaningful, not by economic, social or political factors. As audience members, we watch the performance and as a result the
structural constraints and the actions available to us in our own lives come to be
elucidated, criticised or reaffirmed. A performance, that is, is a way for society
to think. As members of the audience, we are no longer telling only our own
story, but forced to consider other people’s stories and the stories of our society
as a whole (Walker 2006; see also Nellhaus 2000). This is the story-�telling to
which social scientists too, in a modest fashion, make a contribution.
To koutou or not to koutou?
To say that an international system is ‘anarchic’ is not to say very much.
Anarchy refers to the positioning of political subjects in relation to each other,
but such a positional map tells us nothing as to how their relationships are interpreted. In order to understand the logic of a certain international system, we need
not a theoretical analysis, but a historical account. Only a historical exposition
can tell us how a certain definition of anarchy came to be established and how it
came to matter to states and to the individuals acting in their name.
The rituals performed at the imperial court in Beijing answer these questions
as far as the Sino-�centric international system is concerned (Ringmar 2012). The
fact that the system was centred on the Chinese capital, and that envoys from the
rest of East Asia paid their respects before the imperial throne, reveals the basic
logic of the system. The emperor stayed put, that is, and the envoys appeared
The ritual and performance problem╇╇ 75
before him carrying their respective tributes. Through the rituals, including the
koutou, they affirmed their submission, much as a Chinese child might do before
a father. The emperor responded in kind, affirming that the envoys and their
masters now were under his care. The rituals, in short, stressed hierarchy, inequality, but also mutual obligations. This was how the Sino-�centric international
system was interpreted and it was through these rituals that it became visible,
that is, real. Through the ritual the relationship between agency and structure
became obvious to all participants.
Contrast and compare the international system which emerged in Europe in the
late Renaissance (ibid.). This Westphalian system was not ritualistic but theatrical. The world, in the popular metaphor, was regarded as ‘a stage’ on which states
acted and interacted with each other. This metaphor took on concrete manifestations in various locations across Europe – in theatres of war but also in the chambers of peace congresses or, more recently, in the assembly halls of international
organisation like the United Nations. Here there were plenty of rituals too, but
there was no set script and no one director. Instead the states and their representatives were free to write their own lines, subject only to the requirements imposed
by the common performance. There was an audience too: a ‘world opinion’
expressed through the printing press which regularly passed its judgement on
what states did and what they should do. In contrast to the rituals taking place in
Beijing, these performances stressed equality, sovereignty and self-�determination.
States were guided by their ‘interests’ and constrained only by other states who
were guided in the same fashion. It was through these performances that the
Euro-�centric international system came to be visualised and made real. It was in
this way that agency was related to structure in the Westphalian system.
Given that anarchy was so differently conceptualised in the two systems,
there were bound to be misinterpretations and conflicts between them, symbolised, as we have seen, by the question of the koutou. To the legates dispatched
by Rome, however – including the Jesuits fathers who were permanently stationed in Beijing – the issue was never presented in these terms.8 The Church,
much as the Chinese emperor, had a ritualistic view of the world and a firm conviction regarding its own centrality – and it did not recognise the newfangled
notion of state sovereignty. Given their incompatible universalisms, however,
one would have expected Rome and Beijing to clash and the legates to have had
serious problems with the koutou. Such confrontations, however, were avoided
by the dexterity of Jesuits missionaries such as Matteo Ricci who argued that
these were rituals of no particular significance. To Ricci what mattered was
access to the imperial court which he regarded as key to a successful conversion
of the Chinese people. It was only once the power of the Jesuits in Rome had
been eclipsed by that of the Dominicans that this interpretation came to be questioned. It was also only now that Rome’s legates made trouble about the koutou.
The Portuguese and the Dutch koutou-�ed, but in order to win commercial
favours. To both countries trade was paramount and they were not going to make
a fuss about the trifles of court protocol. In fact, the Portuguese took great pride in
their respect for local customs – they did not, for example, like other Europeans,
76╇╇ E. Ringmar
impose their own place-Â�names on the foreign lands they encountered – and the
Dutch were not even represented by the country’s diplomats but instead by officials of the VOC, the Dutch East India Company (Seed 1995). Moreover, both
countries had a direct stake in the Sino-�centric system. Since 1550, the Portuguese had had a foothold in Macau and this made them, if not Chinese subjects,
at least highly dependent on the emperor’s benevolence. And Holland first settled
in Batavia on the island of Java in the early seventeenth century, and at this
trading-Â�post they too were an integral part – of the Sino-Â�centric system (Wills
1984).
As for Russia’s relations with China, they were established on an entirely different footing (Cahen 1914). Since the Russians approached China overland
rather than from the sea, they were treated as a Central Asian rather than as a
European power. Central Asian powers, the Chinese emperors knew only too
well, were dangerous, and the Russians, as a result, were treated with far more
respect. For example: the two countries concluded a series of agreements in the
seventeenth century in which a common border was established. Meanwhile,
back in Europe itself Russian diplomatic practices were considered as hopelessly
old-Â�fashioned. The Russians thought of themselves as an empire – as a ‘Third
Rome’ – and as such they shied away from the emerging Westphalian practices.
They did not, for example, station ambassadors abroad, and European visitors to
Moscow had to follow a protocol which resembled that employed in Beijing.
Yet this was why Russia and China got along so comparatively smoothly.
Russian ambassadors koutou-�ed in Beijing without complaints as long as the
Chinese promised they would do the same in Moscow. That no Chinese ambassadors were likely to go abroad was less often mentioned. It was only as a result
of the diplomatic reforms during the reign of Peter the Great that difficulties
between the two countries arose. Once Russia had joined the Westphalian
system, and suddenly found itself as an actor among others on its stage, the
status of the country in the eyes of the Chinese became a matter of great concern
to its diplomats. This was also when Russian visitors to Beijing suddenly refused
to koutou.
There was never a question of the one American delegation, led by John
Ward in 1859, ever koutou-�ing. At the time Americans were sceptical even of
European-�style diplomacy which they regarded as too secretive and too aristocratic (Satow 1917; Foster 1906). Thus no ambassadors were ever received in
Washington, DC since this ‘extraordinarily foreign privileged class’ (US Secretary of State, Thomas F. Bayard, 1885, quoted in Watson Foster 1906) was
thought to fit badly with American republican ideals. Moreover, the State
Department insisted that its own diplomats ‘should appear in the simple dress of
an American citizen’ when representing the country abroad (Foster 1906). As
Ward was approaching Beijing, his fellow Americans worried that he would
embarrass the country, yet Ward, firm in his republican convictions, did not
koutou (New York Times 1859). His steadfastness does, however, raise the question of what the Americans aimed to achieve in China. When the imperial
courtiers informed them that a koutou was mandatory, the Americans left on
The ritual and performance problem╇╇ 77
their own accord. Instead a partial agreement was signed, in a thoroughly unceremonious fashion, as they were about to board their ships to go home.
British diplomats, like the Americans, never koutou-�ed, and ironically, the
reason for this was that they shared many of the same ‘republican’ ideals
(Ringmar 2006). Members of the British aristocracy took great pride in their
commonsense attitude to life and they were often sceptical of empty ritualism
and blind beliefs. While as a class they were often dismissive of their social inferiors, they had just as much disdain for all claims to absolute power. In their
eyes, their own king was a primus inter pares entirely bereft of sublime
attributes. Not surprisingly, British writers were scathing of the spinelessness of
their fellow Europeans, and the Dutch in particular were endlessly lampooned
(Barrow 1804). And yet the British, much as the Dutch and the Portuguese,
wanted concessions on trade, and for that reason they needed to come to an
agreement with the imperial authorities. The American solution of a partial
treaty concluded in a provincial town was dismissed, however, as being beneath
the dignity of the representatives of the British government.
The British diplomats, in short, were confused, and the confusion was
reflected in their instructions. George Macartney, visiting Beijing in 1793, was
told not to ‘commit the honor of your Sovereign or lessen your own dignity’, yet
neither should he ‘let any trifling punctilio stand in the way of the important
�benefits which may be obtained by engaging the favourable disposition of the
Emperor and his ministers’ (quoted in Pritchard 1943.) Macartney, that is, had
the option to koutou, yet on the day he could not bring himself to do it. Much the
same was true of the mission led by William Amherst in 1816. On the way to
Beijing extensive discussions pro et contra the required prostration took place
among Amherst’s staff. What they hoped for was some kind of face-Â�saving
measure, yet when no compromise was forthcoming, Amherst excused himself
from the audience, insisting he was ill. After being examined by the emperor’s
own doctor, however, the whole embassy was promptly sent packing. Why the
British acted in this manner was impossible for the Chinese to understand. Why
travel so far, at such an expense, and then ruin everything over such a trifle?
The British diplomats were confused since they were torn by conflicting imperatives. They wanted concessions on trade to be sure, but in addition they wanted the
Chinese to treat them with respect. They demanded to be recognised as equals, that
is, they wanted the Chinese to deal with them on European terms. That such recognition was impossible for the Chinese to even consider was �impossible for the
British to understand and they constantly complained about the ‘stubbornness’ and
‘stupidity’ of Chinese officials (see, for example, Lane-Â�Pool 1894). This, in our
terms, was not only a political, but also a cultural conflict. The Euro-�centric and the
Sino-�centric international systems were incommensurate with each other and while
imperial authorities and other visitors found a way to work around these incommensurabilities, the British refused to compromise. The issue was only resolved through
the Opium wars, 1839–1842 and 1856–1860, in which the entire Sino-Â�centric international system was blown to pieces. Once Beijing was occupied and the emperor’s
palace destroyed, there was no more talk of koutou (Ringmar 2012).
78╇╇ E. Ringmar
Where does culture go?
Culture enters our analyses of social phenomena to the extent that the actions of
actors are based on interpretations – and actions are always based on interpretations.
Before we act we must understand what we want, who we are, what kind of a situation we are in, and who the other people in the same situation are and what they
want. Understanding all these things requires interpretations. There are no ‘structures’ without interpretations, no ‘actions’ and no acting selves. The question,
however, is not only what, but also how something means. There is a pragmatics of
discourse, a way of showing and making known through which discursive meanings are turned into shared and socially relevant meanings. In this chapter we briefly
contrasted and compared two such pragmatics – rituals and social performances.
One of the main tasks of a pragmatics of discourse is to present solutions to the
agency–structure problem. That is, to provide social actors with a means of understanding the world they are confronting and the options at their disposal. Social scientists do not analyse these pragmatics as much as to add to them.
This is why, and how, culture matters to a study of international relations.
Anarchy is not real but interpreted, or rather, the interpretations become real
once they are staged, performed, and then acted on. As we have shown this is a
social process, and as such it is delimited by the boundaries of a certain inter�
national society. In this chapter we briefly analysed two such international societies and it was not surprising to find that their respective interpretations of
anarchy varied widely together with the pragmatics through which these interpretations were expressed. In the Sino-�centric international system the units were
unequal, hierarchically ordered and connected through mutual obligations; in the
Euro-�centric system the units were taken as equal, sovereign and free to pursue
their separate goals. The Sino-�centric system was visualised through rituals
whereas the Euro-�centric system was visualised through social performances.
If culture is the property of a particular international society, the question
becomes what happens when different international societies come into conflict
with each other. This was the topic of our historical case-�study. The koutou, as
we saw, was interpreted in entirely different ways in East Asia and in Europe. In
East Asia it was the ritual by which a foreign envoy was inducted into the international system organised by the Chinese. As such it manifested and confirmed a
set of mutual obligations. To the Europeans it was a performance which signified complete submission and thereby national humiliation. Whether the Europeans in Beijing koutou-�ed or not depended on how they felt about performing on
these terms; that is, it depended on how they defined their interests and their
identities. This issue was easily dealt with by legates from Rome and by Russian
diplomats prior to the reign of Peter the Great since both regarded international
politics in similarly ritualistic terms as the Chinese. The issue was easy also for
the Portuguese and the Dutch who did regard the ritual as humiliating, but who
quickly decided that this was a small price to pay for subsequent commercial
�benefits. The issue was easy for the United States too for whom a koutou always
was out of the question. It was instead only Britain that struggled with the issue.
The ritual and performance problem╇╇ 79
What was at stake here was the place Britain saw itself as occupying in international relations. Commercial benefits were important to them too, but more
Â�important still was Britain’s standing in the world. Instead of performing on
Chinese terms, they defied their hosts and eventually destroyed the entire Sino-�
centric international system.
Notes
1 The most detailed description in English is Chun (1989). On the koutou in Sino-�
European relations, see Rockhill (1905).
2 This definition follows Lisa Wedeen (2002).
3 Compare Turner’s discussion of ‘liminal moments’ (1975).
4 As already emphasised by Aristotle (1898).
5 ‘Theory’ and ‘theatre’ share etymological roots in the Greek, theo, meaning ‘seeing’.
6 Compare Turner’s (1975) ‘social drama’, which however has a more restricted definition. See also Alexander (2006).
7 Burke (1969). On the ‘pragmatics of discourse’, see Wedeen (2002).
8 For how this was a fortiori the case for the Jesuits working at the imperial court, see
Mungello (1989).
References
Alexander, Jeffrey C. (2006). Cultural pragmatics: Social performance between ritual and
strategy. In Jeffery C. Alexander, Bernhard Giesen and Jason L. Mast (eds), Social performance: Symbolic action, cultural pragmatics, and ritual (pp.€ 29–90). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press,
Aristotle (1898). The Poetics (translated by Samuel Henry Butcher). London: Macmilllan.
Barrow, John (1804). Travels in China, Containing Descriptions, Observations, and
Comparisons, Made and Collected in the Course of a Short Residence at the Imperial
Palace of Yuen-�Min-Yuen, and on a Subsequent Journey Through the Country, from
Peking to Canton (pp.€9–13). London: T. Cadell & W. Davies.
Burke, Kenneth] (1969 [1914]). A grammar of motives. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Cahen, Gaston (1940 [1914]). Some early Russo–Chinese relations. Shanghai: National
Review Office.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36(3), 245–270.
Chun, Allen J. (1989). The Ching tribute system as guest ritual: A preliminary description. In Proceedings of the Second International Conference on Sinology (pp.€169–208).
Taipei: Academia Sinica.
Dessler, David (1989). What’s at stake in the agent–structure debate? International
Organization, 43(3), 441–473.
Fairbank, John K. (ed.) (1973). The Chinese world order: Traditional China’s foreign
relations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Foster, John W. (1906). The practice of diplomacy as illustrated in the foreign relations
of the United States. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Hamlin, Alan and Jennings, Colin (2011). Expressive political behaviour: Foundations,
scope and implications. British Journal of Political Science, 41(3), 645–670.
80╇╇ E. Ringmar
Johnstone, Barbara (2004). Discourse Analysis and Narrative. In Handbook of Discourse
Analysis (pp.€635–649). Oxford: Blackwell.
Lane-Â�Poole, Stanley (1894). The Life of Sir Harry Parkes, Sometime Her Majesty’s
Minister to China & Japan. Vol 1: Consul in China (p.€376). London: Macmillan.
Mungello, David E. (1989). Curious land: Jesuit accommodation and the origins of
Sinology. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
Nellhaus, Tobin (2000). Social ontology and (meta)theatricality: Reflections on performance and communication in history. Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism, 14(2),
12–20.
New York Times (1859). Important from China: The American Minister at Peking. 16
November.
Pritchard, Earl H. (1943). The kotow in the Macartney embassy to China in 1793. Far
Eastern Quarterly, 2(2), 184.
Ringmar, Erik (2006). Liberal barbarism and the Oriental sublime: The European destruction of the Emperor’s summer palace. Millennium, 34(3), 917–933.
Ringmar, Erik (2012a). Performing international systems: Two East Asian alternatives to
the Westphalian order. International Organization, 66(1), 1–25.
Rockhill, William W. (1905). Diplomatic audiences at the court of China. London: Luzac
& Co.
Satow, Ernest M. (1917). A guide to diplomatic practice, Vol. 2. London: Longmans,
Green, & Co.
Seed, Patricia (1995). Ceremonies of possession in Europe’s conquest of the New World,
1492 – 1640. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Swidler, Ann (2003). Talk of love: How culture matters. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Turner, Victor (1975). Dramas, fields, and metaphors: Symbolic action in human society.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Walker, Julia A. (2006). The text/performance split across the analytic/continental divide.
In David Krasner and David Z. Saltz (eds), Staging philosophy: Intersections of
theater, performance, and philosophy (pp.€ 19–40).. Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press.
Watson Foster, John (1906). The practice of diplomacy as illustrated in the foreign relations of the United States. Boston, MA: Houghton, Mifflin & Co.
Wedeen, Lisa (2002). Conceptualizing culture: Possibilities for political science. American Political Science Review, 96(4), 713–728.
Wendt, Alexander E. (1992). Anarchy is what states make of it: The social construction
of power politics. International Organization, 46(2), 391–425.
Wendt, Alexander E. (1987). The agent–structure problem in International Relations
Theory. International Organization, 41(3), 335–370.
Wills, John E. (1984). Embassies and illusions: Dutch and Portuguese envoys to K’anghis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Asia Center.
Zhang, Feng (2009). Rethinking the ‘Tribute System’: Broadening the conceptual horizon
of historical East Asian politics. Chinese Journal of International Politics, 2, 597–626.
7 Agency and structure in EU
foreign policy practices
Magnus Ekengren
Introduction
One common thread for the students of the European Union’s (EU) foreign
policy is the search for new frameworks of analysis. For the actor-�oriented
observers, this has been important in order to avoid a perspective based on traditional analysis of (national) foreign policy that misses out characteristics particular to the Union (Sjöstedt 1977). For similar reasons, the structurally
interested analysts have wanted to avoid pre-�empirical assumptions of an EU
foreign policy structure that could misguide the investigation and hide a possible
new structural reality (Bretherton and Vogler 1999; Whitman 1998). Naturally
there have been many calls for frameworks able to combine the EU-�as-actor
(agent) and structuralist approaches in empirical study (White 2001: 32). New
terminology has evolved to conceptualise the unique relationship between
agency and structure in EU foreign policy, for example ‘actorness and presence’
(Bretherton and Vogler 1999). All these approaches have formulated the problem
as a tension between, on the one hand, holding investigations as open as possible, in order not to limit the empirical examination unduly, and, on the other,
using well established foreign policy analysis (FPA) categories able to provide a
focus for the same research (Jørgensen 1997; Smith 2003). A central question
has been to what extent the Union could be compared with existing, traditional
foreign policy actors.
This brief recapitulation explains why research on European foreign policy to
such a large extent has been occupied with issues related to induction strategy
and the agency–structure relationship. It also highlights the fundamental importance of Walter Carlsnaes’ ground-Â�breaking studies on agency and structure in
processes of foreign policy change for how the key problematiques in the EU
literature have come to evolve. Carlsnaes showed that the relationship should be
understood as a dynamic process where agents and structures causally condition
each other over time, and made EU students aware of the interplay’s constitutive
nature (Carlsnaes 1992, 1993). In this way he inspired a whole generation of
scholars who were significantly growing in number not least as a result of the
important transformations of European foreign policy from the 1990s. Many of
us are also indebted to Carlsnaes for introducing us to thinkers that, surprisingly,
82╇╇ M. Ekengren
came to have a tremendous impact on international relations theory in general,
such as Anthony Giddens and Pierre Bourdieu. Without this opening up towards
broader strands of social sciences in the thinking about IR and the European
Union many of our dissertations in the 1990s would have looked very different,
or perhaps not even existed. Carlsnaes encouraged us to choose subjects in the
realm of social constructivism, and perhaps most important, hold on to them
when research financing was running out and the pressure for chosing ‘easier’
(theoretical) ways forward was hardening. We are all very thankful for this. In
this chapter I will keep following Carlsnaes’ advice and discuss how agency and
structure can be inductively traced in the evolving practices of EU foreign policy
in recent years.
Purpose
A central critical point of departure for a constructivist approach is that many
existing analyses of the Union’s foreign policy activities is ingrained with ‘scientific’ divisions that distort reality by rationalising them into categories that
have little to do with practical life – with actions in the ‘heat of the moment’.
Pre-�empirical assumptions about the character of the EU-�as-actor and EU-�asstructure and definitions of subject areas that follow official lines of division of
the field (‘common security and defence policy’, ‘area for freedom, security and
justice’) are unduly limiting our search for the structures that generate EU
agency in practice.
The approach in this chapter is that EU foreign policy activities in practice
take place as a whole in time and space, where the agency–structure logic is
other than what is normally presented when action is rationalised after the event.
Building on Bourdieu’s thinking, the theory of practice that is presented transcends prefabricated distinctions by a focus on the everyday work of EU practitioners in a rapidly growing field of EU foreign policy, namely, international
crisis management and humanitarian aid. The chapter discusses the agency –
structure relationship on the basis of the findings of a research programme
carried out over several years at the Swedish National Defence College.1 The
programme includes case studies focusing on the EU’s role in crises such as the
Turkish earthquakes in 1999, the reconstruction of Kosovo from 1999 onwards,
floodings in Central Europe 2002, armed conflicts in the Democratic Republic of
Congo 2003, Portuguese forest fires in 2003, the Madrid bombings in 2004, the
Asian tsunami disaster 2004 and the Haiti earthquake of January 2010. The
empirical focus is chosen because like other researchers in the field, we assume
that it is in the EU’s provision of ‘soft’ security, such as humanitarian aid, that
the ‘translation of presence [structure] into actorness .â•›.â•›. is likely to be more efficacious than the “hard” security of military defence’ (Bretherton and Vogler
1999: 198).
Hopefully the chapter can pass on some agency–structure insights to a new
generation of scholars that currently – with the help of Bourdieu – are not only
renewing the study of European foreign and security policy but contributing to
Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices╇╇ 83
the ‘practice-Â�turn’ in IR-Â�theory in general (Mérand 2008; Pouliot 2010). The following can also be seen as a humble contribution to the development of a theory
of practice of EU crisis and disaster managament that is able to challenge existing realist explanations and the view that national interests determine EU intervention and assistance (Gegout 2005; Versluys 2008).
EU crisis management and humanitarian assistance
Common Security and Defence Policy (CSDP)
The so-�called Petersberg tasks were included in the Amsterdam Treaty 1999
(Article 17) encompassing peace keeping, peacemaking and humanitarian and
rescue operations. CSDP missions should be carried out for the purpose of
peacekeeping, conflict prevention and the strengthening of international security
in accordance with the principles of the UN Charter.2 The Lisbon Treaty (Article
43) expands this list to include disarmament, military cooperation, conflict prevention, fight against terrorism: including cooperation with third country. The
EU’s first independently launched military operation – Operation ARTEMIS in
the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC), in 2003 – was carried out at the
request of the UN (under a Chapter VII resolution).3 There have been six military missions, involving 15,200 troops in total, one peace-�monitoring mission,
six police missions, three rule-�of-law missions and two border management
support missions – in 15 countries and on three continents (Howorth 2007). In
number of personnel they range from legal advice teams of only a handful of
experts to thousands of military troops. With the European External Action
Service in place – the EU high representative leads the external crisis management of the Union. She presides over the EU Council of Foreign Ministers and is
at the same time vice chairman of the EU Commission. The Political and
Security Committee, consisting of the security ambassadors of the member states
prepares the ministers meetings together with the new internal security committee (COSI). These committees are supported by the EU military committee, seconded by a 150 strong military staff, and the Committee for Civil Crisis
Management and the Council Secretariat.
Civil protection
The 11 September 2001 attacks led to the creation of a Community ‘mechanism’
for the compilation and use of member state resources, not only for natural disasters but also terrorist attacks (Ekengren et al. 2006). However, the idea of a
mechanism had already been discussed in relation to the problems of
�co-�ordination of the civil protection intervention teams of the EU member states
to Turkey during the earthquakes in 1999.4 In 2007 the Union developed the
mechanism into ‘A Community Civil Protection Mechanism’ and set the parameters for the development of a European rapid response capability based on
civil protection modules of the member states. With the rise of the Common
84╇╇ M. Ekengren
Security and Defence Policy (CSDP) member states ensured that also the mechanism could be used to coordinate events both inside and outside the EU (Duke
and Ojanen 2006). The mechanism has been employed externally several times
since its establishment. After the 11 September 2001 events more than 1,000
rescue workers from the member states were co-�ordinated through the mechanism for missions across the Atlantic (de Wijk 2004). The Monitoring and Information Centre of the mechanism (MIC) has launched requests for assistance
in connection with the oil accident caused by the Prestige tanker outside the
Spanish coast in the autumn of 2002.5 In 2006 the mechanism for the first time
was used in a war situation when it helped member states to evacuate their citizens from Lebanon and coordinated European experts for the education of
locals to clean up the oil spill caused by Israeli bombing. Major disasters where
assistance was requested includes the Prestige accident (2002); earthquakes in
Algeria (2003), Iran (2003, 2004, 2005), Morocco (2004) and Pakistan (2005);
the tsunami in South Asia (2004, 2005); forest fires in Portugal (2003, 2004,
2005); floods in Romania and Bulgaria (2005); and Hurricanes Katrina and Rita
in the US (2005) and Haiti (2010).6 National participation in EU civil protection
cooperation has steadily grown (Hollis 2010).
Humanitarian aid
The mandate of the European Community Humanitarian Aid department
(ECHO) is to provide emergency assistance and relief to the victims of natural
disasters or armed conflict outside the European Union.7 Since 1992, when
ECHO was established, it has funded humanitarian aid in crisis zones in more
than 85 countries via partners such as NGOs and the UN Disaster Assessment
and Coordination (UNDAC), UNHCR, UN-�OCHA8 and the Red Cross. ECHO
grants cover emergency aid, food aid and aid to refugees and displaced persons
worth a total of more than €700 million per year (in parity with US humanitarian
aid). The legal basis of the ECHO, created in 1996, states that sole aim of EU
aid ‘is to prevent or relieve human suffering’, resulting from natural disasters or
human-�made crises such as wars.9 The EU humantitarian assistance competence
was included in the treaties for the first time through Article 214 of the Lisbon
Treaty, where it is shared with the member states. The Union has now the right
to conclude agreements with other international organisations and to increase
Â�coordination between the EU and the member states. While the EU’s civil protection provides for ‘first aid’ assistance in the intervention and relief phase,
ECHO is mainly involved in the recovering phase and the rebuilding of infrastructure. The civil protection mechanism identifies the public service resources
of the member states, while ECHO is engaging non-�governmental organisations
and is dependent on the partners it can find in the field due to the fact that it has
no operational capacity of its own. Civil protection assistance is only provided in
response to a request from the relevant state. Humanitarian aid through EU-�
ECHO provides non-�discriminatory humanitarian emergency assistance regardless of any request or agreement from the country hit by disaster.
Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices╇╇ 85
Towards a theory of practice of EU crisis management
The theory of practice that Pierre Bourdieu developed is strikingly applicable to
the problematiques of EU FPA. He offers an inductive method for empirical
studies able to integrate an analysis of agency’s room of manouvre vis-Â�à-vis
structure in a strong focus on everyday practice (Bourdieu 1990). In the following I draw on an earlier application of Bourdieu’s theories in the study of the
post-�national time logic of European governance and how it affects European
policy making and institutions (Ekengren 2002).
Bourdieu conceives of structure (habitus) as an unconscious memory of past
experiences for future use disposing agents with a ‘knowledge’ of how ‘to go
on’ (practical sense) in their practice.10 He constructs, via interpretation, an
objective world of relations, an objective structure. The so-�called structural
method is the same as in traditional structural theory; it is the search for the
social relations that generates the practice of agents. However, the structure
under investigation should not be assumed in advance, and only thereafter tested
by means of empirical data. Instead, it should ‘crystallise’ in the process of
empirical investigation, in what Bourdieu calls ‘the second break’. The
researcher should try to situate himself in the position of the subject at the very
moment when the act is taking place. In order to relate the agent’s own ‘feeling’
of his practice and the objective structure constructed by the researcher,
Bourdieu uses the concept of habitus.11
In this way, we not only avoid assessing EU actors’ practices only from the
outside, from the viewpoint of an ‘objective’ structure constructed by the
researcher, but also a perspective based only on subjective or ‘visible’ (in a positivistic sense) social phenomena – a view that has tended to produce a-Â�historical
assumptions about EU actorness and agency. Thus, structure is supposed to crystallise in our gradually growing understanding of how practices of EU foreign
policy are created and organised, and based on a combination of actors’ subjective views and our objective interpretations.
In the case studies carried out in the research programme referred to above
we reconstruct what the most closely involved EU actors do in practice. It is
these micro-�level practices that structure the field. Our sole pre-�empirical
assumption is that there exists structures that generate EU agency. This looser
type of hypothesis is based on a preliminary familiarity of the area. It is not a
‘testable’ hypothesis in the positivistic sense. Instead, these first steps of the
investigation should provide material for the construction of systems of social
relations, generating hypotheses which later on can be tested by sociological
method, such as systematic ethnographic observation.12 The aim of the method is
to throw light on new practices and define the object of study step by step.
Bourdieu argues that we should not exclude ‘any’ of the relations and contacts
of the actor beforehand. Systems of relations should instead crystallise during
the process of collection of data. In other words, systems are not supposed to be
included in the premises of€the study but should instead appear as a result of the
investigation. The risk of leaving any significant facts – a particular EU style of
86╇╇ M. Ekengren
foreign policy – in the dark due to the use of prefabricated conceptions originating
from the study of nation-�states, other international organisations or other fields of
European integration should be minimised. The task is to reveal the generative
structure that lies closest to the agent. Union actions are seen as a creator as well
as an outcome of structure. EU agency is seen as a product of a feeling (sense) for
‘how to go on’ in relation to the structure searched for and constructed.
As with all inductive strategies there is no exact in before-�hand given level of
empirical findings when structural conclusions should be drawn. All empirical
analysis is always a mixture of continuous observation and decoding. In our
case, EU foreign policy structure exists to the extent the actors of the field attach
importance to it and we can observe it as generator of action, when trying to put
ourself in the actor’s situation. Hence, an actor’s refering to national ‘interests’
in her own description of what determines EU action is not enough evidence for
the lack of an EU structure, perhaps more important in the generation of her or
his action. Only by combining this subjectivist fact with an objectivist knowledge of social relations and actors’ un-Â�conscious sense of ‘how to go on’ in the
field, can we construct an objective structure.
How should we recognise and value significant social relations when we see
them? The agent is always operating in a social context – a field, where the participants have in common a set of recognised social ‘capital’, which is at stake and
over which they struggle. The capital consists of the specific competences,
resources and recognition that are considered to be of value in the field. The field
is also defined by the specific rules, questions, methods and style of risk taking
and investments for the gaining of capital. The ‘tension’ of the field depends on
the distribution of capital between the participants. A field with high tension is a
field where there exists an uneven spread of capital, for example differences of
competence and legitimation in the political field. According to Bourdieu,
habitus is the result of experiences of similar situations and social relations
where the degree of similarity to a high degree depends on the tension. The aim
of this tool of induction is to increase our sensitivity for the unwritten as well as
unspoken rules of conduct in our search for relations of high generative significance. What capital is the driving force for action in our field of study? What are
the specific competences and resources? Who is in practice given the legitimate
right to act?
Structure and agency in EU practices
As mentioned, the conclusions in this section are the result of a dozen of case
studies of the EU’s crisis management and humanitarian aid based on participant
observations, in-�depth interviews and written sources covering a wide range of
official and informal documents. Taken together the cases give an indication of
how EU policymakers go on in the field. They show the ‘commonsensical’
meaning EU agents attribute to their own, un-�conscious, future-�oriented practices when faced with crisis and natural disaster. In this way they constitute an
important contribution to the construction of habitus in the ‘EU collectivity’ that
Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices╇╇ 87
generates Union activities. Do members of this collectivity take their engagement in the crisis for granted in everyday life, or not?
It is of course impossible to examine all actors of the ‘collectivity’ of EU
institutions and member states. The strategy has been to select groups of practitioners that are more representative of the collective habitus than others. The
implication is a lean towards officials at lower-Â�level of admistration and ‘first
responders’. Decision makers at higher political levels – in the capitals of the EU
member states and in the EU Council of Ministers – are not as central to the
object of study as they normally are in investigations of EU decision making.
The focus is of course highly problematic from a realist perspective that emphasises the fact that EU activities in the area of crisis management and humanitarian aid remain within the realm of intergovernmental decision-�making rules. It is
the governments of the EU member states that ultimately decide when and how
the EU should act. This is the reason, argues the realist, why national interests
should be in focus in explanations of EU action.
But again, the aim is not to define moments of formal, central government decisison making but to reconstruct the underlying common sense that dispose the EU
collectivity for the practices of engagement and handling of international crisis.
The task is to select groups of people that are representative ‘producers’ and
holders of these tacit underlying trends, that is, the ‘background knowledge’ in the
EU collectivity. In the emirical investigations it has been assumed that a key group
consists of the actors who first try to make sense of the crisis, communicate their
views and proposals for action upwards in the hierarchies for formal approval of
their practices, and, implement the same formal decisions, that are – as we have
discovered – very often in line with the practical logics of first responders in the
field. What do these people sense as self-�evident when confronted with crisis?
Each case study started off by focusing on the group of EU officials directly
confronted by crisis and humanitarian disaster, normally Commission and EU
agency officials. This group functions as the core from which further ‘circles’ of
relations are mapped. The aim has been to ‘follow’ and reconstruct their actions
over time with the help of a variety of empirical material that can help sketch the
contours of structure and generate hypotheses for further research.13
In the following it is only possible to give a glimpse of the conclusions on
structure and agency drawn from these detailed studies that account for practices
on a day-�by-day, and often hour-�by-hour, basis.14 The aim is to exemplify the
potential of a focus on the logic of EU practicality in international crisis as a way
to illustrate the interplay between agency and structure.
Structure
There are many indications of a habitus making it self-�evident to act in situations
of international crises and natural disasters. The Union’s officials and first
responders in the Commission and EU agencies, such as ECHO, have embodied
a practical sense that disposes them to engage. A tacit ‘background knowledge’
has evolved that simply makes it natural to act in such situations.
88╇╇ M. Ekengren
Habitus also includes a sense of the symbolic power struggle between the EU
actors and representatives of other international crisis managers over intervention, resources and division of labour. Formally, the field of international
crisis management and humanitarian aid is made up of distinct and overlapping
international organisations and national-�states with equal status, responsibilites
and actions, resulting from a non-�hierarchical order with regard to the legitimacy
of the various players. In practice, however, the studied EU actors reveal a structure of greater generative significance; a structural whole originating from ‘inter-Â�
organisational’ symbolic power struggles and informal hierarchies.
A well recognised possession of instruments for crisis management and
humanitarian aid seems to be the condition for participation in the field. A good
‘track-Â�record’ from earlier crises generates symbolic capital and respect. The
field is held together by a common set of recognised values that can be illustrated by the strategic issues that guide the international actors that have gained a
legitimate right to act in the eyes of other. These include, of course, the general
humanitarian and political ones, but also when and in what way should the crisis
management intervention and assistance begin?’ On the demand of whom? On
the basis of what information? Who should take the lead?
What will other actors than the EU do (NATO, the UN, etc.)? How should the
needs be defined? What are the medium and longer term tasks? Indeed, it is difficult to understand the character of the field without including the practical
sense that can in the heat-Â�of-moment ‘answer’ these questions. A sense which
depends on the inter-�organisational tension and the tacit evaluation of competences and experiences gained from earlier crises.
At stake is the elaboration and diffusion of the legitimate principles of geographical and resource limits for international humanitarian aid action. Basically,
the principle concerns the question of how the global scene of crisis and disaster
should be divided and how management responsibilities should be defined. The
ultimate goal for each international player is to achieve a monopoly of providing
these principles and thereby of the mobilisation of resources, groups, states, non-�
governmental organisations etc. This would make their own particular tools
objectified instruments of power.15 ‘At the back of their minds’, the involved
actors attach a lot of importance to this tension in their everyday work and planning for future situations. It is the unquestioned conviction of all the participants
that the struggle concerns these principles and that to a large extent holds the
field together. Key social relations for the generative structure are the ones in
which this struggle is expressed. This makes it not very meaningful to trace and
isolate moments of ‘EU actions’ in the construction of structure (habitus), independent from the other main actors. Instead it is more correct to view the field as
structured by relational practices and tensions in overlapping international organisations. See Figure 7.1.
The competences, resources and instruments by the means of which the symbolic capital in the field are achieved are distributed unevenly among the actors.
This creates a tension that is un-Â�consciously ‘remembered’ by the actors and
forms their ‘knowledge’ of how to go on. The uneven distribution among the
Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices╇╇ 89
UN-OCHA
Council of Europe
EADRCC
NATO
EU/ECHO
Figure 7.1╇International actors involved in crisis management and humanitarian aid
Assistance.
main aid organs – EU-Â�ECHO, NATO-Â�EADRCC,16 UN-Â�OCHA, the Council of
Europe – often leads to a tension that can explain the peculiar mix of coordination and competition in the field. Formally, every international actor is
supposed to contribute a unique piece of the puzzle. In practice, they are largely
overlapping, which makes each and every actor a part of a larger process they
have in common. Of high generative significance is the channeling of resources
of the international organisations from their member states to their humanitarian
aid organs for implementation through contracts with non-�governmental actors
closely cooperating with local authorities. There are a lot of tensions in these
processes due for example to habitus’ ‘forgotten memory’ of the performance of
the NGOs in the past. The international structure is characterised by information
and decision networks of international organisations and non-�governmental
implementation. It is a structure of non-�governmental implementation of non-�
state decisions.
Because the EU practices are so intertwined with other organisations’ activities – horizontally as well as vertically in nearly all phases of action – they are
part of an international structuration. The integration in practical life is so tight
that to conceive of a distinct EU foreign policy structure would only distort
reality. Together with other international organisations possessing the recognised
means and competences, EU actions both create and are the outcome of an international network. Consequently, the structure we are searching for in our study
90╇╇ M. Ekengren
of EU foreign policy might not be an ‘EU structure’. Instead our investigation so
far points to an evolving international structure of crisis management.
To sum up, the habitus of EU officials is oriented towards engagement and
management in international crisis and disaster, and is adjusted to other actors’
moves so as to stay within the limits set by the unwritten division of labour and
competition resulting from the field’s tension. On the basis of our case studies
we can now tentatively define the interplay between EU agency and international
structure.
Agency
Explaining EU agency only as a function of the revealed ‘international’ structure
would leave out the choices of action in which the particular logic of EU crisis
management might reside. It would risk seeing the EU actors as structural dopes.
Neither would a one-�sided focus on the freedom of choice, constructed on the
basis of subjective views of alternatives of action account for the structural constraints. It would overlook the complex agency–structure relationship in the
many times un-�reflected strategic EU behaviours (which depend) on the current
tension of the field. This includes not only the competition between the (potential) organisations involved but the strategic timing in the choices of action.
In our case studies, the EU actors’ own sense of the situation was to a large
extent determined by strategic time calculations of ‘the right moment’ for when
decisions for crisis management could be taken, announced, implemented and
prolonged. Plans were made both consciously in coordination with other organs
and in the form of unconscious adjustments to foreseen up-�coming events. From
the perspective of timing there were no independent EU, NATO, Council of
Europe, UN or NGO actions. Instead, these were taken simultaneously,
sequenced into each other over time and synchronised with the help of strategic
calculations, predictions, anticipations, timing considerations – ‘when’–Â�
questions. This does not mean that there was no overlapping and duplication of
measures taken among the various actors. The synchronisation aimed at is not
provided for by any formal leader, but achieved by the sharing of the same information, a hierarchy based on symbolic capital giving the UN a privileged
status, and a sensitivity of each other’s status, competences, resources and
moves, i.e. symbolic power. Tacit, unreflected, adjustment rather than conscious
coordination shaped the interrelationships in the field. The very little knowledge
of each others’ existence in the field, at least according to the interview answers,
gives evidence to this interpretation. This ignorance was particularly striking in
the case of the relation between the EU-�ECHO and NATO-�EADRCC.
Some examples of EU agency, the case of the Turkish earthquakes (1999) for
example, show that it was not self-Â�evident that the European Commission –
despite the ‘international’ structure – should continue its crisis management in
the reconstruction phase as well. There were choices for the Union representatives. The strategic moves by Commissioner van den Broek (responsible for
humanitarian aid) and President Tarja Hallonen (EU president at the time), on
Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices╇╇ 91
behalf of the Union were instrumental for the Union’s eventual decision to
prolong its aid to Turkey into the reconstruction phase. There was room for subjective manouvre in the strategic forestalling of EU decisions of funding by van
den Broek (that did not exist when he took the initiative). He based this on his
‘sense’ of a widespread feeling of European responsibility that eventually would
result in formal decisions. Habitus disposed him for an action adapted to what he
foresaw, towards the future. In ‘the heat of the moment’ the agent adjusts his
action not only to what he sees in the present but what he foresees in an upcoming future, i.e. the ‘objective probabilities’ (Bordieu 1990: 81). In turn, the high-Â�
level actions were only the top of an ice-�berg which was shaped by European
contacts and international coordination structuring the field at lower levels at an
earlier stage which preceeded the earthquake. Thus, the strategic room for man�
ouvre of Union representatives was not only defined by the international structure
but also by complex intra-�institutional contacts and bargains within the Union.
The European dimension of crises such as the reconstruction of Kosovo 1999,
floodings in Central Europe 2002, Portuguese forest fires in 2003 and the Madrid
bombings in 2004 was from the outset recognised by the EU collectivity which
prompted it to act swiftly and forcefully in order not to jeopardise any trust�
worthiness with regard to taking a ‘European responsibility’. The common
concern of this symbolic capital was a strong driving force behind agency.
Habitus generated action for the protection of this capital. The capital was so
�important that the financial resources allocated for the crisis management were,
almost in all cases, not rationally calculated in relation to the size of the disaster
and did not stand in proportion to the possibility of practical implementation.
The engagement of institutions such as the European Parliament and the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe with no formal mandate and with
little competence in crisis management and humanitarian aid, further witnessed
of the strong symbolic basis of action.
Our findings point to a new type of collective action for the EU agents
involved. The agency–structure relationship reveals an EU actorness that could
be defined as the capacity of the various actors to draw on ‘international’ structure in a synchronised manner. The tacit synchronisation for simultaneous action
is based on informal leadership in horizontal networks, often held together by a
strong feeling of European responsibility. Perhaps we are witnessing the contours of a unique dynamics and style of foreign policy agency? The existence of
this agency might be analysed in terms of whether the agents drawing on the
same structure also do it at the same time. This is in contrast to a definition based
on formal organisational affiliations or material actor capabilities and interests.
Our practice oriented approach helps us to define a new meaning of actorness
better suited for the difficult examination of the EU’s role in international crisis
management and humanitarian aid. EU agency is a question of to what an extent
the actors disposed by the international structure, are – not only asserting a presence – but are acting in the same ‘present’.
Our findings provide evidence of a distinct logic of practicality for the EU’s
foreign policy role, unique in structure as well as agency. This can hardly be
92╇╇ M. Ekengren
subject to traditional foreign policy analysis. Our conclusions also challenge traditional explanations of EU foreign policy outcome as only ‘sub-Â�optimal’, ‘in-Â�
efficient’, awaiting future transformation into a more efficient ‘normal’ style.
The case studies on the agency–structure relationship have indicated that EU
foreign policy, rather than being sub-�optimal, might have a logic of its own.
Notes
╇ 1 Programme for European Security Research (EUROSEC).
╇ 2 United Nations, Charter of the United Nations, www.un.org/aboutun/charter/.
╇ 3 Ulriksen (2004:€508–525).
╇ 4 Interview, 11 February 2003.
╇ 5 Interview with an official from the Commission’s civil protection unit, Directorate-Â�
General for environment, 13 February 2003.
╇ 6 http://ec.europa.eu/environment/civil/prote/mechanism.htm.
╇ 7 Regulation (CE) n° 1257/96.
╇ 8 United Nations Office for the Coordination of Humanitarian Affairs.
╇ 9 http://ec.europa.eu/echo/about/what/history_en.htm.
10 Behind the concept of logic of practice is the assumption that there is a fundamental
difference between the logic of science and the logic of practice. The difference lies
mainly in the perception and concept of time; while practice is inseparable from temporality, science is, according to Bourdieu, built on ‘intemporal time’. ‘Science has a
time which is not that of practice’ (1990:€81). Bourdieu admits that it is very difficult
to conceptualise and describe practice: ‘The logicism inherent in the objectivist viewpoint inclines one to ignore the fact that scientific construction cannot grasp the principles of practical logic without forcibly changing their nature’ (ibid.:€90).
11 Habitus can be thought of as ‘forgotten history’. This unconscious capacity for action
has been described by Bourdieu as the result of incorporation into habitus of the
objective structures for future-�oriented practices. Thus, habitus is shaped but not
determined by social processes (Bourdieu 1977: 78). A ‘strategic’ act is an act by
which the agent consciously tries to do something different from that which, through
habitus, she normally would do. With the concept of strategy, Bourdieu shows that it
is indispensable to account for the subject’s own view of his situation in order to fully
explain actions. However, Bourdieu strongly emphasises that strategic calculations
‘are first defined, without any calculation, in relation to objective potentialities, immediately inscribed in the present as things to do or not to do, to say or not to say, in
relation to a probable, “upcoming” future’ (1990:€ 53). In this way, he places the
freedom of the subject within a ‘framework of possibility’.
12 Bourdieu has used the so-�called correspondence analysis for the mapping of fields.
The method has been applied to inter alia aspects of the cultural (Bourdieu 1979:€209,
296, 392) and academic field in France (1984:€73, 111). He has developed this method
on the ground of a critical assessment of traditional statistics, which, according to
him, apriori presume that a certain correlation is of higher importance, and more decisive for the position and action of the studied objects, than others. The model should
in Bourdieu’s words follow data, and not the other way around. By the means of qualitative data, Bourdieu and his students create two dimensional ‘maps’ over the actors’
position in the field.
13 The interviews were conducted using ‘open’ questions, facilitating in-Â�depth conversations about the experience of the respondents, but also a ‘reading between the lines’
of what could be interpreted as the informants’ implicit and unreflected commonsense. That is, the ‘background knowledge’ that generated his practice. The interviews
lasted approximately one hour each. First, we spoke mainly with representatives from
Agency and structure in EU foreign policy practices╇╇ 93
the Commission. In all cases, we plan to complement the existing material with interviews with EU member state representatives, other Union organs and local actors.
Although we have conducted a number of interviews with the implementers of
ECHO’s humanitarian assistance (e.g. UNHCR and the International Federation of
the Red Cross), we are far from having included all NGO perspectives. Although
many of the central decision-�makers at mid-�level are included in our studies, we do
not sufficiently cover those at the top-Â�level (for example, the Commissioners’
Cabinet). Time is also a problem as these interviews were conducted after the crises
(one year after the Turkish earthquakes, three years after the start of Kosovo reconstruction, two years after the tsunami, etc.). People tend to forget things over time and
to (consciously or unconsciously) alter their descriptions. It should be noted, however,
that oral material is but one of the many sources used in this study. By comparing the
content of interviews with that of official documents – reports, press releases, media
material, policies and regulations–we were able to view the interview material with a
critical eye.
14 The full case studies are found in Ramberg (2005), Ekengren et al. (2006), Ekengren
(2007), Boin et al. (2007) and Myrdal (2010).
15 In analogy with ‘objectified political capital’ (Bourdieu 1991: 181).
16 Euro-�Atlantic Disaster Response Coordination Centre (EADRCC).
References
Boin, A., Ekengren, M. and Rhinard, M. (eds) (2007). Protecting the European Union:
Policies, sectors and institutional solutions. Report ACTA B 38. Stockholm: National
Defence College.
Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a theory of practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Bourdieu, P. (1979). La distinction – critique sociale du jugement. Paris: Les Editions de
Minuit.
Bourdieu, P. (1984). Homo Academicus. Paris: Les Editions de Minuit.
Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bourdieu, P. (1991). Language and symbolic power. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bretherton, C. and Vogler, J. (1999). The European Union as a global actor. London:
Routledge.
Carlsnaes, W. (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36, 245–270.
Carlsnaes, W. (1993). On analysing the dynamics of foreign policy change: A critique
and reconceptualization. Cooperation and Conflict, 28(1), 5–30.
Duke, S. and Ojanen, H. (2006). Bridging internal and external security: Lessons from the
European security and defence policy. Journal of European Integration, 28, 477–494.
Ekengren, M. (2002). The time of European governance. Manchester: Manchester
�University Press.
Ekengren, M., Matzén, N., Rhinard, M. and Svantesson, M. (2006). Solidarity or sovereignty? EU cooperation in civil protection. Journal of European Integration, 28(5),
457–476.
Ekengren, M., Matzén, N. and Svantesson, M. (2006). The new security role of the European Union – Transnational crisis management and the protection of Union citizens.
Report ACTA B 35. Stockholm: National Defence College.
Ekengren, M. (2007). EU civil protection and the flooding in Austria, the Czech Republic, Germany and Slovakia 2002. In M. Britz, O. Bures, M. Ekengren, H. Moroff and
94╇╇ M. Ekengren
C.-E. Stålvant (eds), Challenges and opportunities for societal security in an enlarged
European Union. Report ACTA B 39. Stockholm: National Defence College.
Gegout, C. (2005). Causes and consequences of the EU’s military intervention in the
Democratic Republic of Congo: A realist explanation. European Foreign Affairs
Review, 10(3), 427–443.
Hollis, S. (2010). National participation in EU civil protection. Report ACTA B 42.
Stockholm: National Defence College.
Howorth, J. (2007). Security and defence in the European Union. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Jørgensen, K.E. (1997). Introduction. In K.E. Jørgensen (ed.), Reflective approaches to
European governance. London: Macmillan.
Merand, F. (2008). European defence policy: Beyond the nation state. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Myrdal, S. (2010). Signature case: The Haiti earthquake 2010. Paper presented at the conference navigating the Boundaries of EU crisis management, Sainte Maxime, 26–27
April.
Pouliot, V. (2010). International security in practice: The politics of NATO–Russia diplomacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ramberg, B. (2005). The two earthquakes in Turkey in 1999: International coordination
and the European Commission’s preparedness. In S. Larsson, E.-K. Olsson and B.
Ramberg (eds), Crisis decision making in the European Union. Crismart Publication
,Vol. 29. Stockholm: National Defence College.
Sjöstedt, G. (1977). The external role of the European Community. Farnborough: Saxon
House.
Smith, M. (2003). Europe’s foreign and security policy: The institutionalization of cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ulriksen, S., Gourlay, C. and Mace, C. (2004). Operation Artemis: The shape of things to
come? International Peacekeeping, 11(3), 508–525.
Versluys, H. (2008). Depoliticising and Europeanising humanitarian aid: Success or
failure? Perspectives on European Politics and Society, 9(2), 208–224.
Wijk, R. de (2004). Civil defence and solidarity clause: EU homeland defence. Paper prepared for the Directorate-�General for Research of the European Parliament, Brussels, 5
January.
White, B. (2001). Understanding European foreign policy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Whitman, R.G. (1998). From civilian power to superpower? The international identity of
the European Union. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
8 Agents, structures and
international regime significance
Charles F. Parker
Interest in international regimes has grown as states increasingly assemble and
enter into rule-�based governance arrangements to direct behaviour and solve
problems in a variety of issue areas, such as trade, security, human rights and the
environment. Much of the scholarship on international cooperation, regimes,
law, and institutions has focused on the debate over the importance and efficacy
of international institutions, with the bulk of the attention being devoted to the
subject of compliance (Parker 2011).
Many scholars have maintained that regimes are superfluous and that power
relations are the most reliable predictor of international outcomes and states
often strive to avoid complying with inconvenient obligations (Strange 1983:
345; Mearsheimer 1994/1995; Thayer 1995). In cases where compliance rates
are high, these scholars tend to see the outcome as the result of shallow agreements that reflect the law of the least ambitious party or have merely codified
what states would have done even in the absence of an agreement (Downs et al.
1996). Elsewhere, I have maintained that international regimes are not necessarily ephemeral reflections of power capabilities and that since regimes are
plentiful and potentially persuasive, more work should be done to evaluate their
strengths and weaknesses and to pinpoint the specific ways particular regimes
make or fail to make a difference in their issue areas (Parker 1999, 2001). There
is now a great deal of scholarship devoted to this undertaking (Miles et al.
2001; Breitmeier et al. 2006), although much of it has concerned itself somewhat narrowly with compliance (Chayes and Chayes 1993; 1995; Downs et al.
1996; Dorn and Fulton 1997; Simmons 1998). But the relationship between
compliance and significance is a murky one (Simmons and Martin 2002). I
maintain that compliance is not sufficient for effectiveness let alone a broader
conception of regime significance. I believe that the scholarship expressing
skepticism that international regimes can be significant determinants of state
behaviour or the work that has focused narrowly on the issue of compliance has
done so, at least in part, because of a truncated view that regimes should be
treated primarily as structural constraints or injunctions that may or may not be
observed by states.
In this chapter, I want to make the case that if we as scholars are to meaningfully engage with the question of regime significance, there is a need for greater
96╇╇ C.F. Parker
conceptual clarity and that our ability to make sense of regime significance
would benefit from a sophisticated understanding of agency and structure as
exemplified in the work of Walter Carlsnaes (1992, 1994, 2008).
International regimes (re)conceptualized
International regimes, simply put, are issue-�area specific multilateral arrangements designed to govern behaviour and address a particular set of transnational
problems. Regimes should be considered as social institutions that consist of
some combination of identifiable agreed upon or practiced principles, norms,
rules, procedures, and programmes (Krasner 1983: 2; Levy et al. 1995: 274;
Young 1999: 10).
When utilizing the regime approach, it is important to heed James Rosenau’s
caveat that regimes are not independent actors in their own right (1986: 881). As
critics, such as Andreas Behnke (1993: 18–19; 1995), have noted, practitioners
of traditional regime approaches are often guilty of treating regimes as actors
with independent causal power of their own. On the other end of the spectrum
another group of scholars has treated regimes primarily as structural constraints
or ‘explicit injunctions’ (see, for example, Haggard and Simmons 1987: 495;
Jervis 1983). Properly understood, regimes are not treated as independent actors
or solely as structural constraints, but as arrangements with complex agency–
structure dynamics that provide a structured setting for interaction within a realm
of international life and which can give rise to and enable entities – such as secretariats, organizations, and agencies – that, as components of the regime, can
act in various ways in specific domains. Following Carlsnaes (1992, 2008), it is
best to discard conceptualizations that treat agents and structures in a mutually
exclusive fashion. Instead, regimes should be regarded as enabling and constraining arrangements that are constitutive of complex and interactive agency–
structure characteristics and dynamics.
International regimes are agent induced attempts to create arrangements and
competencies that attempt to bind targeted actors to certain rules, and aspire to
govern both states and groups within states. Regimes can be desirable because
they represent attempts to bring things in line with higher objectives. However,
regimes should be seen as more than just structural constraints on states1: they
also enable state action by creating a distinct context for it to take place.
Regimes, as Robert Keohane has shown (1984: 97–98, 100–102, 114–115), can
be used to provide information, reduce transaction costs, and stabilize mutual
expectations regarding future behaviour by providing a ‘long shadow of the
future’, all of which can result in reductions in uncertainty and insecurity. Similarly, Keohane and Hoffmann (1993: 395–402) identify six roles for international institutions such as regimes: (1) as arenas for the exercise of influence; (2)
as mechanisms to constrain bargaining strategies; (3) as instruments to balance
against or replace other institutions; (4) as tools to signal governments’ intentions; (5) as ‘templates’ for policy choice; and (6) as instruments to affect the
preferences of states.
Agents, structures, international regime significance╇╇ 97
An effective regime is used to persuasively influence state behaviour within
its issue area. International regimes can have an intersubjective affect on the
international environment by providing arenas for state action and socialization
that can meaningfully influence the collective reproduction of the international
system and potentially contribute to its transformation.2 Regimes are arrangements, or enablers, that states create and work through and in cooperation with
to accomplish certain objectives or outcomes.
Institutions, regimes and organizations
Within the IR literature it is not uncommon for the terms institutions, regimes
and organizations to be used indiscriminately, interchangeably, contradictorily
or without adequate definition or explanation (see, for example, Hoffmann 1998:
57–58; Martin and Simmons 1998; Gruber 2000). Because these terms have
been used inconsistently and the relationship among them often goes unspecified, a considerable degree of conceptual confusion exists.3 I will simplify this
complex subject as I see it in what follows and provide a working sketch of how
these concepts can be understood and how they relate to one another.
March and Olsen (1989: 160) have defined institutions as ‘collections of
interrelated rules and routines that define appropriate actions in terms of relations between roles and situations’.4 According to Robert Keohane, international
relations are institutionalized in the sense that ‘much behavior is recognized by
participants as reflecting established rules, norms, and conventions, and its
meaning is interpreted in light of these understandings’ (1989: 1).5 Institutional
forms vary and can range from the general and informal to the specific and
formal (cf. Keohane 1989: 3–5; Keohane et al. 1993: 4–5). International regimes,
formal international organizations, and conventions (informal practices) have all
been identified as institutional forms (Keohane 1989: 3–5).
Although both regimes and organizations can be seen as institutional forms, it
must be underlined that they are not synonymous (Hasenclever et al. 1997:
10–11). 6 However, a formal organization or agency can be a component of a
regime. Regime arrangements or complexes may or may not be attached to or
give rise to a formal international organization (cf. Hasenclever 1997: 10–11;
Haas 1990, 172–173; Young 1980: 332–333).
Formal organizations are concrete material entities possessing physical locations (headquarters), offices, budgets, equipment, a staff and legal personalities
(Young 1989: 32; 1999: 7; Archer 1992: 2–3). Organizations are ‘purposive’ entities and have the (circumscribed) capacity to act (Keohane 1989: 3–4; Hasenclever
et al. 1997: 11). Broadly speaking, there are two main varieties of international
organizations: intergovernmental organizations (IGOs) and cross-�national nongovernmental or international non-governmental (INGOs) organizations.7 This
chapter is primarily concerned with the former, because the international organizations that accompany and support regimes tend to be of the IGO variety.8
Unlike perspectives that treat international organizations simply as arenas in
which actors pursue interests or as little more than permanent conferences
98╇╇ C.F. Parker
(cf. Buzan and Little 2000: 266–267), I contend that international organizations
can act independently and exercise power autonomously from the states that
created them (Reinalda and Verbeek 1998; Barnett and Finnemore 1999).9
Although many international organizations can act autonomously, it is important
to recognize that this capacity is not boundless. In the case of autonomous international organizations, while they may have a legal personality separate from
their members, independent powers granted by their constitutions, and organs to
act independently, they are still a collectivity of states and must be regarded as
bounded agents with specific and circumscribed competencies delimited to particular areas of international life. The WTO in realm of trade,10 the IAEA in the
realm of nuclear energy and nuclear non-�proliferation, and the OPCW in the
realm of chemical weapons control are examples of entities that could be termed
as bounded agents, because while they have considerable powers and freedom of
action, these are not unlimited nor equivalent to those held by states.11 Thus, in
line with scholars such as Keohane (1989) and Haas (1990),12 I take the position
that international organizations can be viewed as purposive agents, but that their
agency (ability to act) is circumscribed.
The study of formal international organizations has a long history and there is
a vast literature on the subject that I will not go into here.13 Instead, I will elaborate a bit further on the relationship of regimes and organizations and I will concisely discuss the status of organizations as autonomous actors and as arenas for
interaction.
Regimes can function without international organizations, although in some
cases they are accompanied by organizations designed to support them in various
ways. Conceptually, regimes are superordinate to their accompanying organizations (Haas 1990: 172). Thus, these organizations should be understood as components of the overarching regime (ibid.: 53, 172). For example, the nuclear
non-�proliferation regime and the chemical weapons control regime both have
formal organizations as component parts. In the case of the nuclear non-�
proliferation regime, an existing international organization, the IAEA, International Atomic Energy Agency was formally tied to the NPT.14 While in the case
of the chemical weapons control regime, the CWC (Article VIII) provided for
the creation of an international organization, the Organization for the Prohibition
of Chemical Weapons (OPWC). Many of the regime’s rules and procedures can
be located in the organizations that are attached to them.
Depending on their autonomy and powers,15 organizations also can perform a
host of activities and functions on behalf of the regime and the regime’s member
states, including the provision of information, the monitoring and verification of
compliance16 and the sanctioning of non-�compliance. Additional influence can
be exerted through agenda setting activities, policy-�making, and policy implementation. Organizations also can serve as consultative bodies or venues for
interaction for member states regarding regime issues. Thus, organizations can
be important both as agents and interactive arenas (cf. Kratochwil and Ruggie
1986: 773; Haas 1990: 172; Archer 1992: 141–153). These types of regime
organization possess the ability to act through their secretariats and but also
Agents, structures, international regime significance╇╇ 99
serve as forums for their member states (the IAEA General Conference and
OPCW Conference of the States Parties, for example). Once again illustrating
how regimes can constitute complex entities with actor and structure qualities.
For these reasons it may indeed be useful to consider applying general institutional solutions – such as equipping a regime with an international organization
to carry out monitoring and verification duties – to regimes with similar goals
such as arms control. Also the ‘management’ and ‘enforcement’ approaches to
compliance that are pitted against each other in the literature should be seen as
complementary elements instead of competing alternatives. The measures suggested by these approaches should be merged to provide a continuum of measures to promote compliance as well as deter and detect non-�compliance.
International organizations, such as the IAEA and the OPCW, are well suited to
perform and carry out the valuable tasks identified by these two approaches.
Even so, those looking for easy answers should be warned that these features are
no panacea, and may perform better in one issue area than another due to discrete factors such as the technology in question and differences in the various
behavioural complexes and institutional settings (Parker 2001).
Regimes as enabling and constraining institutions
Thus, it can be argued that regimes are social institutions that represent both constraints on, and possibilities for, state action by organizing arrangements for the
interaction of state actors and, in many cases, giving rise to and enabling purposive agents that can engage in a range of activities – regulatory, surveillance,
sanctioning, resource provision, capacity building, etc. – in specific issue areas.
If regimes are understood as arrangements created for norm directed behaviour
within particular spheres of international life, one is then able to appreciate the
following contribution from Friedrich Kratochwil (1989: 11): ‘Norms are therefore not only “guidance devices,” but also the means which allow people to
pursue goals, share meaning, communicate with each other, criticize assertions,
and justify actions.’
Furthermore, the normative framework provided by regimes allows states a
context in which to develop behavioural habits that can be built up and sustained
across time by processes of political socialization and learning; in other words, a
regime can serve as a forum for the formation of habit driven actors (Rosenau
1986: 886). Regimes can influence and shape interests, behaviour, instrumentality (the way actors connect their preferences to policy choices), and outcomes.
From a new intitutionalist norms perspective, state behaviour is not strictly
determined by decision-Â�makers’ rational calculations of the state’s national
security interests or their parochial bureaucratic interests, but by deeper norms
and shared beliefs about what actions and policies are legitimate and appropriate
in international relations (Sagan 1996/97: 73; Kowert and Legro 1996: 461–465;
Franck 1990: 205–207; Henken 1979; Sundelius 1980: 193). Roles, routines and
rituals are extremely consequential to individuals and organizations for, although
individuals may indeed have ‘interests’, these interests are not formed in a
100╇╇ C.F. Parker
vacuum (March and Olsen 1989). Interests are shaped by the social roles actors
are asked to play, are pursued according to convention and favoured routines as
much as through thought out decision making, and are embedded in a social
environment that designates and favours certain structures as appropriate and
legitimate and ‘denigrates others as irrational and primitive’ (Sagan 1996/1997:
74; Scott 1995; Powell and DiMaggio 1991; Meyer and Scott 1992). International regimes can contribute to this intersubjective process and can thereby
serve the important function of both shaping and reflecting a state’s interests,
identity and behaviour.
The understanding of regimes expressed here implies a sophisticated relationship between agent and structure and the way they affect each other. Traditional
international relations theory generally takes an objectivist stance that separates
agent from structure. One example of this is the conception of the state as a
rational-Â�unitary actor – the rational decision-Â�maker approach – that emphasizes
the primacy of the individual: ‘It does so by attributing to the individual an
ability to objectivize her circumstances as a series of choices to which she
responds rationally’ (Onuf 1989: 56). Another example of this is structuralism,
which emphasizes the social whole over the individual.
Kenneth Waltz’s theories of international politics and balance of power are
prime examples of neorealist structuralism. Waltz argues that structural forces
produce outcomes regardless of the intentions or awareness of the units (1986a:
118–120).17 Waltz writes: ‘According to the theory, balances of power tend to
form whether some or all states consciously aim to establish and maintain a
balance, or whether some or all states aim for universal domination’ (ibid.:
118–119). Waltz claims what is explained is ‘the constraints that confine all
states’ (ibid.: 122).
The work of scholars such as Walter Carlsnaes (1992, 1994, 2008) and others
(Wendt 1987, 1999; Wendt and Duvall 1989; Wight 2007) represents an effort
to achieve a more adequate understanding of the agent–structure relationship in
international relations The perspective advocated here builds on Carlsnaes’ view
that actions are not only affected by structures but in turn subsequently affect
them and that this interplay occurs in a continuous interactive cycle which indicates the ‘mutually dynamic relationship between the two over time as well as
the inherently constraining and enabling character of the structural domain’
(1994: 284–285).
Thus, the more sophisticated conception of the agent–structure relationship
forwarded by Carlsnaes dovetails with the view of regimes sketched above as
constituting arrangements with enabling as well as constraining impacts. This
opens the door for more multi-�dimensional understandings of regime significance. As I have tried to show elsewhere, regime significance can potentially
have a number of different faces (Parker 2001). Regimes can matter functionally
and normatively as standard setting instruments, points of reference, assurance
mechanisms, forums for interaction, policy tools, for, in some cases, giving rise
to purposive agents, and for their overall issue area impact.
Agents, structures, international regime significance╇╇ 101
Concluding reflections
In the years ahead, additional work, methodological and conceptual, will be
needed to help us better understand and evaluate international regime significance. Moreover, more effort needs to be expended to improve our understanding of the relationship between compliance and the influence exerted by
international institutions, regimes, and agreements. The dense thicket of longstanding and emerging transnational problems that demand international solutions ensures that the subject of international cooperation and the challenge of
international regime significance will be of enduring relevance and interest to
scholars and practitioners alike. As this work proceeds researchers will need to
think carefully about agency–structure dynamics, fortunately they will have the
advantage of being able to draw on the important insights contained in Walter
Carlsnaes’ rich scholarship in this area.
Notes
╇ 1 This view of regimes as structural constraints can be found in Robert Jervis’ (1983)
more traditional modified structuralist approach, or Haggard and Simmons’ treatment
of regimes as ‘explicit injunctions’ (1987: 495).
╇ 2 This understanding of regimes (as a context for state action and socialization) is
similar to what Katzenstein (1996: 19) describes as the cultural-�institutional context
of state action. In his words: ‘Cultural-Â�institutional contexts do not merely constrain
actors by changing the incentives that shape their behaviour. They do not simply regulate behaviour. They also help to constitute the very actors whose conduct they seek
to regulate’ (22).
╇ 3 Variations of this complaint can be found in Archer (1992: 2), Haas (1990: 172–173),
Rochester (1986: 800) and Stein (1983: 115), among others. For a detailed discussion
on institutions, regimes and organizations, see Young (1989: 25–27, 32–37).
╇ 4 W. Richard Scott’s complex definition states: ‘Institutions consist of cognitive, normative, and regulative structures and activities that provide stability and meaning to
social behavior. Institutions are transported by various carriers – cultures, structures,
and routines – and they operate at multiple levels of jurisdiction’ (1995: 33).
╇ 5 Robert Keohane has defined institutions as ‘persistent and connected sets of rules
(formal and informal) that prescribe behavioral roles, constrain activity, and shape
expectations’ (1989: 3). With Haas and Levy, ‘practices’ was added to this definition
(Keohane et al. 1993: 4).
╇ 6 In their excellent book Theories of International Regimes, Hasenclever et al. (1997:
10–11) offer some useful clarity on these issues. They declare that international
regimes are international institutions, and that regimes and organizations both represent a type of international institution. However, although international regimes can
include or be supported by international organizations, they ‘are neither synonymous
(i.e. have the same meaning) nor co-Â�extensional (i.e. refer to the same entities)’ (10).
Unfortunately, they do not completely escape from the conceptual confusion surrounding these issues. Somewhat contradictorily, they later state that ‘regimes per se
do not constitute social institutionsâ•›.â•›.â•›.’ (21).
╇ 7 There are, of course, many ways of categorizing international organizations. In addition to IGOs, in which the membership consists of states, and INGOs, in which membership is composed of nonstate transnational actors, there also exist hybrid
international organizations open to both state and nonstate actors as well as supranational organizations. There is a difference between the first three types of organizations
102╇╇ C.F. Parker
and supranational organizations. While IGOs, INGOs and hybrid INGOs can be more
or less autonomous, they all remain subordinate to the state (cf. Buzan and Little
2000: 266). In contrast, a supranational organization, such as the EU, is
generally considered to be one which has power to take decisions, directly binding
upon individual, institutions, and enterprises, as well as upon the governments of
the states in which they are situated, and in which they must carry out notwithstanding the wishes of such governments.
(Shearer 1994: 550)
Of course, the competencies and powers of supranational organizations such as the
EU are restricted to certain areas as well.
╇ 8 Unless otherwise specified, my usage of international organizations refers to IGOs.
╇ 9 Barnett and Finnemore (1999), for example, forcefully advocate viewing IOs as
autonomous actors that can wield power independently of the states that create them.
They argue that this power emanates from two sources: ‘(1) the legitimacy of the
rational-�legal authority they embody, and (2) control over technical expertise and
Â�information’ (707).
10 For an examination of the WTO as an international organization, see Krueger (1998).
11 For further discussion, see, among others, Shearer (1994: 543–549), White (1996:
27–53), Barnett and Finnemore (1999) and Buzan and Little (2000). On one end of
the spectrum, White argues that conceptually international organizations have a legal
personality equivalent to states, and, in theory, have the same rights and duties as
states, although he concedes that states are functionally supreme to international
organizations in practice (1996: 52–53). Buzan and Little take the opposite view and
argue that international organizations do not deserve to be treated as independent
actors, which they are only in the weakest sense, and instead view them more as glorified permanent conferences (2000: 266–267). Shearer expresses what could be seen
as an intermediate view and explains that while international organizations have an
independent legal personality, they are not legally equivalent to states (1994: 547).
12 For other examples, see Barnett and Finnemore (1999), Reinalda and Verbeek (1998)
and Cox and Jacobson (1973).
13 Consult Verbeek (1998), Ness and Brechin (1988) and Rochester (1986) for overviews of this literature.
14 INFCIRC/153 The Structure and Content of Agreements between the Agency and
States Required in Connection with the Treaty on the Non-�Proliferation of Nuclear
Weapons, June 1972.
15 A number of factors, including its constitution or charter, its organs (the possession of
a permanent secretariat), practice (policy initiatives taken by its executive body and
the direction and funding of the organization through its general conference) and the
support of the membership determine how autonomous an organization actually is.
16 According to Anthony Giddens (1985: 12), an organization is: ‘a collectivity in which
knowledge about the conditions of system reproduction is reflectively used to influence,
shape or modify that system reproduction’. This is closely tied with surveillance, which
is the ‘control of information and the superintendence of the activities of some groups by
others’ (ibid.: 2). Thus, the IAEA and the OPCW, for example, can be said to be aspects
of the reflective monitoring of the inter-�state system concerned with the international surveillance of nuclear and chemical weapon acquisition and capabilities.
17 It should be noted that many criticisms of Waltz and neo-�realism (realist systemic
approaches) fail to acknowledge that Waltz accepts that this approach leaves much of
the details of international politics unexplained and therefore needs to be supplemented by other theories (Waltz 1986b: 322–345). In a recent debate article, Waltz
writes: ‘An international-Â�political theory can explain states’ behavior only when
external pressures dominate the internal disposition of states, which seldom happens.
When they do not, a theory of international politics needs help’ (1996: 57).
Agents, structures, international regime significance╇╇ 103
References
Archer, Clive (1992). International organizations. London and New York: Routledge.
Barnett, Michael N. and Finnemore, Martha (1999). The politics, power, and pathologies
of international organizations. International Organization, 53(4), 699–732.
Behnke, Andreas (1993). Structuration, institutions and regimes: The case of the CSBM.
Stockholm: IGS, Stockholm University.
Behnke, Andreas (1995). Ten years after: The state of the art of regime theory. Cooperation and Conflict, 30(2), 179–197.
Breitmeier, Helmut, Young, Oran R. and Zürn, Michael (2006). Analyzing international
environmental regimes: From case study to database. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Buzan, Barry and Little, Richard (2000). International systems in world history: Remaking the study of international relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36(3), 245–270.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1994). In lieu of a conclusion: Compatibility and the agency–structure
issue in foreign policy analysis. In W. Carlsnaes and S. Smith (eds), European
foreign policy: The EC and changing perspectives in Europe (pp.€274–287). London:
Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2008). Actors, structures, and foreign policy analysis. In S. Smith, A.
Hadfield and T. Dunne (eds), Foreign policy: Theories, actors, cases (pp.€ 85–100).
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chayes, Abram and Chayes, Antonia Handler (1993). On compliance. International
Organization, 47(2), 175–205.
Chayes, Abram and Chayes, Antonia Handler (1995). The new sovereignty: Compliance
with international regulatory agreements. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Cox, Robert W., Jacobson, Harold K. et al. (1973). The anatomy of influence: Decision
making in international organizations. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Dorn, A. Walter and Fulton, Andrew (1997). Securing compliance with disarmament
treaties: Carrots, sticks, and the case of North Korea. Global Governance, 3(1), 17–40.
Downs, George W., Rocke, David M. and Barsoom, Peter N. (1996). Is the good news
about compliance good news about cooperation? International Organization, 50(3),
379–406.
Franck, Thomas. M. (1990). The power of legitimacy among nations. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Giddens, Anthony (1985). The nation state and violence: Volume two of a contemporary
critique of historical materialism. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Gruber, Lloyd (2000). Ruling the world: Power politics and the rise of supranational
institutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Haas, Ernst B. (1990). When knowledge is power. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Haggard, Stephan and Simmons, Beth A. (1987). Theories of international regimes, International Organization, 41(3), 491–517.
Hasenclever, Andreas, Mayer, Peter and Rittberger, Volker (1997). Theories of inter�
national regimes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Henken, Louis (1979). How nations behave: Law and foreign policy, 2nd ed. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Hoffmann, Stanley (1998). World disorders: Troubled peace in the post-�Cold War era.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
104╇╇ C.F. Parker
Jervis, Robert (1983). Security Regimes. In S. Krasner (ed.), International regimes
(pp.€173–194). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Katzenstein, Peter J. (ed.) (1996). The culture of national security: Norms and identity in
world politics. New York: Columbia University Press.
Keohane, Robert O. (1984). After hegemony: Cooperation and discord in the world political economy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Keohane, Robert O. (1989). International institutions and state power: Essays in inter�
national relations theory. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Keohane, Robert O. and Hoffmann, Stanley (1993). Conclusion: structure, strategy, and
institutional roles. In Robert O. Keohane, Joseph S. Nye and Stanley Hoffmann (eds),
After the Cold War: International institutions and state strategies in Europe,
1989–1991 (pp.€381–404). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Keohane, Robert O., Haas, Peter M. and Levy, Marc A. (1993). The effectiveness of
international environmental institutions. In P. Haas et al. (eds), Institutions for the
Earth: Sources of effective international environmental protection (pp.€ 3–24). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kowert, Paul and Legro, Jeffrey (1996). Norms, identity, and their limits: A theoretical
reprise. In P. Katzenstein (ed.), The culture of national security: Norms and identity in
world politics (pp.€451–497). New York: Columbia University Press.
Kratochwil, Friedrich V. (1989). Rules, norms, and decisions: On the conditions of practical and legal reasoning in international relations and domestic affairs. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kratochwil, Friedrich V. and Ruggie, John G. (1986) International organization: A state
of the art and an art of the state. International Organization, 40(4), 753–775.
Krasner, Stephen D. (1983). Structural causes of regime consequences: Regimes as intervening variables. In S. Krasner (ed.), International regimes (pp.€1–21). Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Krueger, Anne O. (1998). The WTO as an international organization. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Levy, Marc A., Young, Oran R. and Zürn, Michael (1995). The study of international
regimes. European Journal of International Relations, 1(3), 267–330.
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P. (1989). Rediscovering institutions: The organizational basis of politics. New York: Free Press.
Martin, Lisa L. and Simmons, Beth (1998). Theories and empirical studies of inter�
national institutions. International Organization, 52(4), 729–757.
Mearsheimer, John J. (1994/95). The false promise of international institutions. Inter�
national Security, 19(3), 5–49.
Meyer, John W. and Scott, W. Richard (1992). Organizational environments: Ritual and
rationality, 2nd ed. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Miles, Edward L., Underdal, Arild, Andresen, Steinar, Wettestad, Jørgen, Skjærseth, Jon
Birger and Carlin, Elaine M. (2001). Environmental regime effectiveness: Confronting
theory with evidence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ness, Gayl D. and Brechin, Steven R. (1988). Bridging the gap: International organizations as organizations. International Organization, 42(2), 245–273.
Onuf, Nicholas (1989). World of our making: Rules and rule in social theory and inter�
national relations. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.
Parker, Charles F. (1999). Book review of Theories of international regimes. Cooperation and Conflict, 34(1), 97–106.
Parker, Charles F. (2001). Controlling weapons of mass destruction: An evaluation
Agents, structures, international regime significance╇╇ 105
of international security regime significance. Uppsala: Acta Universitatis
Upsaliensis.
Parker, Charles F. (2011). Compliance. In B. Badie, D. Berg-�Schlosser and L. Morlino
(eds), International encyclopedia of political science, Vol. 2 (pp.€ 367–370). London:
Sage.
Powell, Walter W. and DiMaggio, Paul J. (eds) (1991) The new institutionalism in organizational analysis. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Reinalda, Bob and Verbeek, Bertjan (eds) (1998). Autonomous policy making by inter�
national organizations. London: Routledge.
Rochester, J. Martin (1986). The rise and fall of international organization as a field of
study. International Organization, 40(4), 777–813.
Rosenau, James N. (1986). Before cooperation: Hegeomons, regimes, and habit-�driven
actors in world politics. International Organization, 40(4), 849–894.
Sagan, Scott D. (1996/97). Why do states build nuclear weapons? Three models in search
of the bomb. International Security, 21(3), 54–86.
Scott, W. Richard (1995). Institutions and organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Shearer, I.A. (1994). Starke’s international law, 11th ed. London: Butterworths.
Simmons, Beth A. (1998). Compliance with international agreements. Annual Review of
Political Science, 1, 75–93.
Simmons, Beth A. and Martin, Lisa L. (2002). International organizations and institutions. In W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B. Simmons (eds), Handbook of International
Relations (pp. 192–211). London: Sage.
Stein, Arthur A. (1983). Coordination and collaboration: Regimes in an anarchic world.
In S. Krasner (ed.), International regimes (pp.€115–140). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Strange, Susan (1983). Cave! hic dragones: A critique of regime analysis. In S. Krasner
(ed.), International regimes (pp.€337–354). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Sundelius, Bengt (1980). Interdependence and foreign policy. Cooperation and Conflict,
15(4), 187–208.
Thayer, Bradley A. (1995). The causes of nuclear proliferation and the utility of the
nuclear non-Â�proliferation regime. Security Studies, 4(3), 463–519.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1986a). Anarchic orders and balances of power. In R. Keohane (ed.),
Neo-Â�realism and its critics (pp.€98–130). New York: Columbia University Press.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1986b). Reflections on Theory of international politics: A response to
my critics. In R. Keohane (ed.), Neo-Â�realism and its critics (pp.€322–345). New York:
Columbia University Press.
Waltz, Kenneth N. (1996). International politics is not foreign policy. Security Studies,
6(1), 54–57.
Wendt, Alexander (1987). The agent–structure problem in international relations theory.
International Organization, 43(3), 335–370.
Wendt, Alexander and Duvall, Raymond (1989). Institutions and international order. In E.O.
Czempiel and J.N. Rosenau (eds), Global changes and theoretical challenges: Approaches
to world politics for the 1990s (pp.€51–73). Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.
Wendt, Alexander (1999). Social theory of international politics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
White, N.D. (1996). The law of international organisations. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Wight, Colin. (2007). Agents, structures and international relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
106╇╇ C.F. Parker
Young, Oran R. (1980). International regimes: Problems of concept formation. World
Politics, 32(3), 331–356.
Young, Oran R. (1989). International cooperation: Building regimes for natural
resources and the environment. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Young, Oran R. (1999). Governance in world affairs. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Part III
.â•›.â•›.â•›and the study of foreign
policy
9 Does Europe have foreign policy
traditions?
Knud Erik Jørgensen
Introduction
The emergence of a (common) European foreign policy and thereby the
(re-)emergence of Europe in world politics is among the most significant novel
features of international relations during the past two decades. Moreover, it is a
development that should be capable of triggering an increased interest in properly understanding European foreign policy. The purpose of this chapter is to
explore the potential consequences of making two seemingly small changes in
terms of analytical perspective. The first ‘small’ change I have in mind is substituting a vertical with a horizontal perspective, i.e. instead of focusing endlessly
on relations between member states and EU institutions, I focus on contending
foreign policy traditions. The second ‘small’ change is to focus on the politics of
foreign policy instead of on policy per se. The general aim of the chapter is to
contribute to an explorative endeavour, an attempt to try out arguments, rather
than summarise the conclusion of a multiple year research project.
Whether we are considering analytical or theoretical approaches, vertical perspectives have dominated horizontal perspectives. Concerning analytical
approaches, Christopher Hill (1983, 1996) has paved the way by means of focusing on national foreign policy traditions as a means of understanding advances in
policy-�making at the European level. While downplaying Europe as a collective
actor vis-Â�á-vis other global actors, Hill managed to (re-)connect policy-Â�making at
national and European levels. Ian Manners and Richard Whitman (2001; see also
Hadfield et al. 2012) have continued this tradition, yet also experienced the
increasingly practical difficulties of including ever more member states. Concerning theoretical approaches, it is most revealing to briefly scan developments during
the last 50 years. Among classical theories of integration, both neo-�functionalism
and intergovernmentalism focused on whether some kind of European (supranational) political community would be feasible. While it is well-�known that they
disagreed on the conclusion, they did share an interest in the vertically structured
relationship between member states and European institutions. Also various
realism-�informed approaches and neoliberal institutionalist perspectives have a
pronounced interest in understanding relations between states (power) and international (European) institutions. Finally, the major non-�substantive approaches,
110╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
whether principal–agent analysis, rational choice or (parts of↜) social constructivism, also share an interest in understanding relations between member states and
European institutions. Thus, principal–agent analysts focus on principals (member
states) and their agents (European institutions), while employing the standard registers the approach is known for. Rational choice-�informed scholars focus on why
rational actors (member states or governments) cooperate, engage in strategic bargaining or design institutions. Social constructivists, at least some, start off with
(national) identity and proceed by means of analysing how identity causes interests, in turn causing policies. To be sure, these analytical or theoretical perspectives have produced excellent studies and significantly contributed to our
knowledge of the dynamics of European foreign policy. However, as with any
avenue of inquiry, there is also a downside. The vertical perspective tends to
downplay the EU as a union – a collective actor – cultivating relations with states,
regional groupings and international institutions around the world (on relations
with international institutional, see Jørgensen and Laatikainen 2012). Indeed, the
vertical perspective tends to produce somewhat biased studies, often Europe-�
introvert and, thus, downplaying the global context in which the EU is situated. In
other words, the vertical perspective on relations between member states and EU
institutions tends to exclude factors external to Europe, whether major actors,
global norms or international institutions. Moreover, the vertical perspective potentially reifies national perspectives (for example, interests or traditions) and, thus,
downplays both possible common features of significance that might exist across
national boundaries and international factors influencing institutions and policy-�
making processes within the European Union.
This is where the first seemingly small change in perspective comes into the
picture. Specifically, what would be the consequences of changing to a horizontal perspective? Which avenues of inquiry would thereby be opened and which
analytical challenges or weaknesses can be foreseen? Concerning the change
from policy to politics, it has no less fundamental consequences for the research
agenda. Rather than logging or rationalising the swings and turns of given policies, a focus on the politics of European foreign policy leads us to examine
foreign policy attitudes at the level of both elite and general public. Moreover,
the patterns of contending worldviews and general preferences will move to
centre court, including change over time. Finally, we would begin to analyse
relations between general dispositions (policy paradigms, discursive structures)
and policy dilemmas.
Horizontal perspectives on European foreign policy
Most European states have long traditions in the conduct of foreign policy,
indeed Europe has been the historical prototype of international society and, in
the discipline of International Relations prominent theoretical models have been
based on or extracted from this prototype. Historically, international politics
simply meant politics among European nations. However, the emergence of a
(common) European foreign policy and thereby the (re-)emergence of Europe in
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?╇╇ 111
world politics has added some significant features to contemporary international
relations. Beginning modestly with experiments in common trade and development policy, followed by attempts at coordinating foreign policy (European
Policy Cooperation (EPC), Common Foreign and Security Policy (CFSP), European Security and Defence Policy (ESDP), and ever more issue areas being
added to the common policy portfolio, the European Union is today increasingly
seen as an international actor in its own right and, in some issue areas, as an
emerging superpower. Hence, the system of policy making has become double-�
layered (national and European), a feature requiring ingenious legal-�institutional
arrangements. As it happens, the process of treaty reform has produced a
dynamic series of such arrangements.
However, the double-Â�layered system also requires a process of epistemic reorientation and reconsideration, i.e. processes related to the ‘software’ of policy-Â�
making, to broad concepts that are tied to values and moral principles, i.e. to
so-�called public philosophies or policy paradigms, embedded in foreign policy
traditions that might exist across national boundaries. The enduring political
debates on these ‘software’ issues constitute what I call the politics of European
foreign policy, at least part of such politics.1 One cluster of questions presents
itself as being particularly important and intriguing, related to the genesis and
dynamics of foreign policy traditions and their impact on policy. How do public
philosophies organise the politics of European foreign policy? What are the
properties of these philosophies and how do they generate and reproduce traditions? Should we expect public philosophies directing policy-�making? How or
to which extent does the politics of foreign policy change over time? How do
these philosophies contribute to define the ‘common’ in the common European
foreign policy?
Instead of focusing on national foreign policy traditions or a singular European foreign policy tradition, this chapter aims at identifying the major contending European foreign policy traditions. The employment of the term ‘tradition’
suggests that patterns of attitude or belief systems among European foreign
policy elites will be fairly stable along a limited number of positions or orientations. Previous research can serve as an inspirational point of departure. Ole R.
Holsti and James N. Rosenau (1990) point out how efforts to label differences
often have obscured commonality. Their point is highly relevant for the argument forwarded in this essay because it might well be that labelling differences
concerning national foreign policy traditions obscure European commonalities.
Because the issue has not been part of our research agenda, it remains largely
unknown whether or not this is the case.
Sources of inspiration
Having thoroughly reviewed the existing literature, it is clear that there are no
major studies of the politics of European foreign policy to reconstruct or to criticise, i.e. some of the major methods of upgrading approach and knowledge are
not available.2 However, the review does suggest that there are four main sources
112╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
that are highly promising for the analysis of horizontal dimensions of European
foreign policy:
1
2
3
4
Research on American elite attitudes (Holsti and Rosenau 1990, 1996).3
Research on American foreign policy traditions (Mead 2002; Nau 2002;
2008; Kane 2008; Nordlinger 1996; Hellmann 1996).
Research on political ideology and European foreign policy (Carlsnaes
1986, 2002, 2007; Holbraad 2003; Sylvest 2009).
Research on public philosophies (Weir 1992; Schumaker 2008).
Holsti and Rosenau analyse foreign policy attitudes among American leaders
and use survey methods for the purpose. However, in the present context it is
primarily their typologies that are of interest. Basically, they combine two
dimensions, military internationalism and cooperative internationalism, and
ask elites whether they support or oppose these forms of internationalism. The
combination produces four types, labelled ‘internationalists’, ‘accomodationists’, ‘hardliners’ and ‘isolationists’. Holsti and Rosenau favour starting off
with dimensions, rather than types, arguing it makes it easier to possibly
extend the number of dimensions if need be. They are aware of the methodological problem that a focus on dimensions by definition makes differences
between dimensions relatively bigger than differences within dimensions. As
they point out, this is an unavoidable bias and essentially any analytical choice
implies a trade-�off of some sort. They also point out that the types are not
equal in terms of significance. In other words, some are more densely populated than others and the distribution of intellectual power changes over time.
Finally, they point out that the isolationist type is the one that internally is the
most heterogeneous, displaying a very rich diversity of attitudes. While Holsti
and Rosenau’s approach produces great insights into the diversity of attitudes
among American elites, the present context prompts us to the logical follow-�on
question, namely, whether the approach can be applied to the case of the European Union. In other words, in addition to having conventional methodological
nationalism shaping our inquiries it might make sense also to analyse the distribution of attitudes among European elites. As Thomas Diez, Markus
Jachtenfuchs and Sabine Jung (1999) have pointed out, there are contending
perspectives on or models of legitimate European governance. It is likely that
the same applies when it comes to European leaders and their attitudes to
foreign policy. The difference is that Diez et al. focus on contending perspectives along national lines, whereas I focus on contending traditions across
member states. Finally, as mechanical application is seldom the most appropriate or rewarding approach, both the kind of dimensions and the labels of the
types might need to be changed. Europe’s colonial tradition as well as its
extension, development policy, might qualify as a tradition that does not exist
to the same extent in the United States. By contrast, Europe’s anti-Â�
Americanism is mirrored by America’s anti-Â�Europeanism, and functioned as
one of the rationales for founding the United States.
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?╇╇ 113
The second inspirational source also begins in the United States, more precisely with studies of foreign policy traditions. Several authors employ this
notion and their studies demonstrate that it is an approach characterised by great
potential. The notion of ‘foreign policy tradition’ enables Walter Russell Mead
(2002) to produce a grand narrative of American foreign policy ever since the
nation was founded. As with most narratives, it is a narrative that is told from a
certain position. Mead argues that American foreign policy has been informed or
shaped by four traditions, labelled after famous American leaders/presidents
(Hamiltonian, Jeffersonian, Wilsonian and Jacksonian) and that these four political mindsets have been in perpetual competition to determine the appropriate
means and ends of American foreign policy. This might explain the considerable
changes over time of the priorities of American policy-�makers as well as some
of the differences between Democratic and Republican administrations as well
as differences between administrations or within political parties such as Bill
Clinton and Barack Obama or between Ronald Reagan and George Bush. Also
Henry Nau (2002, 2008) employs the notion of tradition, first to analyse how a
combination of power and identity theoretical perspectives allows us to avoid
some of the weaknesses that a single-�perspective seemingly by necessity produces. Nau introduces foreign policy traditions in his outline of the identity perspective and subsequently uses the insight to avoid the analytical weaknesses
that a mechanical international distribution of power can lead to. His traditions
are labelled slightly differently to those of Mead and are to some degree overlapping, with labels used to categorise theoretical traditions within international
relations. Such potentially problematic issues need not distract us in the present
context. Instead, I will briefly introduce Nau’s (2008) second engagement with
foreign policy traditions, i.e. his presentation of what he labels conservative
internationalism. He argues that this tradition is not as recognised as another
famous family tradition (i.e. liberal internationalism) but recognised or not, it is
most suitable for the endeavour to understand the foreign policy of republican
presidents since Ronald Reagan and, notably, also the foreign policy of President
Obama. Indeed, Nau (2010) has been among the first to conceptualize Obama’s
foreign policy priorities. Finally, John Kane (2008) is no stranger to the software
or the mindsets of the foreign policy traditions introduced above. He explores
the relationship between virtue and power, arguing that American foreign policy
has been characterised by a persistent moral dilemma. He explains that he first
became aware of the dilemma during the Vietnam War when the US conduct of
war somehow was at odds with the highly prized American virtues. As the story
seemed to repeat itself during the Iraq War, it prompted Kane to write his book
which is essentially an excellent exploration of the American mind, when it
comes to the making of foreign policy.
Having now briefly introduced three slightly different yet similar approaches
to American foreign policy, the question arises as to whether foreign policy traditions, however labelled, also characterises the politics of European foreign
policy. The studies examined above suggest four major American foreign policy
traditions:
114╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
•
•
•
Holsti and Rosenau: hard-�liners, internationalists, accomodationists and isolationists;
Nau: neo-�isolationist or nationalist, realist, primacist and internationalist;
Mead: Hamiltonian, Wilsonian, Jeffersonian and Jacksonian.
We do not know whether these categories apply to the case of Europe because
no one has so far bothered to ask the question, let alone attempted to answer it.
In other words, approaches do exist yet solutions are still missing.
In his foreign policy model, Walter Carlsnaes (1986, 2002) introduces what
he calls ‘structural dispositions’. Seemingly there are strong affinities between
structural dispositions and foreign policy traditions/public philosophies. In other
words, the two latter notions can be used to colour Carlsnaes’ category of ‘structural dispositions’. This leads me to the third inspirational source, namely,
Carsten Holbraad’s (2003; see also Halliday 1988) analysis of European political
ideologies and their interface to nationalism and internationalism, respectively.
His point of departure is the classical troika of European political ideologies,
conservatism, liberalism and socialism, the argument being that each of these
political ideologies has experienced its encounters with both nationalism and
internationalism. Hence, Holbraad ends up with a typology and a two by three
matrix, consisting of six cells. His main objective is to present an overview of
the ideas or – isms that have conditioned the international order of the European
continent. The hypothesis is that the political order has been structured by the
interaction between competing and overlapping trends of internationalisms and
nationalisms. By emphasising the plurality of the two concepts, Holbraad draws
attention to a central claim, namely, that internationalism and nationalism have
been manifested in European political thought in various forms and shapes. By
tracing down the origins and developments of conservative, liberal and socialist
traditions, he seeks to analyse how they have manifested themselves in the
conduct of European politics in the latter part of the twentieth century.
For Holbraad, internationalism does not necessarily entail optimistic
approaches towards cooperation or cosmopolitan aspirations, but represents as a
starting point the ‘ideology of international bonding’ (2003: 1). The general purposes of such bonding differ greatly, which is why it is necessary to analyse
internationalism from three different perspectives. Similarly, Holbraad’s understanding of nationalism is more ‘empty’ than the normal understanding of the
term. Nationalism, according to Holbraad, comes in the same three broad ‘ideal
types’, i.e. the conservative, liberal and socialist versions. As such, Holbraad
describes nationalism and internationalism as ‘opposite sets of political forces’,
but since they come in various forms and shapes Holbraad allows for a detailed
analysis of not only how the concepts have clashed but also the frequent interplay between different versions of the two perspectives.
Conservative internationalism is probably the version that stands furthest
away from conventional connotations of the term ‘internationalism’. As a
‘lowest common denominator’ approach to international affairs, conservative
internationalism can be understood as the ‘mere awareness of a shared interest in
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?╇╇ 115
security and survival’. This approach can be traced back to the peace of Westphalia and the maintenance of the balance of power, and is closely connected
with political realism, characterised by its emphasis on a strong separation of
foreign and domestic politics. Liberal internationalism is the broadest category
of internationalist thought, but similarly contains a wide variety of sub-�categories
(which, not surprisingly, reflects the definitional morass more generally associated with liberalism in political theory). Despite liberalism’s core focus on individual rights and prosperity, Holbraad draws attention to the highly different
preferences as to how these ends are achieved. Agreeing that peace and prosperity are necessary components, liberal internationalism has focused on means
ranging from free trade to integrationist policies. Finally, socialist internationalism can best be defined by its aspiration to reduce inequalities existing between
peoples, with a sharp division between those advocating revolutionary means
and those advocating domestic reforms and strengthening of state power combined with international organisation, as the best way forward.
Conservative nationalism has been manifest in European politics since earliest
times, and often as reactions to waves, or periods, of liberal and socialist internationalist influences. This pattern can still be traced, as the balance between reconciliation of national interests and the organisation of international relations is still
at heart of modern European politics as witnessed in the upsurge of conservative
nationalist parties in Europe over the last decade. Liberal nationalism can be seen
as distinguished in its belief in the nation state as the primary place of ‘individual
fulfillment and prosperity’. As such, the doctrine of national self-Â�determination is
strongly associated with liberal nationalism and in particularly opposed to the
doctrine of socialist internationalism, but also other forms of internationalism that
are seen as threatening liberal values. Finally, socialist nationalism, according to
Holbraad, is a twentieth-�century phenomenon, that can be traced to the revision
of socialist thought and the ‘nationalisation’ of socialist ideology.
In summary, one of Holbraad’s main arguments is that challenges, originating
in a balance, or equilibrium, between the forms of nationalisms and internationalisms, has been and will continue to be the key question governing European
political affairs. As Holbraad’s argument suggests, far from being linear, the
political history of Europe has been a persistent patterns of action/re-�action,
where conservative, liberal and socialist versions of internationalism and nationalism have pushed in different directions, in reaction, or as a challenge, to trends
and developments. The European international organisation over the last half
century should thus be seen partly as a reaction to former periods of nationalism,
and current forms of conservative nationalism can likewise be seen as opposition
to the prevailing liberal internationalism and its organisational manifestations.
One of the strongest aspects of Holbraad’s argument is the understanding of
various forms of internationalism and nationalism and their relevance for the
analysis of European politics, for example, ‘to conceive nationalism as not
merely the outcome of particular social and political circumstances on the
�domestic scene but also as a reaction or challenge to certain ideological trends
and political developments’ (Holbraad 2003: 173).
116╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
The fourth and final source of inspiration consists of the engaging and promising literature on the role of public philosophies. The point of departure is that
the term ‘policy’ surely is popular among political scientists yet also severely
over-�burdened with analytical functions, this makes conceptual unpacking very
necessary. For this reason it is difficult to underestimate the analytical importance and possibilities embedded in the distinction between public philosophy,
programmatic ideas (policy) and administrative programmes, the former coined
by Samuel H. Beer (1978), elaborated by Margaret Weir (1992) and recently
refined by Paul Schumaker (2008). Public philosophies promise that they enable
policy debates as an alternative to ideological warfare. We have seen that foreign
policy traditions are relative stable and coherent clusters of ideas about ends and
means in foreign policy. Specific traditions are based on distinct public philosophies. In the words of Margaret Weir, public philosophy,
expresses broad concepts that are tied to values and moral principles and
that can be represented in political debate in symbols and rhetoric. .â•›.â•›. Public
philosophies play a central role in organizing politics, but their capacity to
direct policy is limited; without ties to programmatic ideas their influence is
difficult to sustain.
(1992: 207–208)
Political rhetoric is often characterised by vague notions, ambiguity and generous inconsistency, leaving plenty of space for connotation. Sometimes, it is precisely such qualities that make political rhetoric work. According to Paul
Schumaker,
Public philosophies, like political ideologies, provide fairly comprehensive
and coherent sets of ideas about politics. Both provide beliefs about how
political communities are governed, ideals about the goals that should be
sought by political communities, and principles providing broad guidelines
for achieving those goals.
(2008: 1)
Schumaker not only defines public philosophy, he also provides a framework for
generating, describing and analysing public philosophies.
The four sources of inspiration all look promising in asking the right questions and subsequently finding answers to the key problematique of this chapter.
In the following section I will outline some analytical bridgeheads that can serve
as interface to the inspirational sources.
Approaching applications
As we have just seen existing studies provide fascinating information concerning
American foreign policy, yet also subsequently trigger intriguing questions: for
example, whether such traditions also exist in Europe, perhaps being similar to
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?╇╇ 117
American traditions in some respects and not in others. Several indications
suggest that it is promising to follow the American example at least for an inspirational start. The four sets of literature outlined above can serve as sources of
inspiration, but it will take considerable more effort to outline a proper research
agenda and to actually analyse European foreign policy traditions, even without
providing a comprehensive answer to the question asked in the heading of this
chapter. What can be done in the present context is to examine a number of tentative beginnings. More specifically, the exploration in this chapter is based on
four indicators suggesting the existence of European foreign policy traditions.
First, according to Walter R. Mead, the origin of the Wilsonian tradition
should be found in the United Kingdom, specifically in the British liberal tradition, and also among ‘the Protestant, Germanic-Â�language speaking peoples of
northern Europe’ (2002: 137–138). Indeed, there are several studies of liberal
internationalism in several EU member states (cf. also Sylvest 2007, 2009). Similarly, Henry Nau has emphasised that his conception of foreign policy traditions
might be universally applicable even if he has only applied it to the case of the
United States. In any case, both proponents and critics agree that the liberal
internationalist tradition has to a considerable extent informed the making of
European foreign policy during both the Prodi and the Barroso Commissions.
European (liberal) values have been highlighted, including the need to promote
or project these values internationally and, within both policy and scholarly communities, where Europe has been presented as a normative power (Manners
2002). The sponsorship of multilateral institutions, with the United Nations at
the heart, has become one of the main objectives of European foreign policy
(Aggestam 2004), indeed, multilateralism has been cherished as both a means
and not least a political end that is valuable in itself. Subsequently, this shared
understanding has enabled the emergence of ‘effective multilateralism’ as a key
objective in the European Security Strategy (2003; see also Biscop 2005). Furthermore, research on the role of values and principles in foreign policy suggests
that the values/principles and ethics/morality relationship is more complex than
often assumed (Lucarelli and Manners 2006). Military interventions have not
been excluded, specifically not when the objective is saving strangers (Wheeler
2000). The EU has been involved in several interventions but intervening in Iraq
(as part of the US-�led invasion) was something the EU could not do. Instead the
EU became/was deeply divided over the Iraq issue.
Critics of liberal internationalism share the analysis yet are concerned about
the outcome. John Mearsheimer (1994) has voiced strong criticism of the false
promise of international institutions and though his target mainly was fellow-�
academics, his point of departure was the liberal internationalism that characterised the Clinton administration. Jean-�Yves Haine (2009) echoes much of
Mearsheimer’s criticism – indeed, Haine’s article can be characterised as standard realist critique of liberal orientations – yet his target is European liberal
internationalism, claimed to experience a crisis. In this fashion, continuity can be
traced back to E.H. Carr’s and Hans Morgenthau’s classical critiques of liberal
thinking. While such continuity is interesting in itself, what is relevant in the
118╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
present context is that Haine’s criticism suggests both the existence of European
foreign policy traditions and their diversity and contending or competitive
nature.
Second, even if predominant, European liberal internationalism, might not be
the only foreign policy tradition that has shaped European foreign policy during
the last 10–20 years. Hamiltonian foreign policy priorities might also have been
influential. Big Business Europe has obvious commercial interest and, according
to critics, the Directorate General for Trade (DG Trade) knows and promotes
these interests. Hence, we should perhaps talk about Corporate Power Europe
rather than Normative Power Europe. In any case, Big Business Europe has a
strong interest in creating an extended home (the Single European Market),
enlarging the home (processes of enlargement) and, to promote a global market
(World Trade Organization (WTO) and Doha round). Representatives of the tradition share with American Hamiltonians a strong interest in keeping sea lanes
open for commercial activity and expect European naval units to provide the
service, whether in the Persian Gulf during the Iran–Iraq war during the 1980s
(WEU joint minesweeping operation), off the coast of Somalia (operation Atalanta) or elsewhere. The idea of lifting the weapons embargo vis-Â�à-vis China did
not exactly contradict the interests of the tradition, yet the strategic priority of
alignment with the major military power also counts. Finally, Big Business
Europe has an interest, despite corporate social responsibility, in downplaying
most of the normative values promoted by liberal internationalists and analysed
by scholars with an interest in this kind of ethical foreign policy.
Third, European isolationists have a hard time in shaping European foreign
policy. Partly because they are, as with American likeminded isolationists, a
highly diverse and internally heterogeneous grouping. Notably, their isolationist
attitudes prompt them to reject the European enterprise in the first place. Hence,
when not feeling or enjoying ownership to the construction of Europe, it is very
difficult to play a prominent role in shaping Europe’s changing foreign policy
direction. Instead, isolationists may express concern about foreign adventures or
the decline of democracy in Europe, i.e. nurturing the democratic deficit issue, or
simply make pleas to cultivate our own (national or regional) gardens first and
foremost. The contemporary proliferation of far right politics in Europe might
trigger increasing efforts at understanding the role of ‘the international’ in this
kind of politics.
Fourth, the employment of terms such as tradition and public philosophy is
novel and unconventional – essentially providing new underpinnings (ontology)
to foreign policy analysis and creating a language or analytical vocabulary to
�describe this ontology. This is a considerable task in itself as currently, there
simply is no such vocabulary, except a few conceptual bits and pieces which
include Atlanticism, Europeanism, Anti-�Americanism, isolationism, a legal
international order, responsibility, hegemony, multipolarity, going-�it-alone, Alleingang, etc. It helps a little that research on both tradition and public philosophy
contributes conceptualisations that have their counterparts in International Relations theory. This is one of the rare examples of the discourse of theory and the
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?╇╇ 119
discourse of political practice actually interfacing. In this context, discourse
analysis becomes highly relevant suggesting that we should seriously explore the
potential of this analytical perspective.
Fifth, we have seen above that Holbraad (2003) has analysed foreign policy
positions along ideological lines, essentially combining the three traditional
European political ideologies – liberalism, conservatism and socialism – and the
distinction between nationalism and internationalism, producing for instance
liberal, conservative and socialist internationalism. Hence, attempts to identify
European foreign policy traditions have been made. However, this literature has
not explored the role of public philosophy or related insights in research on
European foreign policy. In order to do so, it would probably be necessary to
engage in an exercise of analytical macro triangulation, drawing on Comparative
Politics, International Political Theory and International Relations.
Finally, it is a complicating factor that part of the European enterprise is
based on the assumption that contemporary European foreign policy is, or should
be based on a distinct and fundamental rupture with the past, a profound discontinuity. In political reasoning it is often emphasised that Europe’s ‘other’ does
not have a geopolitical nature but is simply Europe’s not so glorious past. In
other words, Europe’s contemporary international identity and self-Â�image should
represent a break with the past. Paradoxically, Europe’s debates on foreign relations seem more dynamic than American debates; compare Mead’s strong
emphasis on a continuous debate stretching back to the founding fathers, and
Nau’s deploring of ‘the limits of the traditional foreign policy debate among
nationalists, realists, and internationalists’ (Nau 2002: 59). It remains an open
question as to whether the rupture in Europe is a political preference or an undisputed reality.
Conclusion and perspectives
We have seen that studies of European foreign policy have focused strictly on
the vertical relationship between EU member states and EU institutions. While
acknowledging that this preoccupation has involved a multitude of theoretical
perspectives – intergovernmentalism, neofunctionalism, rational choice, principal–
agent theory and Europeanisation (in both uploading and downloading versions) –
this chapter turns the perspective 90 degrees and focuses instead on foreign
policy traditions over time and across member states. Moreover, the study of
European foreign policy has traditionally been fairly policy oriented and descriptive, lacking an overarching analytical framework. This lack of a theoretical
foundation implies that, although individual studies generate strong insights,
they do not cumulate to create a coherent picture of, or promote focused debates
about the dynamics of European foreign policy. The proposed change does
enable an interface between, on the one hand, public philosophies being cultivated within traditions and, on the other, theories of international relations, not
least their fundamental assumptions about international life. Finally, whereas
Eurobarometer surveys focus on questions concerning the preferences among
120╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
European citizens concerning levels of decision making, and research on European foreign policy tends to dwell on legal-�institution issues, the essay invites
studies of the politics of foreign policy, specifically contending foreign policy
traditions and specialised debates on the objectives and means of foreign policy.
Instead of paying exclusive attention to policy, the chapter focuses on the politics of foreign policy and on the public philosophies that inform and shape
policy-�making. Instead of engaging in studies of single policy, single case or a
limited selection of, say, three larger or four smaller EU member states, the
subject here includes the politics of foreign policy in all EU member states.
Different analytical trajectories have triggered the idea that European foreign
policy traditions are emerging, yet remain largely undiscovered by the scientific
community. Hence, the prime purpose has been to discover and to some degree
examine these traditions, thereby opening a new research agenda for the study of
European foreign policy and enriching the ontology of contemporary foreign
policy analysis, specifically the politics of foreign policy. This chapter casts the
politics of European foreign policy in a new light; creates a novel conceptual
foundation for studying the politics of foreign policy and international behaviour
more generally, and introduces some ideas about analytically premising avenues
of inquiry. In addition, it might as a bonus have relevance for the making and
planning of foreign policy.
Notes
1 In a different kind of politics, political issues are allowed to masquerade as legal issues.
Within such a politics, strategies ‘expire’, European diplomats only engage in issues
when they have legal competence to do so, and international law is the key factor that
enables or constrains political action. Morgenthau (2012 [1933]) was an early critic of
this kind of politics.
2 Christopher Hill’s, The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy (2003) addresses some of
the issues but is more general in its approach and coverage.
3 Whereas the United States has a long tradition in research on foreign policy attitudes
among both elites and the general public, such a tradition hardly exists in Europe. To
the degree survey data do exist they are almost entirely constituted by national boundaries, the Eurobarometer being among exceptions.
References
Aggestam, Lisbeth (2004). A European foreign policy? Role conceptions and the politics
of identity in Britain, France and Germany. PhD thesis, Department of Political
Science, Stokholm University.
Beer, Samuel H. (1978). In search of a new public philosophy. In Anthony King (ed.),
The new American political system (pp.€5–44). Washington, DC: American Enterprise
Institute.
Biscop, Sven (2005). The European security strategy: A global agenda for positive
power. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1986). Ideology and foreign policy: Problems of comparative conceptualization. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Does Europe have foreign policy traditions?╇╇ 121
Carlsnaes, Walter (2002). Foreign policy. In W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B. Simmons
(eds), Handbook of International Relations. London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2007). European foreign policy. In K.E. Jørgensen, M. Pollack and B.
Rosamond (eds), Handbook of European Union politics. London: Sage.
Hadfield, A., Manners, I. and Whitman, R. (2012). Foreign policies of EU member states.
Abingdon: Routledge.
Haine, Jean-�Yves (2009). The European crisis of liberal internationalism. International
Journal, 64(2), 453–479.
Halliday, Fred (1988). Three concepts of internationalism. International Affairs, 64(2),
187–112.
Hellmann, G. (1996). Goodbye Bismarck? The foreign policy of contemporary Germany.
Mershon International Studies Review, 40(1), 1–39.
Hill, Christopher (ed.) (1983). National foreign policies and European political cooperation. London: Allen and Unwin.
Hill, Christopher (ed.) (1996). The actors in Europe’s foreign policy. London: Routledge.
Hill, Christopher (2003). The changing politics of foreign policy. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Holbraad, Carsten (2003). Internationalism and nationalism in European political
thought. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Holsti, Ole R. and Rosenau, James N. (1990). The structure of foreign policy attitudes
among American leaders. Journal of Politics, 52(1),€94–125.
Jachtenfuchs, M., Diez, T. and Jung, S. (1999). Which Europe? Conflicting models of
legitimate European political order. European Journal of International Relations, 4(4),
409–445.
Jørgensen, Knud Erik and Laatikainen, Katie V. (2013). The European Union and international institutions: Performance, policy, power. Abingdon: Routledge.
Kane, John (2008). Between virtue and power. The persistent moral dilemma of U.S.
foreign policy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Lucarelli, Sonia and Manners, Ian (eds) (2006). Values and principles in European
foreign policy. London: Routledge.
Manners, Ian (2002). Normative power Europe: A contradiction in terms. Journal of
Common Market Studies, 40, 235–258.
Manners, Ian and Whitman, Richard (eds) (2001). The foreign policies of European
Union member states. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Mead, Walter R. (2002). Special providence: American foreign policy and how it has
changed the world. London: Routledge.
Mead, Walter R. (2010). Liberal internationalism: The twilight of a dream. The American
Interest, March/April.
Mearsheimer, John J. (1994/1995). The false promise of international institutions. International Security, 19 (3), 5–49.
Morgenthau, Hans J. (2012 [1933]). The concept of the political. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Nau, Henry R. (2002). At home abroad: Identity and power in American foreign policy.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Nau, Henry R. (2008). Conservative internationalism. Policy Review, 150, 3–45.
Nordlinger, Eric A. (1996). Isolationism reconfigured: American foreign policy for a new
century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Schumaker, John (2008). From ideologies to public philosophies: An introduction to
political theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sylvest, Casper (2007). Beyond the state? Pluralism and internationalism in early
twentieth-Â�century Britain. International Relations, 21(1),€67–85.
122╇╇ K.E. Jørgensen
Sylvest, Casper (2009). British liberal internationalism. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Weir, Margaret (1992). Ideas and the politics of bounded innovation. In Sven Steinmo,
Kathleen Thelen and Frank Longstreth (eds), Structuring politics: Historical institutionalism in comparative perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wheeler, Nicholas (2000). Saving strangers: Humanitarian intervention in international
society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
10 A foreign policy without a state?
Accounting for the CFSP
Helene Sjursen
Traditionally, there has been considerable scepticism to the value of conducting
research on the European Union’s (EU) foreign and security policy. Many felt
there was no such thing as a European foreign policy, and even more so, no
European security or defence policy. Only states were seen as able to conduct
foreign policy, and there were only national, foreign and security policies. To
study European Political Cooperation (EPC), as it was once called, and even as
some did, to write thick books about it (Ifestos 1987), was considered a bit odd.
Nevertheless, it has become increasingly difficult to neglect the EU’s international role. It is the world’s largest trading power as well as a major donor of
humanitarian assistance and development aid. Further, its gradual building of
capabilities in security and defence makes it an important actor in areas of
tension, as we can observe for example with regard to the Middle East. In spite
of the scepticism, the European Union has forced itself upon the international
agenda. And in fact, rather than a research topic that is only for those with very
particular, not to say morbid, interests the EU’s foreign and security policy, the
efforts to build a common European foreign and security policy (CFSP), is both
a fascinating and important object of study. It is an experimentarium, not only in
practical, political, but also in conceptual terms, forcing us to rethink deep seated
understandings of what foreign and security policy actually is and of what a
polity is that can conduct such policies. Walter Carlsnaes’ work very much
reminds us of this (2006). Further, it leads us to think more carefully about the
concepts we use to analyse foreign and security policy, and the way we describe
and talk about it.
In the following I would like to make some suggestions as to the direction in
which this research could go. What kind of questions may we ask and what
needs to be changed in the way we study foreign and security policy in order to
pursue them? I will discuss this based on a critique of the existing literature on
the EU’s so-Â�called ‘normative’ power, and on a reconstruction of some of its
gaps and missing links. In so doing, I draw on a discourse theoretical
perspective.
124╇╇ H. Sjursen
The ambivalence of ‘doing good’: scholars or naïve
moralists?
Seeking to capture the ‘uniqueness’ of the EU, a number of scholars have
described it as a normative, civilising or ethical power within the international
system (Whitman 1998; Smith 2000; Stavridis 2001; Manners 2002; Aggestam
2004; Lightfoot and Burchell 2005). There are considerable challenges involved
in such conceptualisations. They easily conjure up images of European imperialists or missionaries, who set out to shape the world in their image, convinced
that their values and way of life was superior. Alternatively, it could be the stuff
of hypocrisy, a simple cover for the promotion of particular interests. Not only
do scholars refering to such concepts risk appearing as naïve moralists, as realists will argue with Morgenthau or Kissinger that the purpose of a foreign policy
is to pursue state interests and keep well away from morality. They also become
vulnerable to the charge that they are unable to distinguish between their own
sympathy for the European project and their academic role as critical analysts.
The problems with taking such conceptions as the starting point for research
become even more evident against the backdrop of recent developments in European security and defence. How is the availability of military resources reconcilable with a conception of ‘normative’ or ‘ethical’ Europe?
In spite of the difficulties with conceptualising the EU as a ‘normative/civilising/
ethical’ power, a number of empirical observations related for example to the
EU’s policy of democracy promotion, its introduction of human rights clauses in
trade agreements, the emphasis on encouraging regional cooperation or the focus
on building international institutions suggest that there may actually be something distinctive about the EU’s foreign and security policy that requires attention, at least in comparison with what we tend to think of as the typical foreign
policy of great powers (Risse and Börzel 2007). Hence the need to pursue this
further.
What kind of ‘normative’ power? The need for a critical
standard
Rather than questioning the ‘reality’ of the EU as a foreign policy actor, the
‘normative power’ literature takes its existence for granted and seeks to define
and conceptualise it. In this sense the fundamental question is that which is
asked in much of the literature on the EU – i.e. ‘what kind of polity is it?’
However here it is asked with a specific focus on its external dimension. The
EU’s status is unclear and ambiguous. There are different interpretations of what
constitutes its core characteristics, as well as the future direction of integration.
It is less than a state, but certainly more than a classic international organisation.
What then, is it, and how should it be conceptualised? And what kind of foreign
policy may such an undefined entity be able to produce?
In order to assess the putative particularity of the EU’s foreign policy, we
need to know not only whether or not the EU ‘is’ a normative power, but what
A foreign policy without a state?╇╇ 125
kind of normative power it is. Norms are a variety of different things and, after
all, most actors pursue norms; most preferences also reflect a normative position
and many foreign policy actors have some kind of normative influence or
agenda. In fact, the United States or the former Soviet Union have both in different respects been ‘normative’ powers. Still, ‘normative power’ Europe is clearly
identified as different from these. As the ‘normative power’ literature does not
discriminate between different types of norm, it does not have a sufficiently
nuanced conceptual apparatus to investigate what kind of normative power the
EU may be and to substantiate this claim of a particularity to the EU’s foreign
and security policy when compared to that of other powers.
A second and crucial problem that follows from this indiscriminate view of
norms is the often implicit link between the pursuit of norms and the idea that
the EU is ‘doing good’ in the international system, or between the idea that the
EU is a ‘civilian power’ and that such a power is necessarily positive. The challenge here is not only that norms are a variety of different things, but that all of
them do not necessarily lead to good things. In order to resolve this we need to
find a way to assess if the pursuit of norms is legitimate. It could very well be
that the EU’s pursuit of norms or efforts to define what is considered ‘normal’
(Manners 2002) for example is an expression of Eurocentric cultural imperialism, even though the literature claims that this is not the case. If we fail to distinguish between different types of norm and their validity and legitimacy basis, we
cannot really tell – we are required to trust the analyst’s personal assessment of
what is ‘good’, without being provided with clear reasons and critical standards.
Hence the concern that the ‘normative power’ literature is simply apologetic and
uncritical. It is only if we are clear regarding the basis on which such claims are
made, that they may be critically assessed and vindicated – or rejected.1 In other
words, there is a need to establish what kind of standard for ‘goodness’ is being
used and to clarify its legitimacy basis. Surprisingly, this is rarely done in the
existing literature.2
A cosmopolitan perspective
I suggest that a criterion, a critical standard, for a ‘normative’ – or what will
hereafter be referred to as a ‘humanitarian’ – power may be derived from a
cosmopolitan perspective. This perspective presupposes the possibility of a community based on certain universal principles, and depicts an international order
constrained by a higher ranking law, and not by a balance of power.3 An emphasis on law is important as a foreign policy that claims to be ‘doing good’ – to act
in the name of ‘humanity’ – must be held accountable. Unchecked power, exercised in the name of ‘humanity’ as such, in the name of human rights alone, may
easily lead to totalitarianism (Eriksen 2006). Further, the law would alleviate
suspicions of hypocrisy and ensure consistency in the application and pursuit of
norms. There is always a risk that actors will follow their own interests even if
they know that this may harm others, or suspect that others do so, even if they
say the opposite. In order to avoid such risks, common rules are necessary. The
126╇╇ H. Sjursen
law functions as a system of action that makes it possible to implement moral
duties as common commitments.4 A distinction is made, then, between traditional international law and multilateralism on the one hand and a cosmopolitan
law of the people on the other hand. While the rights of states to external sovereignty is a core principle in international law and multilateralism, cosmopolitanism refers to the rights of individuals and prioritises this above the rights of
states.5
Such a critical standard would be consistent with the idea of a foreign policy
actor that breaks with what we understand by the ‘traditional’ foreign policy
practice of great powers. The core feature of a humanitarian power would be that
it acts externally in order to transform the parameters of power politics through a
focus on the international legal system, rather than to write itself into the existing international system through an emphasis on multilateralism or with the aim
of establishing a (new) balance of power. It would be one that seeks to overcome
power politics through a strengthening of cosmopolitan law, emphasising the
rights of individuals and not only the rights of states to sovereign equality, the
purpose being to establish a global law of citizens. Further, a humanitarian
power would be a power that is willing to bind itself, and not only others, to
such common rules. Nevertheless, what is suggested here is a thin version of
cosmopolitanism, where few functions are considered ‘up loadable’ to the global
level. It is based on a narrow conception of justice, where the cosmopolitan level
would focus on human rights and security.
As the international system is still one in which legal procedures for protecting human rights are weak, a question for empirical research could be to what
extent the EU’s arguments for human rights were presented only with regard to
particular actors or cases or whether they were also part of a broader effort to
transform their legal status in international law. An example of such efforts
would be to support the establishment of the International Criminal Court (ICC).
Furthermore, one might expect that a humanitarian power would develop standards, mechanisms and policy instruments that would ensure that its own policies
are consistent with such principles. The confirmation of the Charter of Rights as
legally binding for the EU and its member states would be one such indicator, as
it would ensure greater consistency between internal and externally projected
standards.
What kind of norms?
As noted, a cosmopolitan perspective presupposes the possibility of agreement
on certain universal principles. Hence it rests on the analytical distinction
between moral and ethical norms. Moral norms refer to questions that may be
settled with reference to justice and concern deontological principles such as
human rights, democracy and rule of law. Ethical norms, or values, refer to questions of what is conceived of as the common good and thus revolve on what can
be justified in a context-�bound ethical-�political discourse. While ethical norms
and the concept of values are connected to the characteristics of a specific
A foreign policy without a state?╇╇ 127
�
community
and to the identity of the members of that community, understood as
collective representations of the good that vary according to cultural and social
context; moral norms or rights – referring to justice – are universal in the sense
that they pertain to humanity as such, independently of particular identities and
belongings.6
The distinction becomes central for example if what we have in mind is a
conception of the EU as an actor that promotes norms, but does so without following the path of European imperialism. Whereas it would not be reasonable to
expect transcultural agreement about values, the same is not necessarily the case
with regard to higher order norms such as ‘equality, freedom, solidarity, self-Â�
realisation and human dignity’ (Eriksen and Weigård 2003: 138). Values or conceptions of what is good may vary according to cultural or social contexts. They
are particular for example to a specific community or a specific collective identity. If the EU defines itself, and thinks of itself, as a ‘force for the good’, then,
as already noted, this could be a subjective definition linked to a particular European understanding and defined in a particular European cultural context. It may
not match what is defined as good or valuable in other parts of the world, conditioned by other cultural or social norms. So ‘normative power’ Europe could be
true to its own norms, yet be perceived as acting in the same way as ‘historical
empires’. This basic analytical distinction is important but lacking in the literature on the EU as a ‘humanitarian power’. The suggestion here is that a critical
standard for a humanitarian power be linked to an emphasis on moral norms,
seeking to establish what is right, fair or just, and which can be kept separate
from ethical norms.
Utopian normativity?
Many will however consider that even when such precautions are taken, multilateralism is as good as it can get and that the idea of a cosmopolitan perspective
resting on shared universalistic norms must be set aside. Some would argue that
this is due to cultural differences that make it impossible to come to a rational
agreement on universally acceptable norms (Brown 1999). Others would rather
emphasise the inherent characteristics of the international system leading to
insurmountable practical difficulties in establishing cosmopolitan law, which
would ensure the rights not only of states but also the fundamental rights of citizens. The former seems to be the position of Diez (2005), who suggests that the
‘normative’ power argument should be understood as a practice of constructing
a European identity. From an identity perspective, actor rationality is linked to a
particular context, and the potential for a rational agreement beyond different
cultural contexts or identities is limited. Consequently, from this standpoint,
claims to universality can only be viewed as expressions of a particular conception of what is ‘good’, at worst they represent a form of hypocrisy aiming for the
domination of others. This is what Diez appears to imply when he argues, with
reference to the EU’s international role, that: ‘The standards of the self are not
simply seen as superior but of universal validity, with the consequence that the
128╇╇ H. Sjursen
other should be convinced or otherwise brought to accept the principles of the
self↜’ (2005: 10). However, if this is so, the conclusion regarding ‘normative’
power EU is given in advance. Then, ‘normative’ power cannot be anything else
than a form of cultural imperialism, unless it abandons the ambition to ‘shape
conceptions of what is normal’ (Manners 2002: 239). Quite clearly this puts the
scholarly claim that ‘normative’ power or ‘civilian’ power is a good thing in a
dubious light.
Not all agree. Axel Honneth writes that although a critique of the universalism of human rights finds advocates in growing numbers, it ‘belongs to the antiquated heritage of the counter-Â�Enlightenment’ (1997: 167). He further rejects the
claim that ‘the moral obligations of universalism are too great a burden both for
individual subjects and for nations’ (ibid.). He argues that the character of the
moral relationship between nations and civil actors has changed and that due to
the spread of democracy, civil society plays an increasingly independent role
also in international affairs. Increased transparency and access to information
pressure governments to provide reasons for their policies. A number of organisations and movements promote the realisation of human rights across state
borders. Consequently, the transformation of power politics is already under
way, according to Honneth.
Regardless of where one’s sympathies would lie in the above debate, the main
point here has been to highlight that if we are to pursue research on the notion of
the EU as a ‘normative’ or as it has been labelled here, humanitarian, power,
there is a need for an explicit critical standard, as well as a clarification of the
validity and legitimacy basis of the norms that are referred to. Further, if empirical research is to be pursued, indicators that are consistent with this standard
must be established. This is lacking in the existing literature. It may well be that,
in empirical terms, the critical standard suggested here will not ‘fit’. It may also
be that there are other critical standards ‘out there’ that analysts find more
acceptable. What has been presented here is simply one suggestion as to where
we may look for a such a standard, as well as to what may be its sources of
legitimacy.
Rethinking core categories
What are the implications of this perspective – of the theoretical presuppositions
of the cosmopolitan view – for the study of the EU’s external policy? If we are
to examine its relevance we need to rethink some of the basic categories, or analytical tools traditionally used in the study of foreign policy and international
relations. I will highlight three such here and make some preliminary suggestions with regard to the direction of a possible rethinking.
First, the conception of actors’ rationality. In international relations it is
conventionally linked to instrumentality – actors are seen as rational in the
sense that they seek to maximise their own interests (Krasner 1999). International politics is considered to be the outcome of adverse self-�interested behaviour under conditions of anarchy. As I have already hinted, an alternative
A foreign policy without a state?╇╇ 129
conception would suggest that actors may also act on the basis of normative
expectations or assessments. Justice and fairness, and not only self-�interest,
would be within the realm of rationality. This is linked to a communicative
conception of rationality where actors are considered rational when they are
able to justify and explain their actions in relation to intersubjectively valid
norms, i.e. norms that cannot be reasonably rejected in a rational debate, and
not only when they seek to maximise their own interests (Eriksen and Weigård
2003). A rational actor could explain actions with reference to principles that,
all things considered, can be recognised as ‘just’ by all parties, irrespective of
their particular interests, perceptions of the ‘good life’ or cultural identity. This
conception provides an additional basis to that developed through a rational
choice perspective from which we may understand the policy-�choices that
actors make. It provides the necessary micro foundations for the cosmopolitan
perspective, because it allows us to account for ideal motives as a basis for
rational action. It allows us to conceive of actors that may act in accordance
with normative conviction and not only with reference to particular interests.
Further, the idea of the legitimacy of cosmopolitan law rests on the assumption
that it is possible to come to a rational agreement on universally acceptable
norms. It is the process of deliberation, of giving and taking reasons, leading
to such a rational agreement that would provide the test for the legitimacy – or
lack of such – of the pursuit of norms.
Second, the conception of power. Traditionally (in international relations) it
is understood in materialist terms. Power is seen as linked to physical resources,
be they economic or military. These resources are considered to be what is
necessary in order to allow actors to enforce their own will/to impose it on
others. An alternative conception would suggest that you also need legitimacy in
order to have power. In fact, it would suggest that if an actor does not have legitimacy, i.e. support for what it does, it does not, in the long run, have power
either. Such a reconceptualisation would highlight that the concept of power is
not absent from a cosmopolitan perspective (in spite of what is often argued in
international relations), as the threat of sanctions may be necessary to in order to
ensure that the law is upheld. However, a cosmopolitan perspective relies on the
assumption that it is possible to find a basis for legitimate power.7 This would
arise in the communication between citizens: ‘Power is collective and intersubjective by nature; it is created in the interaction between agents, and it is only in
operation and is only strong as long as the people are assembled and agree’
(Eriksen and Weigård 2003: 173).
Incidentally, such a conception of power is not a far fetched utopia. In fact,
several empirical examples suggest that there is already a conception of ‘legitimate power’ at work in the international system and further that there are already
informal sanctions of some kind in world politics connected to the breach of
accepted norms regarding the exercise of power. This may explain why even the
United States (US), in spite of its overwhelming military might, keeps returning
to the United Nations (UN) to gain support for its policies. Even the world’s
largest, perhaps only, superpower appears ultimately to be dependent on
130╇╇ H. Sjursen
�
legitimacy
in order to achieve its foreign policy objectives. It may also help us
understand why the US was so concerned with highlighting that there was a
large number of participants in the so-Â�called ‘coalition of the willing’ in Iraq,
even though, in terms of resources, they did not all make a substantive contribution. The ‘symbolic’ support that such a coalition provides gives legitimacy to
the action itself. Likewise, through such a reconceptualisation it may seem less
paradoxical that the European Parliament (EP), which has no traditional power
tools to wield in foreign policy, is nevertheless listened to and taken seriously
when it raises its voice on international issues. As described by MEP Elmar
Brook: when the EP criticises a state for example for violations of human rights,
the representatives of the state in question usually show up in his office the next
day to defend or justify their policies. Why, one might wonder, when the EP has
no resources whatsoever available to influence the flow of world affairs – it does
not even have much of a say on the development of the EU’s own foreign and
security policy – would they bother to take it seriously? In order to understand
the power of the EP in such situations, an alternative to the materialist conception is required. – And in turn, this suggests that some elements of the prerequisites for a cosmopolitan world order may actually be in place.
A third concept that may require rethinking in light of a cosmopolitan perspective is that of sovereignty. It is defined formally with reference to international law. In order to be sovereign states, as legal entities, have traditionally
been seen to need two things: first, control over a territory – they need to have
constitutional independence; and, second, recognition from other sovereign
states. There has been no formal link between the perceived legitimacy of a particular government and the status of (external) sovereignty. However, due to two
parallel developments at the domestic and international level, that is the increase
in the number of states that have formally committed themselves to democratic
rule (1); and the strengthening of the legal protection of human rights internationally (2), a state that does not respect the sovereignty of its people faces
increasing difficulties in achieving international recognition. The establishment
of the International Criminal Court, for example, exemplifies the tendency
towards an ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›increasing conditionality of sovereignty’ (Dryzek 2006: 61). Consequently, an attempt at redefining the concept of sovereignty could take the
question of human rights into account, and move in the direction of a link
between the question of a state’s respect, or lack of such, for the fundamental
rights of the individual and its status as sovereign. Such a move would be in line
with a cosmopolitan perspective in the sense that it considers the individual as
the core legal subject. In the words of David Held: ‘The ultimate units of moral
concern are individual people, not states or other particular forms of human
association’ (Held 2003: 470). From a cosmopolitan perspective the individual
human being is seen as the holder of rights within a legal framework. Only individuals can claim moral respect. Borders of states or collectives do not make the
same strong claim (Eriksen 2003: 54)
Such reconceptualisations as the ones suggested above, and in particular the
introduction of the concept of communicative rationality, may also help us tackle
A foreign policy without a state?╇╇ 131
a second question arising through the literature on the EU as a ‘normative/ethical
power’: how can it be that a polity such as the EU – which, as noted, is neither a
state nor an international organisation – can conduct foreign and security policy
at all? The CFSP and its Security and Defence Policy (ESDP) are voluntary
arrangements, held together by a set of common norms and rules; however, the
possibility of formally sanctioning a norm breaker, an actor that does not comply
with a common standpoint, is limited. How come that this policy ‘hangs
together’, then, in particular in situations where there is no obvious and easily
calculable gain for the participants? And, what is the normative basis for this
foreign policy?
How is collective action possible? A focus on institutions and
procedures
A number of empirical observations regarding the operations of the CFSP/ESDP
suggest that cohesion within this policy field is linked to a departure from a
simple intergovernmental organising model (Sjursen 2011). Several authors refer
to a process of ‘Brusselsisation’ of European foreign and security policy (Allen
1998; Howorth 2003), which is defined as a shift in the locus of national decision making to Brussels-�based institutional structures. As a consequence it
becomes increasingly difficult for national foreign ministries to control all
aspects of national foreign policy-�making. The Brussels-�based institutions are
considered to ‘gain the advantage’ partly due to easy and daily access to information and dialogue with partner states. Further, and in line with the notion
of ‘Brusselsisation’, a number of authors point to a certain transformatory capacity of the EU’s foreign and security policy vis à vis national foreign policies
(Aggestam 2004; Tonra 2001; Torreblanca 2001; Pijpers 1996). Despite the
well-Â�known solo initiatives of some of the EU’s member states in situations of
crisis, it is argued that it is increasingly difficult for member states to escape
expectations of consistency between national foreign policy and the foreign
policy positions of the EU. The existence of clearly distinguishable national
preferences within European foreign policy has become less obvious.
The overall impression that emerges through observations such as these is
that although the CFSP remains formally intergovernmental and hence in principle is simply an instrument in the hands of the member states; the Brussels-�
based institutions have gained considerable autonomy (Tonra 2000; Duke and
Vanhoonacker 2006; Curtin 2007). They contribute to shape the EU’s foreign
and security policy and also to re-�shape national perspectives and preferences in
the field. However, a number of questions remain unanswered. Much further
research is required in order to confirm the significance and validity of the above
observations. The phenomenon of ‘Brusselsisation’ must be further specified in
order for us to assess its significance and implications for our understanding of
European foreign and security policy. Most importantly, however, how may
these developments be accounted for in theoretical terms? After all, they challenge deep seated ideas and conceptions of this policy-�field as the exclusive
132╇╇ H. Sjursen
domain of the nation state. How do member states manage to come to agreement
on a common foreign and security policy and how can we account for a voluntary relinquishing of sovereignty to common institutions?
Departing from the concept of communicative rationality, we may conceive of
dialogical actors ‘.â•›.â•›.â•›who co-Â�ordinate their plans through argumentation, aimed at
reaching mutual agreement’ (Eriksen and Weigård 1997: 221). Actors would be
conceived of as able to change viewpoints as a result of a better argument. On
this basis it is possible to conceive of a process of deliberation – of arguing and
counter arguing – as a mechanism that might contribute to account for developments beyond intergovernmentalism (Eriksen and Weigård 1997; Sjursen 2004).
Deliberation stands in contrast to threat-�based bargaining and voting as procedures for coordination. Bargaining, which is considered to be the dominant mode
within international affairs, presupposes the availability of carrots and sticks and
leads to a compromise. However within the framework of the CFSP/ESDP bargaining resources are rather slim – there are few opportunities to threaten. Hence,
at first sight this does not appear to be sufficient reason to account for a putative
move beyond intergovernmentalism. As for voting, which is mostly linked to
�domestic politics although also practised in some international settings, it is less
relevant with regard to the CFSP/ESDP as decisions in this field require unanimity. Deliberation may be particularly relevant because it is a mechanism that highlights the voluntary aspect of a process that leads to an agreement. In a context
where compliance-�ensuring mechanisms are missing, deliberation, or a process of
giving and taking reason, may be seen to compensate for this. Parties coordinate
actions through giving and taking arguments, rather than through power, threats
and/or warnings. Deliberation is expected to lead to a common understanding,
rather than a mere compromise reflecting the relative power balance between the
parties involved. Hence it may also contribute to explaining stability over time of
a given entity. The risk of defection that follows from a process of bargaining is
less pronounced, as actors agree on a joint set of reasons for common policies.8
However, such argumentative processes are fragile. Actors must be in a
setting where they are able to trust that the other parties are also playing by the
rules, i.e. are willing to abide by the better argument. Consequently, this perspective would point us in the direction of the institutions and procedures that
are in place and the extent to which they allow for argumentative processes to be
realised. What kind of values and norms are enshrined in the institutions of
European foreign and security policy, and what kind of sovereignty, power and
rationality do they presuppose or embody? To what extent are the institutions
only aggregative, as one would expect if interaction primarily takes the form of
bargaining or voting? Do they only register preferences or do they function in a
way that allows for an integration of preferences and thereby contribute to establish or provide a basis for collective action? Does a sense of trust, we-�feeling and
collegiality, an institutional identity, allowing for a common agreement on policies appear to have developed amongst the participants?
To take but some examples, mechanisms such as the requirement for consultation between member states, which entails (in principle) that member states
A foreign policy without a state?╇╇ 133
take no final position on foreign policy matters before consulting with the other
member states may be important in this respect. This requirement has (according
to observers such as Nuttall 2000) become the standard in the CFSP – that is,
there is what is often called a ‘coordination reflex’ at work in European foreign
and security policy. The frequency of meetings amongst national representatives
in the various institutional settings organised under the Council and located in
Brussels, the time spent on the preparation of these meetings as well as their
duration, may also be important factors. Research may investigate if they contribute to establish trust as well as a sense of commonality amongst the actors
involved? Committee studies of other EU areas, as well as IR studies, have documented changes in role-�perception, learning and alteration of preferences in
such sites.9
Concluding remarks
In this chapter I have presented a three-�step argument based on a particular
strand of literature on European foreign and security policy. First, I have suggested that we need to develop a critical standard for assessing the putative
normative basis of an EU foreign policy; Second, I have argued that developing
this critical standard entails a need for rethinking some core analytical categories
in the study of international relations and foreign policy. Third, this reconceptualisation opens for a distinct empirical research agenda on European foreign and
security policy, allowing us to move forward in terms of accounting for the
emergence of a foreign policy actor such as the EU.
My intention has neither been to ‘prejudge’ the outcome of any empirical
research that might be developed on the basis of concepts such as those discussed here, nor to make substantive empirical claims about the EU’s external
policies. Although, as noted, it seems to me that there are some empirical observations ‘out there’ that justify the development of such an analytical scheme,
much more systematic empirical research is required. My point has been, in the
spirit of Walter Carlsnaes’ work, that we need to reconsider, clarify and specify
the analytical tools we use in order to conduct such research (Carlsnaes 1992).
Finally, the conceptual scheme discussed here should not be seen as a call for a
‘normative’ theory of the kind that suggests what ‘ought to be done’ in European
foreign and security policy. Rather, and perhaps most importantly on this occasion, the aim has been to point towards a conceptual apparatus that would make
it possible to understand or conceive of ideal motives as a basis for action – to
suggest that there is rationality also to such a form of action. Ideal motives are
not a ‘naïve’ desire to do good. They are linked to the aim of upholding the legitimacy and stability of a political order. Thereby, such concepts may help us
understand the puzzle of how the emergence of the CFSP/ESDP has been possible even though our traditional conceptual toolbox in foreign and security
policy tells us that it is a virtual impossibility.
134╇╇ H. Sjursen
Notes
1 For a more detailed analysis of the ‘normative’ power literature see Sjursen (2006a,
2006b).
2 It follows that attempts at assessing the empirical fit of the ‘normative’ power argument
are not necessarily helpful unless a critical standard is established.
3 There are a number of different ‘cosmopolitanisms’ Brown (1992). What is presented
here can only be a sketchy outline, pointing to some core components. It draws in particular on the chapters contained in Bohman and Lutz-�Bachman (1997), Habermas
(2001) and Eriksen and Weigård (2003).
4 The argument is based on the assumption that modern law is premised on human rights.
For further discussions of the relationship between law and morality see Apel (1997)
and Habermas (1997).
5 For analyses of the legitimacy of cosmopolitan law, see Habermas (1996), Rawls
(1999), Beitz (1979) and Forst (2001).
6 The distinction is connected to that often drawn in debates on international relations
theory between cosmopolitan and communitarian perspectives (Brown 1992).
7 This conception of power may be traced back to Hanna Arendt’s consensual view of
power, and her distinction between power and coercion. She writes that: ‘Power springs
up whenever people get together and act in concert, but it derives its legitimacy from
the initial getting together rather than from any action that then may follow’ (2002:
141).
8 The distinction between deliberation as a decision-�making procedure and deliberative
democracy is important here, as the hypothesis outlined above does not imply that the
establishment of a common European foreign policy entails a democratisation of this
policy-�field. The opposite is more likely to be the case.
9 See Joerges and Vos (1999) and Risse (2000).
References
Aggestam, Lisbeth (2004). A European foreign policy? Role conceptions and the politics
of identity in Britain, France and Germany. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Political Science, Stockholm University.
Allen, David (1998). Who speaks for Europe? The search for an effective and coherent
external policy. In John Peterson and Helene Sjursen (eds), A common foreign policy
for Europe? Competing visions of the CFSP (pp.€41–48). London: Routledge.
Apel, Karl-Â�Otto (1997). Kant’s ‘Towards Perpetual Peace’ as historical prognosis from
the point of view of moral duty. In James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-�Bachmann (eds),
Perpetual peace: Essays on Kant’s cosmopolitan ideal (pp.€79–110). Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Beitz, Charles (1979). Political theory and international relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bohman, James and Lutz-�Bachmann, Matthias (eds) (1997). Perpetual peace: Essays on
Kant’s cosmopolitan ideal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Brown, Chris (1992). International relations theory: New normative approaches. Exeter:
Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Brown, Chris (1999). Universal human rights: A critique. In Timothy Dunne and Nicholas J. Wheeler (eds), Human rights in global politics (pp.€103–127). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 26(3), 245–270.
A foreign policy without a state?╇╇ 135
Carlsnaes, Walter (2006). European foreign policy. In Knud Erik Jørgensen, Mark A.
Pollock and Ben Rosamund (Eds), Handbook of European Union politics. London:
Sage.
Curtin, Deirdre (2007). Transparency, audiences and the evolving role of the EU Council
of Ministers. In John Erik Fossum and Philip Schlesinger (eds), The European Union
and the public sphere: A communicative space in the making? (pp.€ 246–258). New
York: Routledge.
Diez, Thomas (2005). Constructing the self and changing others: Reconsidering ‘Normative Power Europe’. Millennium, 33(3), 613–636.
Dryzek, John (2006). Deliberative global politics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Duchêne, François (1972). Europe’s role in world peace. In Richars Mayne (ed.), Europe
tomorrow: Sixteen Europeans look ahead (pp.€32–47). London: Fontana.
Duke, Simon and Vanhoonacker, Sophie (2006). Administrative governance in the CFSP:
Development and practice. European Foreign Affairs Review, 11(2), 163–182.
Eriksen, Erik Oddvar (2003). Why a constitutionalised Bill of Rights? In Erik Oddvar
Eriksen, John Erik Fossum and Agustín José Ménendez (eds), The chartering of
Europe: The European Charter of Fundamental Rights and its constitutional implications (pp. 48–70). Baden-Â�Baden: Nomos.
Eriksen, Erik Oddvar and Weigård, Jarle (2003). Understanding Habermas: Communicative action and deliberative democracy. London: Continuum.
Eriksen, Erik Oddvar (2006). The EU – a cosmopolitan polity? Journal of European
Public Policy, 13(2), 252–269.
Eriksen, Erik Oddvar and Weigård, Jarle (1997). Conceptualizing politics: Strategic or
communicative action? Scandinavian Political Studies, 20(3), 219–241.
Forst, Rainer (2001). The rule of reasons: Three models of deliberative democracy. Ratio
Juris, 14(4), 345–378.
Habermas, Jürgen (1990). Moral consciousness and communicative action. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Habermas, Jürgen (1996). Between facts and norms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Habermas, Jürgen (1997). Kant’s idea of perpetual peace, with the benefit of two hundred
years’ hindsight. In James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Â�Bachmann (eds), Perpetual Peace:
Essays on Kant’s cosmopolitan ideal (pp.€113–153). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Habermas, Jürgen (2001). The Postnational Constellation. Political Essays. Oxford:
Polity Press.
Haugaard, Mark (ed.) (2002). Power: A reader. Manchester: Manchester University
Press.
Held, David (2003). Cosmopolitanism: Globalization tamed? Review of International
Studies, 29(4), 465–480.
Honneth, Axel (1997). Is universalism a moral trap? The presuppositions and limits of a
politics of human rights. In James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Â�Bachmann (eds), Perpetual peace: Essays on Kant’s cosmopolitan ideal (pp. 155–178). Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Howorth, Jolyon (2003). European defence and the changing politics of the European
Union: Hanging together or hanging separately? Journal of Common Market Studies,
39(4), 765–790.
Ifestos, Panayiotis (1987). European political cooperation: Towards a framework of
supranational diplomacy? Brookfield, VT: Avebury.
Joerges, Christian and Vos, Ellen (eds) (1999). EU committees: Social regulation, law
and politics. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
136╇╇ H. Sjursen
Krasner, Stephen (1999). Logics of consequence and appropriateness in the international
system. In Morten Egeberg and Per Lægreid (eds), Organizing political institutions:
Essays for Johan P. Olsen. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press.
Lightfoot, Simon and Burchell, Jon (2005). The EU and the world summit on sustainable
development. Journal of Common Market Studies, 43(1), 75–95.
Manners, Ian (2002). Normative power Europe: A contradiction in terms? Journal of
Common Market Studies, 40(2), 235–258.
Nuttall, Simon (2000). European foreign policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pijpers, Alfred (1996). The Netherlands: The weakening pull of Atlanticism. In Christopher Hill (ed.), The actors in Europe’s foreign policy (pp.€ 247–267). London:
Routledge.
Rawls, John (1999). The law of peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Risse, Thomas (2000). ‘Let’s argue!’ Communicative action in world politics. International Organization, 54(1), 1–39.
Risse, Thomas and Börzel, Tanja A. (2007). Venus approaching Mars? The EU as an
emerging civilian world power. Paper prepared for the bi-�annual conference of the
European Union Studies Association (EUSA), Montreal, Canada, 17–19 May.
Sjursen, Helene (2004). Changes to European security in a communicative perspective.
Cooperation and Conflict, 39(2), 107–128.
Sjursen, Helene (2006a). What kind of power? Journal of European Public Policy,, 13(2),
169–181.
Sjursen, Helene (2006b). The EU as a ‘normative’ power: how can this be? Journal of
European Public Policy 13(2), 235–251.
Sjursen, Helene (2011). Not so intergovernmental after all? On democracy and integration in European foreign and security policy. Journal of European Public Policy, 18(8),
1078–1095.
Smith, Karen E. (2000). The end of civilian power EU: A welcome demise or cause for
concern? International Spectator, 35(2), 11–28.
Stavridis, Stavros T. (2001). Militarising the EU: The concept of civilian power Europe
revisited. International Spectator, 36(4), 43–50.
Tonra, Ben (2000). Committees in common: Committee governance and CFSP. In
Thomas Christiansen and Emil Kirchner (eds), Committee governance in the European
Union. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Tonra, Ben (2001). The Europeanisation of national foreign policy: Dutch, Danish and
Irish foreign policy in the European Union. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Torreblanca, J. Ignacio (2001). Ideas, preferences and institutions: Explaining the Europeanisation of Spanish foreign policy. ARENA Working Paper, 26. Oslo: ARENA.
Whitman, Richard (1998). From civilian power to superpower? The international identity
of the European Union. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
11 EU foreign policy
‘High politics’, low impact – and vice
versa?
Janne Haaland Matlary
Walter Carlsnaes’ contribution to the study of foreign policy is formidable. He
has written extensively in the most important journals in the field as well as
edited the SAGE Library of International Relations (with Guzzini 2011, a five-�
volume set) and contributed to Foreign Policy Analysis (Smith et al. 2012).
While being famous for his scholarship on the structure-�agent problem, he has
also worked extensively on EU foreign policy (Carlsnaes 1994, 2004), inter alia
as editor of a book where both the undersigned and many other contributors to
this Festschrift appeared (Carlsnaes et al. 2004).
‘Foreign policy is neither fish nor fowl in the study of politics, but an empirical subject matter straddling the boundary between the internal and the external
spheres of a state’ (Carlsnaes 2012: 3). This simple starting point has informed
my own work on foreign policy, in particular security and defence policy. Situated in the rationalist tradition, I have sought to find out what the dominant political dynamics in the European Union (EU) are (Matlary 2009). In my 1994
doctoral thesis where Carlsnaes served as first opponent at the defence, I tried to
show – somewhat unsuccessfully, I must admit with hindsight – that the EC
Commission has agenda-�setting power in the field of energy policy (Matlary
1997). The starting point and perhaps the conclusion about EU foreign and
general policy is that it is both intergovernmental and supra-�national, depending
on issue area and governments’ engagement – it is ‘neither fish nor fowl’. The
EU is a laboratory for the testing of foreign policy theories, semi-�supranational
as it is in trade policy while being intergovernmental in foreign and security
policy.
All variables vary when we try to characterise the EU: the scope of foreign
policy – when including trade, economic policy and enlargement, the EU is a
major actor on the world scene and has great powers over candidate countries
(Smith 2011); when defining the scope as traditional diplomacy and security
policy, however, the EU has little actor capacity and impact (Howorth 2011).
When we look at foreign policy tools, the picture is also bewildering: the EU has
no military capacity of its own and a small budget for traditional foreign policy.
But it can impose economic sanctions and greatly influence the rules of international trade, as well as make rules for markets, labour, capital, and a host of other
market-�related policy fields inside the EU itself, with great ramifications on the
138╇╇ J.H. Matlary
outside (Wong 2011). The sheer size of the EU as an economic actor means that
it has leverage – others must adapt to its rules (Smith and Steffenson 2011).
Thus, if we look at traditonal tools of statecraft, the EU appears to be very weak.
But if we look at economic and normative tools, the EU is very strong as an
actor.
Finally, the relationship between structure and agency is important: where the
EU has structural powers, as in trade and economic matters, it also has agency,
being vested with mixed sovereignty by and with member states. It acts as one
actor in the World Trade Organisation (WTO), albeit with a mandate sanctioned
by member states. But where the EU has no structural power, such as in traditional diplomacy, it is often very divided and unable to agree to be one actor
(Hill and Smith 2011; Edwards 2011).
Thus the EU poses many challenges to the student of foreign policy. In this
chapter I will try to analyse the political dynamics of security policy in the EU,
contrasting it with areas where the EU has structural power in order to show the
variance in EU foreign policy and to discuss the impact that the EU has as a
foreign policy actor.
EU foreign policy today
The EU is generally thought to punch below its weight in foreign policy today.
Despite the new formal powers of the High Representative, Lady Ashton, the
choice of a politician without experience in the field indicates that states are
uninterested in a strong EU foreign policy. Her predecessor Javier Solana had
much less power in formal terms but made the most of his role. Wherever the
EU could be an actor, he inserted himself. Lady Ashton, however, is slow to
react, travels much less and she has yet to make her mark. Despite some few
rather surprising moves in traditional high politics, like the embargo on imports
of Iranian oil in 2012, there has not been much common action from the EU over
the last few years.
Member states conduct their own foreign policy and do not seem to seek consultation with each other as they should according to EU rules. For instance, at
the Munich security policy conference in February 2012, Guido Westerwelle,
the German foreign minister, stated that the EU will not tolerate nuclear weapons
in Iran, but that Germany rules out military action to stop this from occurring.
Other EU states, like France and Britain, however, do not rule out military
action, and those two states were the leading actors in the Libya operation in
2011 where Germany abstained in the UN Security Council. There is thus a
glaring difference between the main actors of the EU with regard to traditional
‘high politics’.
Does this mean that the EU is impotent in foreign policy? This chapter poses
the question of EU impact in foreign policy. It will explore the perhaps counter-�
intuitive idea that EU foreign policy is the more powerful the less it is in the
headlines. Where the policy content is routine and does not provoke rivalry and
controversy among member states, it is at its most powerful. So-Â�called ‘low
EU foreign policy╇╇ 139
�
politics’
areas is where the EU has a role in the world; one that is often unnoticed. However, when we move to the area of so-Â�called ‘high politics’, the EU
seldom manages to speak with one voice and the national prerogative of member
states is challenged. Typically, security and defence issues belong in this category. In ‘high’ politics, the EU has an arena function only; and actors use and
choose arenas as they see fit.
This initial distinction between ‘high’ and ‘low’ is neither novel nor original.
The EU has great structural power because it is the largest trading bloc in the
world and it also has legal competence in trade policy, thus acting with one
voice. The fact that ‘mixite’1 applies also in this area, thus involving the member
states at every turn of trade policy negotiations at the World Trade Organization
(WTO) only seems to strengthen the EU as an actor in the world. When united
as one with a power base that is large enough to be structural; the EU is on a par
with the US.
Also in other areas of foreign policy it is well-�known that the EU has major
impact. Enlargement is the foremost. As long as a country is a candidate, the EU
Commission wields very great powers over it, to the point of being able to interfere with almost any aspect of the internal political and legal set-�up of the state
in question. The EU applies conditionality and it works. But when the state is a
member, diplomatic etiquette rules among equals. Only in very rare cases does
the EU openly criticise another member state, as for example in the case with
Hungary in 2012 after it adopted a constitution that challenged the separation of
powers. In March the same year Hungary had economic sanctions imposed on it
because the budget deficit was too large. This was the first time the EU had
imposed economic sanctions on a member state, but as the International Herald
Tribune notes, hardly the last.2 Thus, the severity of the economic crisis in
Europe seemingly made the EU bolder than before towards its members.
The EU thus has powers to have major impact on the world and in the world,
but these powers depend on issue, area and on which tools are the relevant ones.
The lack of unitary action capacity is very much of a problem when there is a
need for swift and unitary action and reaction, but the cumbersome negotiation
procedure of the EU’s decision-Â�making system may be an asset insofar as its
brings legitimacy to the decisions made. This slow grind of decision making
ensures processes where everyone is included, and also routinises policy-�making.
The outcomes of these processes are predictable and standardised and rarely
make the headlines. But such outcomes may have great impact.
In this chapter I wish to compare and contrast the dynamic of EU foreign
policy-Â�making in high politics – choosing the hardest of hard cases, namely,
security and defence involving military means – with the low politics that is
typical of areas involving third country trade and political agreements, including
aid.3 In the former area we will see that the EU has an arena function where
states can move in and out, using the arena and moving away from it. In the
period 1998 to about 2010, France and Britain used the EU arena in security politics, but now seem to have abandoned it for bilateral cooperation and coalitions
of the willing, exemplified by the Libya operation. The EU capacities built up by
140╇╇ J.H. Matlary
these two states, particularly the battle groups, are not used any more. Thus, the
impact of the EU in high politics comes and goes. When states no longer chose
the EU as their arena, there is no impact.
But when we look at the EU’s role in trade, enlargement and third country
agreements, we find a permanent set of agreements which cover the entire globe
and where the EU, represented by the Commission, is the stronger party and can
set the conditions. Political conditionality is a hallmark of all these agreements,
and the impact of the EU is continuous (Carbone 2011).
Which type of foreign policy is the more important? The policy resulting
from an occasional arena function for the EU or the policy that is always there,
as a structural feature? This question requires a discussion of power in terms of
types of power, as well as power as agency and structure.
Power, agency and structure
The EU wields structural power as the world’s major trading bloc and as the pre-Â�
eminent organisation in Europe itself. It is so important in economic terms that
almost all states in the world have to take it into account. The same structural
power pertains to the relationship between the EU Commission, the Court and
the member states: the latter become heavily ‘Europeanised’ through a steady
stream of directives from Brussels that are transposed into national law. The
Norwegian EES-Â�agreement4 with the EU, which functions rather like a ‘passive
membership’, has fundamentally transformed Norwegian domestic politics over
the years. A recent in-�depth study of this concluded that two-�thirds of all
�domestic policy in Norway stems from the EU (Europa-�Utredningen 2012).
This illustrates the point that the impact of the EU is fundamental in areas
where it is not visible in the headlines. If we accept that also economic policy is
foreign policy, the EU is a giant as an actor, both towards its member states and
towards the world. It possesses both structural power and united agency capacity. Further, this power is exercised in routinised ways and follows the treaty
rules that member states have signed on to. The ‘day to day’ nature of such
bureaucratic politics usually means that its impact goes unnoticed as it is
incremental.
In contrast, traditional foreign policy – high politics – concerns issues that are
highly visible, highly politicised, and often the subject of disagreement among
states. In the EU, foreign policy has a short history precisely because it is such a
sensitive and contested area. The European Political Cooperation (EPC) was recognised as a cooperating mechanism among the foreign ministers in 1970, but
was not included in the treaty until 1985, in the Single European Act. With an
important addition of security policy in the Treaty on European Union in 1992,
the EU has had a modest budget and apparatus for foreign policy since them,
with incremental steps towards more unitary actor capacity with each treaty revision. However, the main decision-�making basis has remained intergovernmental.
In the economic field, the EU has major structural power, and with this basis,
also a major agency ability. The EU is a unitary actor in economic policy. Within
EU foreign policy╇╇ 141
the EU in dealings with member states, DG Competition can launch morning
raids against businesses in member states, take them and/or governments to
court, impose fines, etc. Towards the international community the Trade Commissioner acts as a unitary actor in the WTO, seconded by governments and
sharing sovereignty with them. In sum, it is clear that in the economic field the
EU has unitary actor status as well as major structural power.
Turning to foreign policy proper, the situation is entirely different. As we
shall see below, there is little if any common EU actor capacity, and there is no
structural power in the security field. Although the EU may be argued to represent European values and democracy, human rights, and rule of law as a bloc in
the world, this structural power is activated only when there is unitary action.
There is no structural power vested in the EU; the various tools of power
‘belong’ to member states, and are only activated when there is a decision among
all to do so, i.e. to create unitary actor capacity. This rarely happens, although
the EU manages to agree with speak with one voice at the United Nations
General Assembly (UNGA) each autumn delivering one intervention on behalf
of all members and voting in the same ways on resolutions. The process towards
agreeing on one stance is subject to least common denominator-�outcomes, as
was the case when Sweden and other ‘progressives’ had to give in to Poland,
Malta and other states that refused to promote abortion as a woman’s right at the
UN during the spring of 2012, much to the regret of the Norwegians (FN-�
sambandet 8 March 2012). Thus, unitary action comes at the price of watered-�
down substance and the impact is accordingly limited.
Thus, we see that the EU is powerful when acting as one, but this happens
routinely only rarely, as in the case mentioned above. Usually there is no unitary
EU action – at the UN Security Council, the Organisation for Security and Cooperation in Europe (OSCE), the Council of Europe or at NATO – despite the fact
that European states mostly agree on foreign policy. Thus, the lack of common
action is the more remarkable. When it comes to using military force or to
threaten such use in coercive diplomacy, the lack of unitary action is typical.
Summing up, structural power has impact, even when there is no unitary actor
capacity. States must adapt to the way a major actor acts – be it the US or the
EU. But when there is unitary actor capacity coupled with structural power, the
impact is even greater. The EU is an economic giant – despite the current financial crisis, and when it can act as one, as in trade agreements with third countries
or at the WTO, it is one of the three most powerful actors in the world in terms
of impact. The US, China, and the EU ‘rule’ the world economically.
But without structural powers and unitary action capacity, the EU is reduced
to a mere arena for intergovernmental action – one that can be abandoned at will
by states.
Case: EU security and defence policy
Britain and France undertook to ‘boost’ EU security policy around 1997–1998.
They also turned away from the EU some ten years later, simply by not using the
142╇╇ J.H. Matlary
battle groups they had created. The question is why these two states chose to
build up EU security policy in the first place, and then why they abandoned it for
bilateral cooperation and NATO as their preferred arena. When France returned
to NATO’s military structure in 2008, the French–British cooperation took place
there or bilaterally, no longer in the EU.
Understanding the political dynamics behind these developments allows us to
infer whether there was an EU role in this at all, or whether the EU was simply
an arena.
France and Britain share a number of important security interests that explain
why the European Security and Defence Policy (ESDP) got seriously under way
after 1998. France and Britain ‘hang together’ in mutual dependency in the
ESDP: neither state can realise this policy without the other. Britain thinks
France cannot be left alone in the ESDP because that would endanger the
primacy of NATO in the European security architecture. On the other hand, the
French conclude that Britain cannot be allowed to dominate the ESDP as that
would ensure that the EU would rank as a second-�order security organisation.
Both states are therefore bound to participate in all ESDP initiatives in which
one of them engages in order to shape, constrain or counteract the former – provided that one of them opts to use the EU arena (Matlary 2009). As Howorth
puts it, ‘There is a paradox in the French–British security relationship. The two
sides cannot manage a European security policy without one another, yet they
have enormous difficulty, where transatlantic policy is concerned, in working
with one another’ (2005: 39). There is an interdependence between France and
Britain despite the different strategic interests they have. Even strong governments have a need to operate at an international level, in this case that of the EU.
The EU decision in 2003 to form 16 battlegroups and to rotate them two by
two biannually was spearheaded by the UK and France, who also have lead
nation roles. A lead nation role in command and control is not realistic unless it
contributes significantly on the ground. Big states are therefore dominant in military integration schemes because they can offer HQs as well as entire units, like
battle groups.
The battle groups of the EU illustrate the discrepancy between the military
integration commitment and the intergovernmental nature of political decision
making. Although the EU Council will decide on deployment by consensus, only
those states that are military contributors are likely to matter in real terms. We
know that the coalition of leaders regarding the use of force in the EU consists
of France and the UK, with the support of Germany, but that no request for an
EU deployment arises without prior consultation with troop contributing states.
We can assume that the EU will remain vague on the question of ‘grand strategy’, and will be willing to deploy only on an ad hoc basis, as in the case mentioned. Thus, the consensual character of the decision-Â�making process will
remain in formal terms, but the real decision making will evolve around those
states that are on rotation with a battle group, always involving the major states
France and the UK. In the case of multinational battle groups, all contributing
states are bound to deploy together even if the formal option of defecting exists.
EU foreign policy╇╇ 143
As Andersson points out in his study of the Nordic–Baltic battle group, even
non-Â�EU member Norway is formally ‘consulted’ on the decision to deploy
(2006: 39). In theory, states can withdraw their contribution. In reality to do so
would be a significant blow to the credibility of that battlegroup member state.
Which political dynamic?
In the example of EU security and defence policy we see that states – even large
ones – seek influence through an international organisation (IO) which serves as
an arena for state action. Small states in particular seem to seek power within
IOs as they do not have the ‘great power option’. The typology of power suggested by Barnett and Duvall (2005) is useful in this regard: power can be direct
– A makes B do something B would not otherwise do; but it can also be indirect,
in the form of institutional rule-Â�making – when A cannot compel B to do something, he can create conditions for B’s freedom of action that set the agenda or
preclude certain types of decision. Thus, building international regimes, institutions, and law are not power-�neutral activities, but are as much a result of strategic thinking as is coercive diplomacy.
Barnett and Duvall (ibid.: 9) criticise much of the liberal institutionalist literature on the basis that it ignores power and presents international cooperation
and the concept of governance as benign arrangements for solving ‘cooperation
problems’. But institutional power, they point out, ‘can operate .â•›.â•›. in underlying
social structures and systems of knowledge that advantage some and disadvantage others’.
States can be expected to seek IO arenas for bolstering their power, using
indirect power rather than direct power. As multilateral legitimacy matters, even
in high politics, this may explain why also great powers turn to IOs like the EU.
But acting in and through an IO does not mean that the IO in question is
�important in its own right. It has an arena function that ends when states cease to
use it. This is the political dynamic of security and defence policy in the EU, I
argue.
Security policy in the EU is driven largely by the national interests of states.
However, these national interests are not the traditional, static geo-�political interests that used to characterise security policy. The cooperation that occurs in the
EU foreign policy area is often referred to as a ‘pooling’ of sovereignty. This
means that states agree to cooperate, but that this cooperation is reversible
although it may occasionally entail obligations.
The main political dynamic in EU security policy is directly tied to the post-�
national situation in Europe: the more optional the war, the weaker the support
achieved. Hence the need for ‘negotiating’ between the domestic and the multilateral levels on the part of the state executive. Further, the more dangerous the
mission, the more contested it becomes. Taken together, this means that an
‘optional war’ that is dangerous equals wavering and weakening public support.
As we move from humanitarian missions of peacekeeping into very dangerous
wars in places like Afghanistan and Iraq, the domestic political stakes are much
144╇╇ J.H. Matlary
higher. Which government can survive major losses in an optional war in a
society that no longer understands the risks of war?
In sum, this fundamental change makes for new security policy dynamics in
Western nations, particularly in Europe. The relevance of the domestic policy
level becomes high also in security policy. Foreign policy analysis as well as the
more specialised security studies field is not usually concerned with domestic
factors. The dominant theory of security studies – realism – rules out the importance of domestic factors altogether, dismissing them. States are thought to be
unitary actors pursuing a geo-�political interest where self-�help and relative power
counts. The realist view is that states always pursue security because they are
always threatened in an anarchic world. Thus, the state’s interests are given, and
take pre-�eminence over all other political interests because they concern the very
survival of the state. Today’s optional wars are of another kind than the existential state-Â�to-state war. As security and defence policy has become ‘normalised’,
so has the political process.
Where can we find analytical frameworks that help in the study of these new
security dynamics? In the international relations literature, there is still very little
emphasis on domestic determinants of foreign policy even if they now impact
heavily also on security policy. The most sophisticated theorist of the domestic –
international foreign policy dynamic is Robert Putnam. In his renowned article
about two-�level games from 1988, he outlines how government executives use
their exclusive access to both levels to gain advantages on both (Putnam 1988).
When a minister emerges from a EU ministerial meeting, he addresses his
national press and tells them how he has advanced national interests. If his interests were not favoured, he is able to argue that ‘the EU made me do it’– and so
blame the EU.
Putnam defines several policy dynamics. Policy pressure from the international
level can be used to change policy domestically, as the government binds itself to
international obligations and can argue that it is bound to implement them at home.
Also, domestic constraints can be used to get one’s way in the international organisation – in fact, the more bound one is, the more one may gain because other states
that want to reach an agreement and have larger scope for negotiation may be
forced to concede much more than they would normally do. The government elite
can play both levels of policy to their advantage, as we shall see in this book. In
security and defence policy, governments can blame the international level when
things go wrong; they can share risk and cost, and they can use the second level to
effect changes at home. In neutral states like Sweden and Finland, the EU has been
used to change the meaning of neutrality as one example of how the international
level impacts on the national level (Græger et al. 2002).
Having a multilateral ‘cover’ becomes increasingly important and makes for
a precarious balance between commitment in ongoing operations and domestic
public opinion. Western elites increasingly lack the experience of war and a ‘war
ethic’, and the same must be said for Western publics When media report from
the battle field, criticism mounts, and NGOs and media request detailed information on targets, weaponry, calibration, etc. (Frantzen 2005). They demand the
EU foreign policy╇╇ 145
right to change views on deployment as fighting progresses and are often swayed
by day-�to-day events in the field. Only in operations without much media
coverage can elite control be maintained – both political and military. But almost
all military operations today are highly media aware. Media are often ‘embedded’ in operations themselves, and in general, operations must count on much
media interest once military force is employed.
The Putnam (1988) framework of analysis postulates that states strong in the
policy field in question – here security and defence – also can make use of the
two-�level dynamics. The strong state can impact the more on negotiations and
use the IO as a multiplier for its interests. Where the weak state can make use of
its weakness to argue that others may accommodate it in order to an agreement
to be made, a strong state can play games more freely.
The development of this theme is especially interesting in the work by
Koenig-Â�Archibugi (2004), who advances the thesis that governments ‘collude’ in
seeking a strengthened role for themselves vis-Â�à-vis their own publics. He cites
examples that show how the Italian government has opted for collusion in order
to effect change at home, acting from a position of weakness: ‘During the Cold
War, the government was quite happy to surrender sovereignty to international
organisations if it meant removing defence from the political debate’ (ibid.: 173).
This has also been the case with Germany in the security and defence field.
Thus, weak governments will welcome ‘self-Â�binding’ at the international
level precisely because the domestic level is so important in policy-�making. As
for states with strong powers in a given issue area, they may need ‘pooling’ of
sovereignty for other reasons, such as ‘pooling’ of risk and cost, and/or shaping
of the IO in question. The importance of the EU means that also EU-�sceptical
states like Britain have to participate.
Thus, postmodern national interests are very different from the static geo-�
political interests of traditional realist security policy. Instead they are change�
able and optional, but not more optional than the fact that a government that
wants influence in NATO and/or the EU must be able to contribute relevant military capacities and take risk. What we see emerge here is a fascinating political
dynamic: the domestic level now matters most in security and defence policy,
but its interests are often different to those of the government. The government
typically wants to make major contributions to operations under NATO and the
EU in order to strengthen their hand in these and to maintain them as such, and
governments regard security policy in the traditional manner of ‘high politics’.
Publics and domestic actors have little insight into and knowledge of this traditionally secret policy area, and are wont to use civilian yard sticks and criteria
for making their judgements. There is controversy over risk and rising casualties,
over cost and longevity of operations, and over motivations: why participate in
optional wars, may be for the sake of gaining general influence? Both weak and
strong governments need the multilateral setting of IOs, as arena, scape-�goat and
as raw material for shaping their strategies.
Thus, the French and the British cooperated bilaterally and also opted to
develop the EU in this policy field. The inventions of the battlegroups as well as
146╇╇ J.H. Matlary
the EDA were made by them. The battle groups were a major novelty requiring enormous effort by many states. Yet the battlegroups of the EU have not
been deployed in the six years since 2006. The British under PM Gordon
Brown refused to deploy them to the Congo. It remains unclear why, but also
this was a highly optional ‘war’. It seems that both the British and the French
decided to ‘nationalise’ their cooperation some years ago. Today their bilateral cooperation continues as the major showcase of such in Europe, but it is
now bilateral, presented as a ‘partnership’, and the international arena both
states choose, is NATO, not the EU. The Libya operation was planned and led
by London and Paris, and only belatedly did NATO assume the role of military command and control, after intensive lobbying to be accorded such a
role. NATO’s secretary-Â�general was not even invited to the crucial coalition
meeting in the Elysee Palace on Saturday, 22 March 2011, when the operation commenced. Only the heads of state from contributing nations were
invited.
Each of the two states, France and the UK, could have provided national HQs
to command the operation. In the Libyan operation the EU had no role whatsoever. It was not invited to any meetings, only the Germans wanted to involve the
EU (albeit not themselves).
The Libyan case illustrates the logic presented above. Security and defence
policy is conducted at the national level, and states use IOs as arenas. They need
and want such arenas in a post-�modern political setting where domestic politics
matter also in this field. Yet the arena can be abandoned, as it was in the case of
the EU’s battle groups. Despite the major effort made at creating the battlegroups, France and the UK have retreated to their bilateral collaboration in
security and defence and sometimes opt to bring this to another arena, namely,
NATO. But also here the movement is from capital to IO, based on pure
intergovernmentalism.
To sum up, the empirical data on EU security and defence policy strongly
suggest that it has an arena function only. In the eight year period between
1998–2006 it played a role, but was subject to great powers’ political will to use
it. After 2006 the EU played no military role.
Conclusion: does the EU need military power?
Joseph Nye has written much about contemporary power – types and levels
(2002, 2008, 2011). In his most recent book, The Future of Power (2011), he
argues that
today, power in the world is distributed in a complex three-�dimensional
chess-�game. On the top chess-�board, military power is largely uni-�polar and
the US is likely to remain supreme for some time. But on the middle chess-�
board, economic power has been multi-�polar for more than a decade, with
the United States, Europe, Japan, and China as the major playersâ•›.â•›.â•›.
(XV)
EU foreign policy╇╇ 147
Thus, on the structural level of economic power we find Europe (EU) – as one of
four major actors. In the field of military power, however, no one rivals the US.
How important are types of power in relation to each other? Can they be compared at all? Nye attempts to do so, and concludes his analysis of the utility of
force today thus:
Military force remains important because it helps to structure world politics
.â•›.â•›. markets and economic power rest upon political frameworks. In chaotic
conditions of great uncertainty, markets fail. Political frameworks rest upon
norms and institutions, but also upon management of coercive power.
(ibid.: 49)
In other words, the ordering power of military force is indispensable, even if this
source of power cannot be used to achieve gains as it could in previous
centuries.
Applied to the EU, we can say that the stability and order of its member states
presupposes the deterrent effect of police and military, and beyond the EU, that
this role of force is even more important. Ideally therefore the EU should be able
to complement its economic power with military force, but it cannot. It relies on
the coercive ability of economic and political dependence and on its ‘power of
attraction’, assuming that Europe remains politically stable.
Yet, the territorial dimension of power is not the most relevant one today.
Power is related to innovation, education, and global attractiveness. It is increasingly a matter of effective public diplomacy and of being, in the words of Chayes
and Chayes (2005); a constructive international citizen. The competition is not for
land, but for attraction talent and capital, what we can refer to as innovation ability.
The EU’s race to overcome the economic crisis is necessary in order for it to work
on becoming the most attractive and innovative region in the world, in order to
achieve the goal set by the Lisbon strategy. Military power and the ability to
coerce through such power seem rather irrelevant to the EU’s political goals.
The EU ‘commands’ economic power, not military power. It has structural-Â�
level economic power because the EU is an internal market and because it can
act in the world both as a major rule-�maker, as in the WTO, and because it uses
its economic power of money and of attraction as the template for impacting on
candidates, third countries, and the other actors in the world economy. The economic strength of the market and the structural funds provides the EU’s power
of coercion as well as attraction. In addition to this the EU mostly acts as one in
this field, and the impact is great, especially when contrasted to the feeble role
the EU plays in traditional ‘high politics’. Here it is but an arena; ‘now you see
it, now you don’t’.
Notes
1 The term refers to shared competence, and has been developed as a legal category
by€ the EU court. In practice this means that all member states must co-�sign a WTO
148╇╇ J.H. Matlary
agreement, and they also partake in discussions on the mandates of the trade commissioner in Brussels in a committee wittily named ‘le comittee des belles-Â�meres’.
2 International Herald Tribune, ‘EU agrees to punish Hungary for budget slips’, 14
March 2012.
3 I focus in depth on the former policy area, and use ‘low’ politics in the EU as illustrations only. Space does not permit equal attention to both.
4 European Economic Area.
References
Andersson, Jan J. (2006). Armed and ready? The EU battlegroup concept and the Nordic
battlegroup. Stockholm: International Peace Research Institute.
Barnett, Michael and Duvall, Raymond (eds) (2005). Power in global governance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carlsnaes, Walter and Smith, Steve (1994). European foreign policy: The EC and changing perspectives on Europe. London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter and Smith, Steve (2004). Contemporary European foreign policy.
London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter and Smith, Steve (2012). Foreign policy analysis in international relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chayes, Abram and Chayes, Antonia Handlerl (1995). The new sovereignty. compliance
with international regulatory agreements. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Frantzen, Henning A. (2005). NATO and peace support operations, 1991–1999. London:
Frank Cass.
Edwards, Geoffrey (2011). The patterns of the EU’s global activity. In Christopher Hill
and Michael Smith (eds), International relations and the European Union (pp.€44–75).
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Græger, Nina, Larsen, Henrik and Ojanen, Hanna (2002). The ESDP and the Nordic
countries. Berlin: Institut fur Europeaische Politik.
Hill, Christopher and Smith, Steve (2011). Acting for Europe: Reassessing the EU’s place
in international relations. In Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (eds), International
relations and the European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Howorth, Jolyon (2005). From security to defence: The evolution of the CFSP. In Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (eds), International relations and the European Union.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Howorth, Jolyon (2011). The EU’s security and defence policy: Towards a strategic
approach. In Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (eds), International relations and the
European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Koenig-Â�Archibugi, Mathias (2004a). International governance as a new raison d’etat? The
case of the EU CFSP. European Journal of International Relations, 10(2), 147–188.
Matlary, Janne Haaland (1997). Energy policy in the European Union. The European
Union series. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Matlary, Janne Haaland (2009). European Union security dynamics: In the new national
interest. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Nye, Joseph (2011). The future of power. Philadelphia, PA: Public Affairs.
Putnam, Robert (1988). The logic of two-�level games. International Organisation, 42(3),
427–460.
Smith, Michael (2011) «The EU and the US». In Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (eds),
International relations and the European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
EU foreign policy╇╇ 149
Smith, Steve, Hadfield, Amelia and Dunne, Tim (eds) (2012). Foreign Policy Analysis:
Theories, Actors, Cases. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wong, Reuben (2011) The Europeanization of foreign policy. In Christopher Hill and
Michael Smith (eds), International relations and the European Union. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Carbone Maurizio, (2011). The EU and the developing world: Partnership, poverty, politicization. In Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (eds), International relations and the
European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Smith, Michael and Steffenson, Rebecca (2011). The EU and the United States. In Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (eds), International relations and the European Union
(Ch. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
12 The EU foreign and security
policy
High expectations, low capabilities?
Pernille Rieker
Introduction
As Knud Erik Jørgensen has argued in Chapter 9, vertical perspectives (emphasizing the relationship between the national and the European levels) have dominated horizontal perspectives (emphasizing the EU as an actor) in the literature
on European foreign policy. This chapter offers a horizontal perspective, but also
recognizes the importance of the national level, in that I argue for a multi-�level
governance perspective on European foreign policy. More systematic empirical
studies of the functioning of European foreign policy are needed for us to understand and thereby conceptualize this field better. Walter Carlsnaes has made an
excellent contribution with the edited volume, Contemporary European Foreign
Policy (Carlsnaes et al. 2004). This chapter follows up on this endeavour.1
For over 30 years, scholars have argued that the EC/EU has lacked the required
capabilities needed to be perceived as a credible actor (Bull 1983; Hill 1993, 2007;
Hoffmann 2000; Hyde-Â�Price 2006, 2008; Kagan 2003). However, the EU’s many
achievements in the area of security policy since the early 1990s should provide
ample grounds for concluding that it must now be seen as a security policy actor.
Suffice it here to mention only four. First, the EU has had a Common Foreign and
Security Policy since 1992 (CFSP) and a Common European Security and Defence
Policy (CSDP) since 1999. Second, in 2003 the member states agreed on a European Security Strategy (ESS) that identifies threats, objectives and instruments.
Third, the European Union (represented by the European Commission, the Council
or the newly established European External Action Service) has implemented a
wide range of programmes and activities to promote stability and conflict prevention in Europe and all over the world. Finally, the EU has had responsibility for a
considerable number of crisis management operations (17 civilian/civil–military
operations and seven military operations) since 2003.2
While the European integration process has long been an important security
policy instrument that has helped to prevent wars and conflict among its
members, as well as having a stabilizing effect on the region as such, today’s
European Union can also be characterized as a security policy actor. Surely,
then, the question is no longer whether the EU is a security policy actor, but
rather what kind of actor it is.
The EU foreign and security policy╇╇ 151
Among those who accept that the EU is an actor, it has been common to
emphasize its importance as some kind of normative or cosmopolitan actor
(Manners 2002, 2006; McCormick 2006; Sjursen 2006; see also Chapter 10 in
this volume). While providing insights, this literature has tended to downplay
the capability issue. In this chapter, I focus on the actual functioning of the EU
as a security actor and how it differs from most other actors in international
society (Moravcsik 2010). The fact that the EU is something between an international organization and a federal state makes it different from OSCE and NATO
on the one hand, and national security policy actors on the other (Rieker 2006,
2009). Instead of using the normative power argument as a point of departure, I
will therefore start by analysing the relationship between integration and security
and then turn to the various actor capabilities of the EU. While Christopher
Hill’s (1993) argument concerning the gap between expectations and capabilities
remains valid to some extent, the EU’s many achievements in security policy
since the early 1990s also illustrate the need to revisit his argument, as I intend
to do here.3
Security and integration
There is general agreement that the integration process as such has been, and
remains, an important security policy instrument. In fact, it was precisely the
desire for lasting peace and stability in Europe after two disastrous world wars
that made the integration process so important. Also other factors have contributed to peace and stability in this part of the world, but there can be little doubt
that stronger economic integration in Europe has been a pivotal instrument for
creating peace. According to Buzan and his colleagues, the ‘European Security
Complex’ is characterized by centralization, with the EU as the core. Further,
they hold, a reversal of this process is unlikely, since any form of fragmentation
of the European integration process would have negative security policy consequences (Buzan 1991; Buzan and Wæver 2004; Buzan et al. 1998: 12).
The integration process has had security policy consequences beyond the
Western part of Europe. The Eastern enlargement of the EU after the end of the
Cold War, and more recently also its European Neighbourhood Policy (ENP)
must be seen as continuations of this idea (Epstein and Sedelmeier 2008; Rieker
2012; Sæter 2003). These projects have aimed at creating peace and stability on
the continent through commitments and interdependence. Membership of the EU
requires, among other things, a well-�functioning market economy, democracy
and respect for human rights and minorities. This means that the prospect of
joining the EU can serve to discipline and prevent conflicts internally in these
aspirant countries and thereby in the region as such. This is evident in relation to
the 12 countries accepted as members in recent years, and among current applicants in the Balkans.
While the EU is a peace project in itself, with the desire for peace and security
serving as the main reason behind the integration process, the fields of security
studies literature and integration literature have long been seen as belonging to
152╇╇ P. Rieker
two different disciplines. With the security community literature, we find an
opening for a combination of the two.
The EU as a tightly coupled security community
The concept security community was first developed by Karl Deutsch in the late
1950s (Deutsch 1957) in order to contribute to a deeper understanding of the
tight transatlantic relations that, in his view, could be characterized as a pluralistic community built on co-�operation and transactions on many levels, with
common understandings and common values. The concept has since been
applied and further developed by other scholars. Adler and Barnett (1998), for
instance, have examined how it can be used for understanding other regional
processes around the world. They distinguish between loosely and tightly
coupled security communities. Both types are characterized by mutual dependence and respect, but differ in the degree of political integration: a loosely
coupled security community has a low degree of political integration, a tightly
coupled one has a high degree of political integration. This is not a dichotomous
relationship. We should perceive such of a security community as a continuum,
with differing possible degrees of loose or tight coupling. The EU, being something in-�between an international organization and a federal state, has gradually
evolved and moved along this continuum, becoming an increasingly tightly
coupled security community.
Just what do we mean by saying that the EU is a tightly coupled security
community? And what consequences does this have for its security policy role?
In order to grasp how the EU functions in practice, we need to take a closer look
at how it is governed. Perhaps the functioning of the EU can be best understood
as a kind of multi-�level governance system where the member states, the Council
of European Union and the European Commission all play important roles.
The EU understood as a multi-�level governance system
Multi-Â�level governance refers to a ‘polity-Â�creating process in which authority
and policy-Â�making influence are shared across multiple levels of government –
sub national, national and supranational’ (Marks and Hooghe 2001: 2). It can be
argued that the EU as a whole functions as a multi-�level governance system in
most policy areas and that this is a consequence of it being neither a true federation nor a true international organization. However, this approach has been
applied in order to understand how the European Community (previously
referred to as ‘pillar 1’) functions, and why that particular area has achieved such
a high degree of decision-�making power. Other policy areas, such as the
Common Foreign and Security Policy (‘pillar 2’), have generally been analysed
in line with an interest-�based perspective that sees the member states as the most
important actors.
In fact, an institutional perspective can be fruitful for analysing also this
policy area. Even though CFSP still is a policy area where most decisions are
The EU foreign and security policy╇╇ 153
made by unanimity, and where the member states are the main actors, the EU
level – represented by the Council Secretariat and the Commission and now primarily the External Action Service – has gradually come to assume a more
central role in the development and implementation of foreign and security
policy.
Several initiatives have come from the EU level (until recently represented by
the High Representative for CFSP alone or together with the Commissioner for
External Relations). This was the case, for instance, for the programme for conflict prevention decided upon in 2001, the European Security Strategy in 2003,
the report on climate change and international security that the member states
jointly supported in 2008 and the recent report (2011) proposing an EU response
to the Arab awakening and the changing EU neighbourhood. In addition, most
proposals for the development of the CSDP have been prepared by the High
Representative (until recently, often in cooperation with the presidency) before
the members adopt them at the bi-�annual summits. With the establishment in of
a new High Representative assisted by an External Action Service (EEAS), the
EU level has assumed even greater importance.
It is also the EU level that, to a large extent, implements the CFSP. Until
recently the Commission has implemented activities within the frame work of
civilian crisis management and conflict prevention, with the Council implementing the ESDP operations. Now, with the establishment of the new High Representative and the EEAS, these efforts must be seen as a whole. The difference
between the ‘pillars’ within the EU has become less important than previously.
A perspective on the CFSP that stresses the importance of different levels has
the advantage that it avoids giving the EU level too little or too much emphasis,
which is the case with, respectively, the intergovernmental and the neo-�
functionalist perspectives on EU policy (Rosamond 2000). A multi-�level governance perspective enables us to study the EU as an actor, on the basis of how
decisions in are made and how they are implemented.
At this point, we may conclude that the EU is a security policy actor underway to becoming a tightly coupled security actor, with a decision-�making structure best characterized as multi-�level governance. Let us now see what
consequences such a perspective on the EU could have for drawing conclusions
as to its capacity to act.
The EU’s actor capabilities
Actorness in international politics may be understood in various ways. While
some scholars stress the importance of internal resources (Sjöstedt 1977), others
put more emphasis on the perceptions of international society (Bretherton and
Vogler 2006). I would argue that two basic preconditions must be fulfilled in
order to claim that an actor has the capacity to act and to avoid a gap between
expectations and capabilities (Hill 1993). First, the actor has to be able to formulate clear objectives and make decisions according to these objectives; second,
the actor must have the necessary administrative and operational capabilities
154╇╇ P. Rieker
(Rieker 2009). To what extent has the EU managed to develop these
capabilities?
Ability to formulate objectives
The EU lives up to expectations when it comes to the ability to formulate objectives. Its member states have adopted a wide range of declarations and agreed on
fairly ambitious objectives within the area of foreign and security policy, which
would indicate that the political will to strengthen the EU as a security policy
actor is in place. This is also made explicit in the European Security Strategy
adopted in December 2003. Here the member states identify potential threats,
strategic objectives and implications for the instruments of the EU (European
Council 2003).
In order to implement these objectives, the EU must be able to make �decisions
that commit its members. As was seen in relation to the Iraq War in 2003, the
EU will not be able to act if its various member states differ deeply in their
approaches and views concerning a given conflict. In the case of Iraq there was a
divide between those who supported a US-�led war, and those that were against.
A further example: the EU countries failed to send troops to Congo in November
2008 – a country then on the brink of exploding into civil war. Whereas France
was keen to send EU’s battle groups, which have been developed for precisely
for such cases, Germany feared that such an EU force could weaken the legitimacy of the UN operation in the country.
Despite occasional difficulties in making decisions, there have been many
instances of internal ‘crisis’ or major international events that led to decisions
which have made the EU gradually more capable of action. While CFSP was
established as a consequence of the end of the Cold War, the establishment of
the ESDP came as a consequence of the Balkan wars and the recognition that the
EU would have to strengthen its capacity for handling international crises in its
neighbourhood. Moreover, the events of 9/11 led to a strengthening of the EU’s
anti-�terror policy. Internal disagreements among member states prior to the Iraq
War also helped to bring about the adoption of a European Security Strategy.
Finally, the enlargement of the EU has led to institutional reforms, here materialized in the establishment of a High Representative for Foreign Affairs and
Security Policy (Catherine Ashton) and an External Action Service aimed at
making an enlarged Union more capable of acting – also in security policy.4
There is also broad agreement within the EU concerning what kind of security
policy orientation it should have – for instance, as to the importance of multiÂ�
lateral institutions, and that the focus should be on a broad approach to security
where conflict prevention and civilian crisis management play an important role
in addition to the development of a military crisis-�management capacity. Thus,
the member states have managed to agree on the overarching objectives even
though they may from time to time find it difficult to make decisions in relation
to specific crises and conflicts. On the other hand, the EU has implemented a
total of 24 crisis-�management operations, and has developed capabilities in
The EU foreign and security policy╇╇ 155
�
intelligence,
analysis and anti-�terror policy: surely evidence that it does have the
ability to make decisions.
Capabilities and resources
In addition to the ability to formulate objectives and make decisions, an actor
needs certain administrative capabilities. According to March and Olsen (1995:
91), these include a well-�functioning set of rules, rights and authorities, necessary resources (in the form of budgets, staffs and equipment), knowledge and
competence, and organizational capacity. The remainder of this chapter will
examine the extent to which the EU possesses these administrative capabilities
in foreign, security and defence policy.
1╇ The existence of a formal set of rules, rights and authorities
A smoothly-�functioning set of rules, rights and authorities is necessary in order
to act, since this clarifies what the actor can do, in what way and with what kind
of means. In security policy, the EU’s rules have gradually become more extensive. The CFSP is currently regulated in the Title V of the Treaty on European
Union signed at Maastricht in 1992 and revised in 1997, 2001 and 2007.
The Treaty identifies some overarching goals and principles (for instance, that
the CFSP shall be in accordance with the UN Charter and with international
law), together with more detailed rules clarifying the competencies of the different EU institutions. Whereas the CFSP was included in the 1992 Maastricht
Treaty, the establishment of a High Representative for CFSP was not introduced
in the Treaty until 1997. The position was meant to be held by the Secretary
General of the Council, thereby contributing to make this policy area more
visible at the overall EU level. The Commission – otherwise the most important
institution of the European Union – has a more limited role in this policy area.
Article 27 of the Treaty confirms, however, that the Commission s is to be fully
associated with the work under the CFSP and is to ensure that EU policy is
undertaken in accordance with the acquis communautaire. In addition, the Commission has, through the budget, a certain role concerning implementation of this
policy. The Commission may also, in the same way as the member states,
propose changes to the Treaty.
Thus, there can be little doubt that the EU is equipped with a set of rules in
the field of security policy, and that these have been gradually strengthened since
the CFSP was first established in 1992. Still, this policy area is formally an intergovernmental cooperation where most of the decisions are taken by unanimity.
On the other hand, as we have shown, there has been a development towards
greater influence by the EU level, also in this area. The establishment of a High
Representative for CFSP and the gradual strengthening of the role of the Commission have led to more supranationality here as well. The Lisbon Treaty,
making the High Representative (HR) also the Vice President (VP) of the Commission, has made this even more evident. The fact that it is the HR/VP (and no
156╇╇ P. Rieker
longer a rotating presidency) who is to preside over the Foreign Affairs Council
as well as representing the EU in matters of CFSP also strengthens the role of
the EU level in this policy area. The new diplomatic service, the European External Action Service (EEAS), will also assist the HR/VP in fulfilling her mandate.
While this new service will not be fully operational before 2012, perhaps even
later, the considerable capabilities at its disposal might prove crucial when in
place. One clear result is a stronger centre formation. Another possible development is the downscaling of some of the member states’ capabilities. Already
some member states have announced that they might reduce their own national
diplomatic corps as a consequence of the EU developing this service under the
EEAS. In periods of financial uncertainty and debt problems, many member
states may wish to consider more cost-�effective arrangements, and they may
prove more willing to consider the benefits of economies of scale.
2╇ Limited, but increasing, resources
In addition to a formal set of rules, an actor also needs certain resources, such as
a stable economic frame, staff and equipment, in order to implement its policy.
As we shall see, the EU has had limited but increasing resources in this area.
In 2011 the CFSP budget (€0.3 billion) represented 0.2 per cent of the overall
EU budget. If we include all the funds earmarked for its international activities –
in the budget referred to as ‘the EU as a global actor’ (€8.8 billion), which
includes the enlargement process, neighbourhood policy, development assistance, various activities to promote democracy and human rights around the
world, CFSP and the Stability Instrument – this represents 6.1 per cent of the
total EU budget.5 In other words, only a very small part of the budget is used for
various security policy initiatives, even when we apply a broad understanding of
‘security’ as a basis. On the other hand, it should be noted that the CFSP budget
has increased substantially since 2002 (from €30 million to €300 million) and
that the financial framework for the period 2007 to 2013 envisages a further
increase (up to €340 million).6
As the EU budget goes to the activities of the Commission, EU military
operations will be covered by national contributions, not by this budget. National
contributions come mainly from those countries that participate in the various
operations. To make the EU more dynamic here, however, the member states
have agreed on a financing mechanism, ATHENA, which allows the Council
Secretariat to have a certain amount of funding available to cover the shared
costs of an operation – typically, the cost of headquarters, infrastructure and
medical help. The participating countries then contribute with soldiers, weapons
and equipment. But since ATHENA represents only 10 per cent of the total costs
of a military operation, the EU is still dependent on the participation of one or
more of the larger member states.7 A major challenge to the EU is still that it
lacks funds to enable it to act quickly in an emergency. This leads to a disparity
between the ambitions expressed in the EU’s official security strategy and the
means it actually has at its disposal.
The EU foreign and security policy╇╇ 157
The Council and the Commission are together responsible for ensuring that
the EU has a consistent foreign policy. This includes all aspects of external relations, security policy, economy and aid. Among the Commission’s staff, there
were, prior to the establishment of the EEAS, only 6 per cent who in one way or
the other were working within this field, even though many different offices and
‘ministries’ are involved. In the Council Secretariat there has, since the establishment of the CFSP, been an increase in the number of employees working
with this policy area. All the same, the criticism that the EU has many institutions and few people to implement its security policy is probably still valid.
Although the number of employees may not be the most important factor in
determining whether the EU is an effective security policy actor, it gives nevertheless an indication of how much priority is accorded to this policy area.
Beside budgets and staff, an actor must also have the equipment necessary for
implementing policies. A security policy actor cannot function properly without
civilian and military capabilities. The EU has relatively limited resources in this
area, but its members have pledged to make a certain number of civilians and
military capabilities available through various ‘Headline Goals’ (Lindström,
2007). At the summit in Laeken in December 2001, the member states declared
that the EU was now able to conduct some crisis management operations. Since
then, it has further developed and improved its abilities in international crisis
management.
On the military side, the focus has been on developing smaller battle groups
that can be inserted in a crisis area at short notice. A Defence Agency was established in 2004 to support the member states and the Council in their efforts to
strengthen EU military crisis-�management capabilities and to develop industrial
policy. However, some shortcomings remain. The lack of common European
military headquarters, evacuation forces, joint training and interoperability is
considered to be the main challenge in this area (Howorth 2007). On the other
hand, the EU has been very effective in drawing on and utilizing member-�state
military facilities to achieve common European goals (Ulriksen 2007). The
establishment of emergency response forces or ‘battle groups’ has also strengthened the ability to act quickly when needed.
On the civilian side, member states have met the objectives, but some uncertainty remains as to how accessible these capabilities actually are. Many of the
same capabilities are also committed to other multilateral institutions and might
therefore be in use by the UN or the OSCE when the EU needs them (Jakobsen
2006).
The fact that the EU has been able to carry out 17 civilian and civil-�military
operations and seven military crisis management operations since 2003,
however, indicates that it does have a certain amount of resources available.
3╇ A continuous learning process
A third type of administrative capability necessary for an actor is security policy
expertise, experience and knowledge. As individuals acquire knowledge and
158╇╇ P. Rieker
skills through education and training, institutions represent enshrined knowledge
in traditions and rules. Skills and knowledge will therefore depend on a combination of good recruitment policies, good leadership, good training programmes
and the appropriate use of advice emanating from the expertise of reputable
research institutes and think-�tanks. For the EU, security policy competence will
hinge on a combination of the institution’s ability to draw on the expertise of its
member states and its ability to develop specific programmes for training and
learning.
It has been argued that the EU is a young and inexperienced security political
actor (Hoffman 2000; Kagan 2003) or a small power (Toje 2011). Such criticisms fail to account for the fact that the member states all come with extensive
experience – from their individual security policies, as well as through participation in other multilateral structures such as NATO and the UN. In turn, this
expertise will be channelled into the EU through national participation in various
expert groups (the Commission) and working groups or committees (the
Council). However, we should also note that the Commission has significantly
reduced its use of expert groups in this area since 2000 (Gornitska and Sverdrup
2011). The Council, on the other hand, draws heavily on national expertise. The
Political and Security Committee (PSC, represented by the member-�state ambassadors), which gets advice from the Military Committee (MC, represented by the
member countries’ designated heads or their representatives) and the the Committee for Civilian Aspects of Crisis Management (CIVCOM, represented by
various national experts), has been particularly influential. Additionally, many
workshops are held, with national experts in various fields.
The EU has proven surprisingly adaptable to the new security policy context
– perhaps even more so than many of its individual member-Â�countries. Perhaps
because the EC/EU had no clearly defined security policy until after the Cold
War, it was easier to adapt to a new era. Unlike well-�established security policy
actors, the EU did not have to go through long and difficult restructuring pro�
cesses: it could start to develop a security policy from scratch. Since then, the
EU has taken a range of initiatives to increase its expertise in this field. For one
thing, both the Commission and the Council have made use of expertise from
various research institutes and think-Â�tanks. The EU’s own Institute for Security
Studies (EUISS) in Paris is frequently used, as is the European Policy Centre in
Brussels. The EU has also established a separate college, the European Security
and Defence College (founded in 2005), which offers training of civilian and
military personnel. Training programmes for civilian–military coordination are
implemented by both the Commission and Council in addition to a range of
civilian and military crisis management exercises. This is an ongoing process.
The EU has built up a certain degree of expertise in this field, both by virtue of
the experience held by its member states, and by developing its own learning
programmes.
The EU foreign and security policy╇╇ 159
4╇ Lack of organizational skills
Organizational skills are the last but perhaps most important capability essential
to an actor’s ability to take collective action. While such skills also depend on
the presence of other capabilities (regulations, resources and expertise), all these
must be applied effectively. As March and Olsen argue, ‘Without organizational
talents, experience, and understanding, the other capabilities are likely to be lost
in problems of coordination and control [.â•›.â•›.]’ (1995: 95). There are many institutions at several levels that have a role to play in EU’s security policy. In fact,
the Commission, the Council, various independent agencies and member states
all contribute to the development and implementation of the CFSP. Although
there are regulations for how they are to operate together, these are often so
general that uncertainties remain as to the distribution of responsibilities. Such
coordination problems can be observed within the Commission, within the
Council as well as between the Commission and the Council.
Coordination problems within the Commission relate first and foremost to the
fact that there are several DGs and underlying bodies responsible for the external
relations and security policy of the EU. Due to internal communication problems, the Commission does not always manage to act in a unified way. In some
cases this has even led to contradictory policies towards third countries (Duke
2006: 10). However, various reform measures have been implemented to remedy
these problems. With the Amsterdam Treaty, for instance, the Commission’s
various bodies responsible for external relations were simplified and a separate
ministry for external relations (DG Relex) was created, tasked with ensuring
�coordination and cooperation. The creation of a programme for conflict prevention in 2001 and the increase in flexible funding arrangements, such as the Rapid
Reaction Mechanism (2001) and the Stability Instrument (2007), have also
aimed at streamlining the Commission\s activities.
By contrast, coordination problems within the Council are of a different character, with political as well as institutional dimensions. While the political
dimension concerns the traditional coordination problems between member
states within a policy area where most formal decisions are taken by unanimity,
the institutional dimension is about coordination problems between civilian and
military personnel. While the problems in the political dimension have no solution in the short term and will from time to time continue to put certain restrictions on the EU’s ability to act, those in the institutional dimension have led to
the creation of structures designed to strengthen civil‒military cooperation. The
establishment of a civilian–military unit within the military staff in 2005 must be
understood as an attempt to do precisely that (Knutsen 2008).
As we have seen, measures have been undertaken in order to do something
about the coordination problems within the Commission and the Council.
Despite the measures set out in the Lisbon Treaty, there remain some important
coordination problems between these two institutions (Topala 2010). This is due
mainly to different bureaucratic cultures and an unclear division of labour –
especially as regards civilian crisis management.
160╇╇ P. Rieker
Recently, efforts have been made to promote such inter-�institutional coordination. In addition to the Lisbon Treaty, the new financial framework for the
period 2007–2013 opens the way for a more flexible funding system for international civilian crisis management that may facilitate better coordination in this
policy area.
Concluding remarks
We have seen that the European Union is both a security policy instrument and a
security policy actor – or rather, the European integration process is a security
policy instrument and the EU is a security actor. While the integration process itself
is an instrument of security policy and peace-�building, the creation of a common
foreign, security and defence policy, in addition to the Commission’s activities in
civilian crisis management and conflict prevention around the world have demonstrated that the EU has also become an important security political actor.
Since the EU is neither an international organization nor a state, alternative
analytical tools are needed in order to understand what kind of actor the EU is
and how it works. This chapter has shown how a combination of a security community perspective and a multi-�level governance perspective may prove fruitful.
With this combination, the value of the integration process as the security policy
instrument is emphasized, while the EU is presented an actor without over- or
under-�emphasizing on the EU level as such.
We have also seen how a study of the EU’s ability to formulate goals and
make decisions together with a study of its administrative capabilities can contribute to a better understanding of the EU’s actor properties. While it has formulated clear objectives for its security policy in the European Security Strategy
of 2003, the EU has not always succeeded in taking the decisions necessary to
follow up these goals. In this sense there has been created a certain gap between
expectations and capabilities, as described by Christopher Hill (1993). On the
other hand, the various crises in EU history related to the inability to make
�decisions have led to a continuation of the integration process in this area. The
question is now what consequences the current financial crisis will have for the
further development of the CFSP.
With regard to administrative capabilities, study of the EU regulations,
resources, expertise and organizational capabilities shows that the EU is gradually, although sometimes slowly, becoming a more potent security policy actor.
Despite some remaining deficiencies in these areas, the biggest challenge is
perhaps still related to the lack of coordination, control and management in the
EU. This is a significant point since, according to March and Olsen (1995), precisely these are the most important of the necessary capabilities. While it is the
lack of decision-Â�making ability that most often places limitations on the EU’s
ability to perform as a security policy actor, coordination problems between the
institutions (or levels) often restrict what it can achieve even when a decision
has been reached. And perhaps this is the main reason why the EU’s potential as
a security political actor has yet not been fully exploited.
The EU foreign and security policy╇╇ 161
Notes
1 I have enjoyed the support and guidance of Professor Walter Carlsnaes – first as my
supervisor, then as a colleague at the Norwegian Institute of International Affairs. His
experience, academic skills and extensive connections have been crucial to my work,
and I am extremely grateful for having the opportunity of working so closely with him.
2 www.consilium.europa.eu/showPage.aspx?id=268&lang=en.
3 An earlier version of this work was published in 2009 in the Journal of European Integration, 31(6), 703–720).
4 The External Action Service was officially launched in December 2010, but will not be
fully operational before 2012.
5 http://ec.europa.eu/budget/library/publications/budget_in_fig/dep_eu_budg_2008_
en.pdf.
6 http://eur-�lex.europa.eu/budget/www/index-�en.htm.
7 www.consilium.europa.eu/uedocs/cmsUpload/ATHENA_june-�2007.pdf.
References
Adler, Emanuel and Barnett, Michael (eds) (1998) Security Communities. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Bretherton, Charlotte and Vogler, John (2006). The European Union as a Global Actor.
London: Routledge.
Bull, Hedley (1983). Civilian power Europe: A contradiction in terms? In Loukas Tsoukalis (ed.), The European Community: Past, present and future. London: Blackwell.
Buzan, Barry (1991). People, states and fear: A security agenda for the post-�Cold War
era, 2nd ed. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.
Buzan, Barry and Wæver, Ole (2004). Regions and powers: The structure of national
security. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Buzan, Barry, Wæver, Ole and de Wilde, Jaap (1998). Security: A new framework for
analysis. London: Lynne Rienner.
Carlsnaes, Walter, Sjursen, Helene and White, Brian (2004). Contemporary European
foreign policy. London: Sage.
Deutsch, Karl W. (1957). Political community and the North Atlantic Area: International
organization in the light of historical experience. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Duke, Simon (2006). The Commission and the CFSP. EIPA Working Paper. Maastricht:
EIPA.
Epstein, Rachel A. and Sedelmeier, Ulrich (2008). Beyond conditionality: International
institutions in postcommunist Europe after enlargement. Journal of European Public
Policy, 15(6), 795–805.
European Council (2003). A secure Europe in a better world: European security strategy.
Brussels, 12 December.
Gornitzka, Åse and Sverdrup, Ulf (2011). Access of experts: Information and EU
decision-Â�making. West European Politics, 34(1), 48–70.
Hill, Christopher (1993). The capability–expectation gap, or conceptualizing Europe’s
international role. Journal of Common Market Studies, 31(3), 305–328.
Hill, Christopher (2007). The future of the European Union as a global actor. InPaolo
Foradori, Paolo Rosa and Riccardo Scartezzini (eds), Managing a multilevel foreign
policy: The EU in international affairs. Lanham, MD: Lexington.
Hoffmann, Stanley (2000). Towards a common foreign and security policy? Journal of
International Affairs, 38(2), 189–199.
162╇╇ P. Rieker
Hyde-Â�Price, Adrian (2006). Normative power Europe: A realist critique. Journal of European Public Policy, 13(2), 217–234.
Hyde-Â�Price, Adrian (2008). A ‘tragic actor’? A realist perspective on ‘ethical power’
Europe. International Affairs, 84(1), 49–64.
Jakobsen, Peter Viggo (2006). Nordic approaches to peace operations: A new model in
the making? London and New York: Routledge.
Kagan, Robert (2003). Of paradise and power. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Knutsen, Olav (2008). Class voting in Western Europe: A comparative longitudinal study.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Lindström, Gustav (2007). The headline goal. Paris: EU Institute for Security Studies.
Manners, Ian (2002). Normative power Europe: A contradiction in terms? Journal of
Common Market Studies, 40(2), 235–258.
Manners, Ian (2006). Normative power Europe reconsidered: Beyond the crossroads.
Journal of European Public Policy, 13(2), 182–199.
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P. (1995). Democratic governance. New York: Free
Press.
Marks, Gary and Hooghe, Liesbeth (2001). Multi-�level governance and European integration. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield.
McCormick, John (2006). The European superpower. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Moravcsik, Andrew (2010). Europe, the second super power. Current History, March,
91–98.
Rieker, Pernille (2006). Europeanization of national security identity: The EU and the
changing security identities of the Nordic states. London: Routledge.
Rieker, Pernille (2009). The EU – a capable security actor? Developing administrative
capabilities. Journal of European Integration, 31(6), 703–719.
Rieker, Pernille (2012). Integration, security and the European neighborhood: The importance of the ENP as a security policy instrument. Studia Diplomatica, 1, 69–77.
Rosamond, Ben (2000). Theories of European integration. London: Macmillan.
Sæter, Martin (2003). EU-Â�prosessen omformer europeisk sikkerhet. In P. Rieker and S.
Ulriksen (eds), En annerledes supermakt? Sikkerhets- og forsvarspolitikken i EU. Oslo:
Nupi.
Sjöstedt, Gunnar (1977). The external role of the European Community. London: Saxon
House.
Sjursen, Helene (2006). The EU as a ‘normative’ power: how can this be? Journal of
European Public Policy, 13(2), 235–251.
Toje, Asle (2011). The European Union as a small power. Journal of Common Market
Studies, 49(1): 43–60.
Topala, Oana (2010). Communicate, coordinate and cooperate: The A–Z of cohering
crisis management in the post-Â�Lisbon era. European Security Review, 51, 2–4.
Ulriksen, Ståle (2007). European military forces: Integration by default. In J.H. Matlary
and Ø. Østerud (eds), Denationalised defence: Convergence and diversity. Aldershot:
Ashgate.
13 Ideas in foreign policy decision
making
The invasion of Iraq
Fredrik Bynander
Introduction
Do ideas matter to foreign policy? The answer to this question – not really – was
for many decades considered a foregone conclusion in western scholarly debates.
However, with the advent of postmodernist and social constructivist approaches
to the subject, the debate was provided with fresh fuel in the early 1990s. Not
only do ideas matter, but equally the manner in which they originate, diffuse and
are perceived. The reaction from the mainstream rationalist camp was that either
the whole notion was dismissed as lacking in scientific rigour and methodological potential, or it was co-�opted into the prevailing narrative of the rational
actor as a calculation of the existing ideological ‘moods’ that could affect the
success of a foreign policy framework pursued by any given government. The
most vivid installment into the second portrayal of ideas was an edited volume
by Robert Keohane and Judith Goldstein, Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs,
Institutions and Political Change (1993). Walter Carlsnaes offered this book as
required reading in his Master’s course for several years, and used it to problematize ideational causation and expand the notion that ideas do matter to foreign
policy. The gist of the book’s argument, elaborated in Goldstein and Keohane’s
succinct introductory chapter is that ideas have causal pathways to influence
(that are largely compatible with formal models of rational choice) and that arguably satisfies the call for ideational causation.
The Goldstein and Keohane suggestion of a space for ideas in actor’s choices
is part and parcel of the ‘thickening’ of rational choice theory, and the incorporation of new explanans into the rational actor model of analysing politics. The
problem with these thick-Â�rational accounts is that they ‘contain no theory determining the selection of agent identities, values, beliefs, and strategic opportunities’ (Ferejohn 1991: 282). More than that, in combining analytical entities that
are both the traditional ingredients to rational choice modeling, and others that
have been allowed to shape the theoretical and conceptual tools of distinct
approaches, thick-�rational accounts of political action risk putting the cart before
the horse. Ian Shapiro has put it concisely: ‘That is why we press the question,
What seems most likely to account for X? as superior to: How can a rational
choice model be developed that can account for X?’ (Shapiro 2005: 89).
164╇╇ F. Bynander
This chapter will suggest a number of ways that ideas, in these cases deeply
held ideological convictions, can influence foreign policy decisions in spite of
serious objections based on legal, political, strategic and popular grounds. It will
not provide conclusive evidence of the ‘causal pathways’ that these ideas
traveled into policy, nor will it falsify alternative explanations to the specific
policy outcomes, but it will make credible and reflect upon ideas as political currency, and ideological compatibility as conducive to salience, on a given government’s agenda. The theoretical tools used will be retrieved from the broader field
of political psychology, and will devise credible strategies for individuals coping
with the cross pressure of ‘evidence’ and political expedience.
The cases selected for this discussion, the US and UK use of intelligence information in their respective decision to initiate military action against Iraq are,
considering what is generally known about the decision-�making processes a most
likely case. Most likely, that is, to reveal poorly disguised attempts by the political leadership to influence ostensibly rule-�based processes of intelligence gathering, evaluation, and analysis. On the other hand, the two national systems
under scrutiny have admittedly strong traditions of accountability and public disclosure, which attaches a measure of real risk to tampering with ‘due process’
and the independence of professional intelligence organizations. Numerous scandals over the years, in both national governments, have demonstrated both the
risks involved and the conflicting proclivity to manipulate and use political
power in illegal or illegitimate ways in order to produce support for controversial policies.
The decision to intervene in Iraq 2003
When the bombing campaign in Iraq was initiated on 20 March 2003, the timing
was based on last second intelligence from the CIA that Saddam Hussein and his
sons were gathered at a southern Baghdad compound, Doura Farms, which was
targeted with cruise missiles and bunker busting bombs. The intelligence proved
to be unreliable. It was the latest installment a series of intelligence mistakes, the
most infamous of these being reports on Iraqi Weapons of Mass Destruction
(WMDs) that had been served to the White House in the President’s Daily Briefs
and the Senior Executive Intelligence Briefs (US Senate 2004). As Secretary of
State Colin Powell prepared for his speech to the U.N. Security Council on the
eve of war in February that year, he spent time face to face with Director of
Central Intelligence (DCI) George Tenet going over the best possible estimate of
Iraqi capabilities, questioning the CIA’s reports and their sources. ‘Tenet looked
him in the eye and told him it was rock solid’ (Weiner 2007: 568). In light of
this, can the failure of providing a casus belli for the invasion of Iraq thus be
squarely placed with the CIA, or is it more complicated than that?
Was it, rather, the extreme and well-�documented pressure applied by the principals of the Bush team rather that threw the intelligence system out of orbit and
produced the fiction and fables that the administration wanted to hear? I will try
to shed light on these questions by exploring value complexity as a dilemma
Ideas in foreign policy decision making╇╇ 165
when faced with a more or less acute security context, and relate the resulting
dynamic to the intra-�governmental pressures as they may be applied and/or
anticipated.
The link between these decision processes and the failure to produce a legitimate policy is constituted by ignorance of long-�term consequences that usually
would conflict with decision-Â�makers’ own ethical standards. The concern with a
greater good forces a number of lesser evils into the policy process that undermine the possibility of an outcome that abide by established ethical norms, to the
damage of the primary actors as well as their institutional surroundings.
In order to draw reasonable conclusions about the administration of classified
intelligence and discreet advice, we need to recognize both the limited (some
would say inconclusive) empirical basis for such studies, and the often self-�
serving account decision-�makers and advisors provide of actual deliberations
and decisions.
The cases
This chapter will examine and discuss early empirical accounts of the decisions
by the Bush administration and the Blair government to invade Iraq in 2003.
Obviously, the historical record is far from complete regarding the decision-�
making and intelligence processes that preceded the invasion, and facts that
could potentially affect the validity of our findings could surface as more classified material is made public. Nevertheless, the actions of these two governments
have been more publicly scrutinized in closer proximity to the events in question
than perhaps any other event of global political importance. Furthermore, the
value complexity that drives the processes hypothesized here, and that manifested themselves over the course of the decision-�making process, are to a large
degree in the public domain (such as the evidence presented by Secretary of
State Colin Powell in the UN Security Council in February 2003).
The US
The primary, and extremely public, failure of both the studied governments to
legitimize their cause for war was their ultimately discredited claim that Saddam
Hussein had the capacity to unleash weapons of mass destruction in 45 minutes.
The more substantial argument presented to the United Nations’ Security
Council was that Iraq was in material breach of UNSC resolution 1441, in its
refusal to cooperate with the UN weapons inspectors and provide evidence of
the destruction of its known possession of WMDs. However, the pièce de résistance was the repeated claim that Saddam indeed possessed and planned to
deploy these weapons. In attempting to trace the intelligence process that provided cover for the claim, we need to consider the end of the first Gulf war, and
the weapons inspection regime that was put in place under the auspices of the
UN. The evasive tactics of the Iraqi military and political establishments rapidly
eroded any remaining shred of credibility that the regime might have had with
166╇╇ F. Bynander
the inspectors (or with the CIA, which was deeply involved in the search for elements of a weapons programme). Faced with a culture of lies, the prevailing
wisdom in the West was that whatever Saddam could get away with, he would
(Kay 2004; Blair 2010: 413).
The CIA was, throughout the end of the Cold War and with the depletion of
resources that followed it, short on human intelligence, eyes and ears on the
ground, in current and likely future hotspots of US foreign policy (Berkowitz
2003). This became painfully obvious as Al Qaeda raced up the security agenda
and it turned out that their capabilities were largely unknown to the western
intelligence community (Woodward 2006: 49–52, 90). The CIA tried to make up
for their poor intelligence capacity by offering large sums of money to defectors
and regional experts with knowledge of the Iraqi military system. The result was
a flow of low quality intelligence that could not be verified or validated through
other means (Kay 2004).
The relationship between the Bush administration and the intelligence community was, despite their common interest in finding the goods on Saddam
Hussein, a tense one. The most visible sign of the distrust that existed between
the levels of government was the politically motivated exposure of a covert CIA
operative named Valerie Plame. Plame’s husband, former Ambassador Joseph
Wilson IV, had been sent by the CIA to investigate the rumor that Iraq tried to
acquire yellow cake from Niger. He had quickly decided that the rumor was
false, and when the allegation started to show up in government arguments for a
war with Iraq, Wilson published an op-Â�ed in the New York Times, entitled ‘What
I didn’t find in Africa’. Plame’s identity was revealed, allegedly as an act of
Â�retribution against Wilson, by Vice President Cheney’s chief of staff Lewis
‘Scooter’ Libby. Libby was convicted in federal court for his role in outing
Plame (US v. Libby 2005). Other senior figures of the Bush team were also
implicated: Senior Adviser to the President Karl Rove, Deputy Secretary of State
Richard Armitage, and the vice president himself. The affair exacerbated the
conflict between the intelligence community and the administration.
That conflict had simmered ever since Donald Rumsfeld and Dick Cheney
returned to posts in the federal government with the election of George W. Bush.
They were both critics of the US intelligence community in general and of the
CIA in particular. Rumsfeld had, during his first stint as Secretary of Defense
1975–1976, a poisonous fight with the CIA over budgets and had stated that the
CIA was spying on him. Ironically, the director of central intelligence at that
time was George H.W. Bush (Garthoff 2005: 113–116). The distrust from
�important principals was well known in the intelligence community and there
was a sense of desperation in the CIA as the mission became more complex, and
publically demanding, but the intelligence resources had already been eroded
(Woodward 2008: 137).
If the administration had realized that the intelligence on Iraqi WMD was
phony, they would not have stressed this aspect of their causes for war as
strongly. They would likely have prepared for a post-�invasion debate and argued
the poor human rights record of Saddam Hussein more strongly, for example. In
Ideas in foreign policy decision making╇╇ 167
a way, the leadership had duped themselves into believing information that was
the product of doctored intelligence from suspicious sources. This manipulation,
in turn, was a product of their own single-�mindedness in dealing with the Iraq
problem and the way they directed federal agencies to implement their view of
that problem.
The US modus
The active communication of flawed intelligence came from several government
units and was originally a product of poor sources on Iraq combined with rapidly
growing political pressure after 9/11. The reliance on defectors in search of
asylum, protection, and cash, was never a solid basis for estimating the capabilities of Saddam’s regime. Furthermore, the political urge to build a case for
action crowded out concerns over the legitimacy of a war in the longer run. The
intelligence community became increasingly aware that the Iraq policy was in
relentless motion, and the constant worry of the intelligence leadership was of
not being onboard, of not being useful to the administration when it was summoned. The results were errors of judgement in at least three stages of the intelligence cycle: the intelligence-�gathering was sloppy and did not meet
professional requirements, the communication of the resulting analysis was over�confident and lopsided, and the reaction of the principals was not one of sound
skepticism but of impatient calls for tougher conclusions, the return of lost
nuggets from previous briefings, and erring on the side of recklessness (US
Senate 2004; Weiner 2007).
The US administration over-�emphasized internal values domestically and
internationally (how to sell the war, rather than establish a cause for war that
would hold up across time). It clearly selected information that confirmed and
premiered pre-�existing beliefs over anomalies and the multiple sources that
argued that the Baghdad regime was in general compliance with international
treaties. The US administration was overconfident that the intelligence community had reliable information; and leading administration officials have
repeatedly and honestly testified that the war on terror gave Iraqi WMD a new
sense of urgency and made a qualitative difference in the decision-�making
process (Halverscheid and Witte 2008).
The pre-�existing belief that Saddam was toying with the international community, that he was still pursuing WMD capabilities, carefully concealed those
efforts, and was willing to deploy them against his enemies, was so strong that it
tended to marginalize evidence to the contrary. Opponents of forceful action
against Iraq would concede as much in the long debates that preceded the war, and
the issue of the smoking gun would become increasingly academic to the proponents of such action. Even the cautious head of the United Nations Special Commission (UNSCOM) at the time, Hans Blix, talked about the Iraqi behaviour in
this way, although arguing that there was no detection of the proverbial smoking
gun (Blix 2004: 151). Cheney, Rice and others in the Bush administration would
answer that the ‘smoking gun might be a mushroom cloud’ (Blitzer 2003).
168╇╇ F. Bynander
In addition, there was a strong conviction in the top circles of the Bush
administration that being successful is being right, and that as long as regime
change would be swift, comprehensive and stabilizing to the region, the international and domestic criticism would be mild.
The UK
In Britain, the Iraq policy was strongly linked to that of the US, and the intelligence process followed a similar trajectory. The intelligence cooperation
between the two states is far-�reaching, and British intelligence agencies have
become growingly dependent on the larger resources and longer reach of their
American colleagues. Nevertheless, British intelligence has some comparative
advantages in their remaining ties with their former colonies and other (commercial) spheres of interest around the globe that US organizations sometimes have
a hard time penetrating. If the Valerie Plame controversy was a defining incident
for the relationship between the intelligence community and the political leadership in the US, the leaked identity and suicide of WMD expert Dr David Kelly
in July of 2003, was the British equivalent.
The Kelly affair cut right to the heart of the Blair government’s handling of
dissenting voices in the civil service and in the media regarding the war. The
controversy started with BBC radio reporter Andrew Gilligan claiming on
national radio that Downing Street had doctored intelligence reports to
strengthen the case for war against Iraq and that the government knew that the
45-minute claim was false when they stated it. Blair’s team immediately went on
the offensive and took action against the BBC, forcing a showdown that shook
the public service broadcaster to its foundations. The Ministry of Defence (MoD)
released a statement on the unauthorized sharing of information to Gilligan that
was phrased in a way that made it possible to guess Kelly’s identity. When confronted with Kelly’s name, the MoD confirmed it, and Dr Kelly was thrown into
the public eye. In June he appeared before two parliamentary committees, one of
them public and televised. Kelly was interrogated quite harshly and his employer
informed him that he might be subjected to legal action. On the afternoon of 17
July, Kelly left his home to take a walk, during which he committed suicide
(Hutton 2004).
Kelly’s suicide brought to light the aggressive communication tactics of
Blair’s Downing Street operations. In order to contain public outrage, Lord
Hutton was appointed to lead a judicial inquiry into the death of government
employee Kelly and the events that had preceded it. When Lord Hutton released
his report in 2004, he basically exonerated the government from driving Dr
Kelly to suicide, but in the testimonies that had been delivered, several troubling
issues had surfaced. For the prime minister himself it was damaging that his
former Permanent Secretary, Sir Kevin Tebitt, had pointed to Blair as chairing
the meeting that was instrumental in the strategy of naming Dr Kelly (Hutton
2003b). Blair had denied this in the media, but was let off conspicuously easily
when he appeared before the Hutton inquiry (Hutton 2003a). The immediate
Ideas in foreign policy decision making╇╇ 169
victim of this controversy was Alastair Campbell, Blair’s belligerent communications director who had been such a central figure in the conflict with the BBC,
and in the preparation of evidence of an Iraqi breach of UN resolution 1441.
The 45-minute claim had been the account of a single source. According to
the chairman of the Joint Information Committee, John Scarlett: ‘This was a
report from a single source. It was an established and reliable line of reporting;
and it was quoting a senior Iraqi military officer in a position to know this
Â�information’ (Hutton 2003c). According to senior intelligence officials, this disputed fragment had remained in the intelligence flow because of its significance
for potential military action against Iraq. If such action was to take place, the
deployment time for WMDs was of the utmost importance and any piece of
intelligence that could shed light on strategies for conflict initiation was of some
value. In fact, there seems to have been a slow merger going on between a classified assessment of Iraq’s WMD capacities and the infamous public dossier that
was being prepared for the prime minister to state his case against Iraq. The classified text talked about deployment times for biological weapons by Iraq’s army
in terms of 20–45 minutes (ibid.). These assessments were based on scenarios
with input variables that were speculative at best for the purpose of preparing the
British military for an invasion.
The JIC team that was in charge of preparing the intelligence matter of the
dossier was called to Alastair Campbell’s office at 10 Downing Street on
several occasions to discuss presentation. The dossier for the use of the prime
minister was to have a foreword that used a looser and more suggestive language than the intelligence-�based text body. The body of the report, however,
recounted testimonies by individual Iraqi citizens in order to strengthen the
argument that Saddam Hussein was a cruel dictator who needed to be deposed.
The communications staff had, through this arrangement, a reason to get
involved in the drafting process, and to give advice. In an odd passage of
Alastair Campbell’s published diary, Manchester United Manager Alex Ferguson said Campbell was: ‘really worried about Iraq, said he thought it was a very
dangerous situation for [Blair]. I said that TB had a real sense of certainty about
this one’ (Campbell 2007: 639). The influence by the prime minister’s staff on
the process of crafting the dossier increased exponentially as the moment of
presentation drew closer.
Blair’s own position was set with the decision to join forces with the US. His
foreign policy adviser, Sir Stephen Wall recalls: ‘He didn’t ask a lot of crucial
questions about the extent of Saddam’s nuclear capacity, for example. Partly
because he didn’t want to ask the questions’ (Rawnsley 2010: 115). But the real
problem at the Cabinet level was the lack of high-�level quality control. The MoD
and the Foreign Office were excluded from the work on the dossier, and Defence
Secretary Geoff Hoon first laid eyes on the full document hours before its presentation. The other Cabinet members were sent to see Head of MI6 Dearlove
and JIC Chairman Scarlett one by one, and were presented with evidence that
‘there was nothing speculative about’ according to Culture Secretary Tessa
Jowell (quoted in Rawnsley 2010: 115).
170╇╇ F. Bynander
In Blair’s own account of his thought process leading to the conclusion that
an invasion was called for, there is a strong emphasis on Saddam’s track record
of defying sanctions and engaging in human rights abuse. This underscores the
idea that the possession of WMDs was not the primary reason for the decision
on either side of the Atlantic (Blair 2010: 383–387). At the political level, for
which the integrity and credibility of the intelligence community was not the
overriding concern, the behaviour and the duplicity of the Iraqi regime was evidence enough of the ambition to retain and develop WMD capabilities. However,
there is strong evidence to suggest that the idea that Saddam possessed WMDs
was intimately linked to the image of Saddam Hussein as a highly motivated and
politically reckless leader. There was nothing in the behaviour of the Iraqi
regime that suggested he had forfeited the WMD option after the Gulf war, and
his consistent uncooperative behaviour towards the UN weapons inspectors was
considered further proof that this was an option he was still pursuing. As mentioned earlier, the US administration embedded the smoking gun debate in the
Saddam Hussein as reckless villain narrative, and many accounts reflecting a
similar attitude can be found among the UK leadership.
Finally, we need to address the fact that the two cases in this study are closely
linked, and that they in a sense contaminate or spill over to one another. When
studying the meetings between the leaders and their senior advisers, it is clear
that there is a mutually reinforcing air of moral certainty, not only about the
correct strategy to deal with Iraq, but also about the existence of Iraqi WMDs.
According to a declassified diplomatic telegram that was sent from the British
embassy to the Foreign Office, the following was said between Bush and Blair
in their 5–7 April meeting in Crawford, Texas: ‘They agreed that Iraq’s WMD
programs were a major threat to the international community, particularly when
coupled with Saddam’s proven track record on using these weapons. Letting that
program continue unhindered was not an option’ (Iraq Inquiry 2002).
The bolstering of one another’s attitudes on Iraq and WMDs was an ongoing
process between Bush and Blair, causing British senior advisers great worry.
Foreign Secretary Jack Straw wrote Blair a letter days before Blair left for the
Crawford meeting with Bush: ‘[t]he rewards from your visit to Crawford will be
few’; he urged Blair ‘to beware of elephant traps’, stating that ‘regime change
per se is no justification for military action’ (Straw quoted in Rawnsley 2010:
93). US officials, too, pressured Blair to hold back the seemingly relentless
movement towards war that had originated in Washington. Colin Powell had
long conversations with Jack Straw to devise a strategy to get their leaders to
tone down their war rhetoric, and appealed personally to Blair to be firm with
Bush, especially concerning a second UNSC resolution in 2002.
Blair would express his concerns, but he would never lie down on the railroad tracks. Jack and I would get him all pumped up about an issue. And
he’d be ready to say ‘Look here, George.’ But as soon as he saw the President he would lose all his steam.
(Powell, quoted in Rawnsley 2010: 104; see Schaefer and Walker 2006)
Ideas in foreign policy decision making╇╇ 171
The two cases are thus intimately intertwined and the initiation of the Iraq war,
and the intelligence failure that preceded it, constitutes a unique case of personal
interactions between national leaders, not only on strategy, but also on the world
views that informed their respective foreign policies.
One overriding theme of these encounters was the nature of the war on terror
and that they both saw themselves as the leaders of this war. Blair, who prided
himself on having understood and successfully mitigated the complex and sectarian conflict in Northern Ireland, assumed a natural authority on the subject
(Seldon 2007: 535–541). But when it came to global terrorism, represented by
Al Qaeda, he saw the problem as having deeper roots and requiring violent
action in a way that had not been the cure for Northern Ireland. ‘Back in the
instant following the cataclysmic act of terrorism that stunned, shocked and
appalled the world, the issue was clear: the madmen had declared war. They
would be rooted out and eliminated’ (Blair 2010: 349). The connection between
9/11 and Iraq was made in similar terms:
[t]he issue of Saddam and his ten-�year obstruction of weapons inspection
was not upfront, but from then on, it was there in the background. There
was no decision at that point as to how to deal with him; nevertheless, that
he had to be confronted, brought into line or removed was, on any deeper
analysis, fairly obvious.
(ibid.: 357)
The world views of the two leaders were highly compatible, and the main difference seems to have been the means by which to further the end of regime change
in Iraq: unilateral action or multilateral? Blair’s appeals for Bush to be more
patient with the UN Security Council process ultimately fell on deaf ears, and
Bush entered the Iraq war a believer in regime change as the one remaining
option. The only way forward in justifying this course of action was to argue
material breach of UNSC 1441, and Blair, more than Bush, needed the intelligence to prove it.
The UK modus
The British case is different from the American, in the sense that the UK intelligence apparatus never over-�estimated their own intelligence capacity regarding
Iraq nor, for any longer time spans, that of the US or other services. The JIC
process that produced the public Iraq dossier failed primarily because of political
pressure. Blair’s own involvement was not motivated by a will to consciously
distort intelligence, but his strong conviction on the facts and the way forward
made his close advisers realize that in order to keep up with his thinking, and to
protect him from future political fallout, they needed to influence the process in
terms of presentation to the general public. This is the reaction of party officials
in an environment that is threatening to be politically disastrous and to wipe out
political support for their boss.
172╇╇ F. Bynander
The result of this strong emphasis on presentation was the deterioration of
responsibility and quality control, and ultimately a break-�down in political-�
administrative relations, as political appointees ended up influencing what was
generally perceived as intelligence material. The long debates about the doctoring of intelligence and the integrity of the JIC cannot significantly alter this
general finding. One reason for the ethical failure was the erased boundaries
between the public dossier and the material prepared for operational planning.
This suggests a strong top-�down pressure to conform to the official line and
deselect anything that would contradict it. There is little to suggest that this was
part of a declared strategy, but rather that the interpretation of the preferred
process hardened as it descended from the prime minister down the ranks of the
British government.
Conclusions
The two cases of this study are different in a number of core aspects. The UK
security apparatus was subject to a much more temporary break-�down as the
combined impact of political pressures caused a short circuiting of its quality
control mechanisms and its separations of products aimed at evidence collection
and those aimed at tactical intelligence. The US system on the contrary was suffering from a longstanding lack of trust between representatives of major institutions for foreign policy making. It is a fact that the outcome of these two national
processes was similar, but we would need further evidence (over a longer time
period) to fully substantiate this claim.
The specific breakdown of the British system is one of political-�bureaucratic
relations, and it only occurred in a combination of extreme uncertainty, scarcity
of validated information, and great political momentum. This suggests a scenario
that is pre-�determined in the sense that there are too many converging policy
incentives for the system to absorb, thus forcing a disintegration of the analytical
process. In fact, British intelligence organizations had avoided several potential
‘traps’ by discrediting a number of sources early on, only to have them seep
back into the process as pressure mounted in 2003. The other greatly influential
factor in explaining the British outcome was the influence of the American intelligence services and the cooperation between the two states’ leaders. MI6 and
the JIC operated in an environment that slowly, but surely, converged around
cherry-�picking from the highly dubious stories of defected Iraqis. We should not
overstate their attempts to discredit this information, but a central vehicle for
doing so would have been political support. As Jack Straw lost Tony Blair’s ear
and was marginalized in the Cabinet, and Colin Powell seemed to drop his
objections and jump aboard his administration’s push for war, that avenue was
closed.
The US case seems much more deep-�seated and systemic in the origins of its
failure to legitimize its actions. The intelligence community was operating under
a credibility deficit with the administration that forced them to deviate from professional standards on a number of occasions and to report findings it knew to be
Ideas in foreign policy decision making╇╇ 173
false. The idea of actionable intelligence and the notion of the usefulness of the
intelligence agencies had acquired a political dimension that was impossible to
ignore. George Tenet’s personal position as a survivor from the Clinton administration, and the elevation of his office following 9/11, seemed to further reinforce
the need to capitalize on the proximity to power and turn it into political
legitimacy.
The in-�fighting in the Bush foreign policy team was detrimental to critical
debate. Powell was shut out of important processes regarding the Iraq policy and
war planning, and the mentality that produced the Valerie Plame incident illustrated a perception of the administration as being under siege by appeasers and
containment advocates. Bush wrote in his autobiography about his phone call to
Bush Sr. after reading the op-Â�ed article of his father’s former security adviser,
Brent Scowcroft, in the Wall Street Journal, entitled ‘Don’t attack Saddam’
(Scowcroft 2002): ‘â•› “Son, Brent is a friend,” he assured me. That might be true.
But I knew critics would later exploit Brent’s article if the diplomatic track
failed’ (Bush 2010: 297).
The ideological challenge that was the focus for both these governments was
one of standing up to a tyrant vs. international legal requirements of the causes
for war. The first dimension remained more important and would in the main
actors’ own minds legitimize the gentle fabrication of the second. Besides,
Â�‘everybody knew’ that Saddam had WMD programmes; only the weakness of
the inspection regime prevented evidence from being on the table. Also, both
governments considered the breach of UNSC resolution 1441 as the foundation
for the cause for war, and a second resolution based on findings of Baghdad’s
material breach of UNSC resolution 1441 was to shore up international support.
To this day, the main representatives of both governments argue that UNSC resolution 1441 was enough to justify an intervention (Bush 2010; Blair 2010). The
failure of the intelligence system in this view is secondary, and coupled with the
laurels of victory theory that success breeds legitimacy, presentation of evidence
was allowed to take precedence over actually proving the case.
The false WMD claim came to be a white lie rather than a blatant lie in these
deliberations, and the ethical deficiency in the formal causes for war was, in the
eyes of the US and UK governments, amply justified by the secondary legal
arguments regarding human rights abuses, previous aggression and poor compliance with existing resolutions. The weakness, however, of this position is
manifested when the long-�term effects materialize. It is hard for the former
leaders to justify their previous statements in the absence of WMD discoveries
and the ability to sustain a policy in line with the principles stated at the outset of
the campaign is greatly weakened. Both Bush and Blair in their autobiographies,
published two months apart in 2010, blame the intelligence services for overstating their case (Bush 2010; Blair 2010). As we have seen, that is a highly dubious
approach, and it would serve future governments much better to take a long hard
look at how the political level interacts with these agencies, and which pitfalls
and quagmires lurk when the relationship is compromised.
174╇╇ F. Bynander
References
Berkowitz, Bruce (2003). Failing to keep up with the information revolution: The DI and
‘IT’. Studies in Intelligence (unclassified version), 47(1).
Blair, Tony (2010). A journey. London: Hutchinson.
Blitzer, Wolf (2003). Search for the ‘smoking gun’. CNN. Retrieved from http://articles.
cnn.com/2003–01–10/us/wbr.smoking.gun_1_smoking-Â�gun-nuclear-Â�weaponshans-Â�blix?_s=PM:US.
Blix, Hans (2004). Disarming Iraq. New York: Pantheon Books.
Bush, George W. (2010). Decision points. New York: Crown Publishing.
Campbell, Alastair (2007). The Blair years. London: Hutchinson.
Ferejohn, Michael. T. (1991). The origins of Aristotelian science. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Garthoff, Douglas F. (2005). Directors of Central Intelligence as leaders of the U.S.
Â�intelligence community, 1946–2005. Washington, DC: CIA Center for the Study of
Intelligence.
Goldstein, Judith and Keohane, Robert, O. (1996) Ideas and foreign policy: Beliefs, institutions, and political change. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Halverscheid, Susanne and Witte, Erich H. (2008). Justification of war and terrorism: A
comparative case study analyzing ethical positions based on prescriptive attribution
theory. Social Psychology, 39(1), 26–36.
Lord Hutton (2004). Report of the inquiry into the circumstances surrounding the death
of Dr David Kelly C.M.G. London: House of Commons.
Hutton Inquiry (2003a). Testimony of Mr Anthony Charles Lynton Blair (Called).
Retrieved from www.hutton.softblade.com/transcripts.php?action=transcript&session=
22&witness=35#wit35.
Hutton Inquiry (2003b). Testimony of Sir Kevin Reginald Tebitt (Called). Retrieved from
www.hutton.softblade.com/transcripts.php?action=transcript&session=14&witness=16
#wit16.
Hutton Inquiry (2003c). Testimony of Mr John McLeod Scarlett (Called). Retrieved from
www.hutton.softblade.com/transcripts.php?action=transcript&session=18&witness=29
#wit29.
Iraq Inquiry (2002). 5–7 April 2002 – Diplomatic telegram about meeting between Prime
Minister Blair and President Bush. Unclassified. Retrieved from www.iraqinquiry.org.
uk/transcripts/declassified-�documents.aspx.
Kay, David (2004). Weapons of Mass Destruction: Lessons learned and unlearned. Miller
Center Report, 20(1), 3–52.
Rawnsley, Andrew (2010). The end of the party: The rise and fall of New Labour.
London: Viking.
Schaefer, Mark and Walker, Stephen (2006). Democratic leaders and the democratic
peace: The operational codes of Tony Blair and Bill Clinton. International Studies
Quarterly, 50(4), 561–583.
Scowcroft, Brent (2002). Don’t attack Saddam. Wall Street Journal, 15 August, p.€4.
Seldon, Anthony (2007). Blair unbound. London: Simon & Schuster.
Shapiro, Ian (2005). The flight from reality in the human sciences. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
UNSCOM (1995). Notes on a meeting between Hussein Kamal and UNSCOM and
IAEA. Amman, Jordan, 22 August. Retrieved from www.un.org/Depts/unmovic/new/
documents/hk.pdf.
Ideas in foreign policy decision making╇╇ 175
United States of America v. I. Lewis Libby (2005). Indictment. United States District
Court for the District of Columbia, 28 October 28.
US Senate (2004). Report on the U.S. intelligence community’s prewar intelligence
assessments on Iraq. Report. Washington, DC: Select Committee on Intelligence.
Weiner, Tim (2007). Legacy of ashes: The history of the CIA. New York: Anchor Books.
Woodward, Bob (2006). State of denial. London: Simon & Schuster.
Woodward, Bob (2008). The war within. London: Simon & Schuster.
14 Foreign policy analysis and the
governance turn
Thomas Risse
Throughout his academic career, Walter Carlsnaes has been among the strongest
promoters of comparative foreign policy analysis, not as a separate subdiscipline
of International Relations, but linked to international relations theories in general
(see, for example, Carlsnaes 1986, 2002, 2004, 2012; Carlsnaes and Smith 1994;
Carlsnaes et al. 2004). In particular, his contributions to the agency–structure
debate have been significant and very influential in the discipline (Carlsnaes
1992). This chapter introduces the governance perspective into the study of comparative foreign policy thereby engaging in a discussion with Walter Carlsnaes’
work. I argue that the governance turn in international relations, while not ignoring the state and state foreign policy, broadens the perspective of foreign policy
analysis by overcoming a state-�centric focus. Since governance encompasses
actor, process, and structure dimensions, it also takes the mutual constitutiveness
of agency and structure seriously and is fully compatible with it. This chapter
starts with a short description of the ‘governance turn’ in international relations
and then discusses the consequences for foreign policy analysis.
(Global) governance and the study of international relations
There is quite some confusion in the debate over global and/or transnational governance that needs to be clarified before one can discuss its repercussions for
democracy and legitimacy.1 ‘Global governance’ in particular is often used
simultaneously as an analytical concept and a normative prescription for how
global problems should be handled (on the latter see World Commission on
Environment and Development 1987). But even as an analytical concept, the
term ‘governance’ has become such a catchword in the social sciences that it
connotes a whole variety of things (Pierre and Peters 2000; Kooiman 1993). In
the broadest possible definition, ‘governance’ relates to any form of creating or
maintaining political order and providing common goods for a given political
community on whatever level (Williamson 1975). A more narrow view has been
promoted by international relations scholars, such as James N. Rosenau and
Ernst-Â�Otto Czempiel (Czempiel and Rosenau 1992). Accordingly, ‘governance
without government’ refers to political arrangements which rely primarily on
non-�hierarchical forms of steering (see the excellent reviews by Mayntz 1998,
Foreign policy analysis and the governance turn╇╇ 177
2002). In other words, governance beyond the nation-�state means creating political
order in the absence of a state with a legitimate monopoly over the use of force
and the capacity to authoritatively enforce the law and other rules. Of course, there
is no state or world government in the global realm, even though the United
Nations Security Council has limited authority to impose world order and peace.
To the extent that the international system contains rule structures and institutional
settings, it constitutes ‘governance without government’ by definition.
But why do we need to use the language of ‘governance’, if we can talk about
international institutions, such as International Organizations (IOs) or international regimes? While IOs are inter-Â�state institutions ‘with a street address’,
international regimes are defined as international institutions based on explicit
principles, norms, and rules, that is, international legal arrangements agreed
upon by national governments (Keohane 1989). The nuclear non-�proliferation
regime, the world trade order, the regime to prevent global climate change or the
various human rights treaties all constitute international regimes, i.e. form part
of global ‘governance without government’. These regimes have in common that
they are based on voluntary agreements by states and that there is no supreme
authority in the international system capable of enforcing these rules. Hence the
elaborate schemes to monitor and verify compliance with the rules and regulations of international regimes!
There is one emerging realm of international institution which is not covered
by the language of international inter-�state regimes or organizations as commonly used in the international relations literature. The Internet Corporation for
Assigned Names and Number (ICANN) regulates the internet, but is a non-�
governmental institution. Private rating agencies claim authoritative, consensual
and therefore legitimate knowledge about the credit-�worthiness of companies
and states and, thus, play an enormous role in international financial markets, as
the Euro crisis demonstrates. The UN Global Compact consists of firms voluntarily agreeing to comply with international human rights and environmental
norms. Thus, we observe the emergence of governance structures in international
life which are based on private authority, private regimes, or some mix of public
and private actors (see Hall and Biersteker 2002; Cutler et al. 1999; Haufler
1993; Reinicke 1998; Reinicke and Deng 2000). In particular, there seems to be
an increasing number of ‘public private partnerships’ (PPPs) in international life,
some of which are concerned with international rule-Â�setting. Other PPPs – the
Global Compact, for example – focus on rule implementation or service provision (Rosenau 2000; Börzel and Risse 2005; Schäferhoff et al. 2009).
‘Transnational governance’ refers to those governance arrangements beyond
the nation-�state in which private actors are systematically involved.2 Moreover,
we should clearly distinguish between lobbying or influence-�seeking activities of
private actors – firms and non-Â�governmental organizations ([I]NGOs) – on the
one hand, and their direct involvement in rule-�setting, rule implementation and
service providing activities, on the other. Only if and when non-�state actors have
a say in the decision-�making bodies of global governance, should we speak of
‘transnational governance’.
178╇╇ T. Risse
Transnational governance as ‘new modes of governance’ is ‘distinct from the
hierarchical control model characterizing the interventionist state. Governance is
the type of regulation typical of the cooperative state, where state and non-�state
actors participate in mixed public/private policy networks’ (Mayntz 2002: 21).
Thus, ‘new modes of global governance’ refers to those institutional arrangements beyond the nation-Â�state that are characterized by two features (see Table
14.1):
•
•
the inclusion of non-�state actors, such as firms, private interest groups, or
non-�governmental organizations (NGOs) in governance arrangements (actor
dimension);
an emphasis on non-�hierarchical modes of steering (steering modes).
Most of the literature on ‘new modes of governance’3 is concerned with the
actor dimension and, thus, with the inclusion of private actors in global governance. But we must also look at the steering modes. Modes of political steering
concern both rule-�setting and rule-�implementation processes including ensuring
compliance with international norms. Hierarchical steering refers to classic statehood in the Weberian or Eastonian sense (politics as the ‘authoritative allocation
of values for a given society’; see Easton 1965) and connotes the ultimate ability
of states to enforce the law through sanctions and the threat of force, if need be
(Weber 1921/1980: 29). Hierarchical steering is notably absent in the international system except, for example, in supranational organizations such as the
European Union (EU) where European law constitutes the ‘law of the land’ and,
thus, some elements of hierarchy are present.
However, no modern state relies solely on coercion and hierarchy to enforce
the law. The main difference between modern states and global governance is
not that non-�hierarchical modes of steering do not exist in the former. The main
difference is that global governance – whether through inter-Â�state regimes or
PPPs – has to rely solely on non-Â�hierarchical modes of steering in the absence of
a world government. As to these non-�hierarchical modes, we can further distinguish between two forms which rely on different modes of social action and
social control.
First, non-�hierarchical steering can use positive incentives and negative sanctions to entice actors into compliance with norms and rules. The point is to use
incentives and sanctions to manipulate the cost-�benefit calculations of actors so as
to convince them that rule compliance is in their best interest. As to rule-�setting,
‘bargaining’ during which self-Â�interested actors try to hammer out agreements of
give-�and-take based on fixed identities and interests has to be mentioned here,
too. This mode of steering essentially follows a logic of instrumental rationality
as theorized by rational choice. Actors are seen as egoistic utility maximizers or
optimizers who agree to rules, because they are in their own interests. Voluntary
compliance follows from self-�interested behaviour in this case.
A second type of non-�hierarchical steering focuses on increasing the moral
legitimacy of the rules and norms in question. The idea is that actors will comply
•â•‡ traditional nation-state;
•â•‡supranational institutions (EU,
partly WTO)
•â•‡ international regimes
•â•‡ international organizations
Hierarchical:
Top-down;
(threat of) sanctions
Non-hierarchical:
Positive incentives; bargaining;
non-manipulative persuasion
(learning, arguing, etc.)
Note:
Shaded area = ‘new’ modes of governance.
Public actors only
Actors involved steering modes
Table 14.1╇ The realm of governance
Private actors only
•â•‡ corporatism
•â•‡public–private networks and
partnerships
•â•‡ bench-marking
•â•‡private interest government/
private regimes
•â•‡private–private partnerships
(NGOs–companies)
•â•‡Contracting out and out-Sourcing •â•‡ corporate hierarchies
of public functions to private
actors
Public and private actors
180╇╇ T. Risse
voluntarily with norms and rules, the more they are convinced of the legitimacy
of the rule (see Hurd 1999). The legitimacy of a rule can result from beliefs in
the moral validity of the norm itself, but it can also result from beliefs in the
validity of the procedure by which the rule had been worked out. Voluntary rule
compliance is based on the acceptance of a particular logic of appropriateness
(March and Olsen 1989, 1998). But how do actors come to accept a new logic of
appropriateness? They acquire the social knowledge to function appropriately in
a given society or they start believing in the moral validity of the norms and
rules in question. In either case, the micro-�mechanism underlying this type of
social steering involves learning and persuasion based on arguing.
Arguing implies that actors try to challenge the validity claims inherent in any
causal or normative statement and to seek a communicative consensus about
their understanding of a situation as well as justifications for the principles and
norms guiding their action. Argumentative rationality also means that the participants in a discourse are open to be persuaded by the better argument and that
relationships of power and social hierarchies recede into the background (Habermas 1981; Risse 2000). Argumentative and deliberative behaviour is as goal-�
oriented as strategic interactions but the goal is not to attain one’s fixed
preferences, but to seek a reasoned consensus. Actors’ interests, preferences and
the perceptions of the situation are no longer fixed, but subject to discursive
challenges. Where argumentative rationality prevails, actors do not seek to maximize or to satisfy their given interests and preferences, but to challenge and to
justify the validity claims inherent in them – and are prepared to change their
views of the world or even their interests in light of the better argument. In other
words, argumentative and discursive processes challenge the truth claims which
are inherent in identities, interests, and norms.
To summarize the analysis so far, ‘global governance’ refers to international
regimes and international (inter-�state) organizations, on the one hand, and to
transnational arrangements, on the other, which involve non-�state actors directly
in rule-Â�setting, -implementation and service provision. Both inter-Â�state and public–private governance beyond the nation-Â�state must rely on non-Â�hierarchical
modes of steering, be it via incentives and sanctions or be it via learning and
persuasion.
What does the governance perspective add to foreign policy
analysis – and vice versa?
For quite some time, foreign policy analysis used to be a sideshow in the study
of international relations. This is unfortunate, since the analysis of states’ external affairs adds a decidedly agency-Â�oriented perspective to the international relations discipline (Carlsnaes 2002) which used to suffer from overly structural
approaches, be it from a neo-�realist (Waltz 1979), Marxist (Wallerstein 1974,
1980, 1989) or social constructivist standpoint (Wendt 1999). In fact, the governance perspective – I would not use the term ‘theory’ here – has often been
overly structural, too. Some works on global governance or on the rise of private
Foreign policy analysis and the governance turn╇╇ 181
authority in international life have been suspiciously actor-�free (e.g. Hall and
Biersteker 2002; Held and McGrew 2002; for a critical perspective, see Lederer
and Müller 2005). Only recently have scholars started asking ‘who governs the
globe?’ (Avant et al. 2010).
This is where foreign policy analysis and the governance perspective meet.
Foreign policy analysis tries to explain the external affairs of particular agents in
international life, namely, states. Governance focuses on the various modes of
steering by which actors – whether state or non-Â�state – try to contribute to the
political regulation of social affairs or to provide common goods.
Yet, foreign policy analysis has been overly state-�centric. When we think
‘foreign policy’, we mostly conceptualize relations among sovereign states.
Interestingly enough, Walter Carlsnaes’ own definition of foreign policy already
contains an opening toward transnationalism:
foreign policies consist of those actions which, expressed in the form of
explicitly stated goals, commitments and/or directives, and pursued by governmental representatives acting on behalf of their sovereign communities,
are directed toward objectives, conditions, and actors – both governmental
and non-Â�governmental – which they want to affect and which lie beyond
their territorial legitimacy.
(Carlsnaes 2002: 335; see also Carlsnaes 1986, Ch. 2; 2013)
This definition already encompasses transnational relations as defined by Robert
Keohane and Joseph Nye (see above, fn.€ 2) insofar as state actors can direct
their foreign policy decisions and actions toward non-�governmental entities.
State X offering multinational corporation Z some favourable investment conditions would still be foreign policy. Moreover, Carlsnaes’ conceptualization
implies intentional action and directedness – irrespective of whether the foreign
policies of a state might have some unintended consequences. At least implicitly, the definition also encompasses non-�hierarchial modes of social
�coordination as most states pursue their foreign policies through negotiations,
bargaining or arguing without interfering in another state’s territorial control
and authority (‘Westphalian sovereignty’ in Stephen Krasner’s terms; see
Krasner 1999). In short, non-�hierarchical actions directed at other states as well
as transnational relations between states and non-�state actors are the subject
matter of foreign policy, too.
However, Walter Carlsnaes still confines foreign policy analysis to the study
of state behaviour, whether directed at state or non-�state actors. But why not
extend the use of the tools of foreign policy analysis to the external affairs of
multinational corporations or of globally operating non-�governmental organizations (INGOs)? For example, most multinational corporations have instituted
their own external affairs departments by now to deal with the policy world as
well as with stakeholders around the world. In this sense, Daimler, General
Motors or BP all conduct their own foreign policies. Why not compare them
with the external affairs of states?
182╇╇ T. Risse
This is where the governance turn has something to contribute to foreign policy
studies. Work on the ‘new’ modes of governance encompassing non-Â�state actors
and non-�hierarchical modes of steering is still interested in politics and policies
and, thus, in the regulation of social affairs. Market behaviour by private actors is
not subject to governance research, even though the externalities (positive and
negative) of market activities are. From a governance perspective, one would
examine the contributions of actors – whether state or non-Â�state – to the regulation
of global affairs and would not confine foreign policy analysis to states.
Of course, the main objection to this attempt to blur the boundaries between
state and non-Â�state actors is that Daimler and ExxonMobil – despite all their
market power – still lack one important ingredient of statehood, namely, sovereignty. INGOs such as Amnesty International or Greenpeace might affect global
governance and might contribute to international norm creation and implementation. And they are increasingly co-�governing international affairs (Hall and
Biersteker 2002; see also Risse 2013). But they are not sovereign states, of course.
The objection is correct to the extent that non-�state actors lack international sovereignty and the legitimacy which international recognition confers upon states. At
the same time, however, other ingredients of national sovereignty are more fiction
than fact in the contemporary international system. For example, even the most
society-�centric work on transnational actors still takes consolidated statehood for
granted with full domestic sovereignty as the ability to implement and enforce
central decisions and the monopoly over the means of violence (Krasner 1999). We
might be puzzled by the rise of ‘private authority’ in international affairs, but we
assume that nation-�states fully enjoy the ability to rule hierarchically within their
domestic system. What, however, if ‘limited statehood’ in terms of constraints on
the state’s ability to exert domestic sovereignty constitutes the rule rather than the
exception in the contemporary global system (see Risse 2011)? Fragile, failing and
failed states are only the tip of the iceberg with regard to such ‘limited statehood’.
In this case, the distinction between state actors and non-�state actors in terms of the
(in-)ability to steer hierarchically starts blurring. Moreover, we might face situations
in which state actors act like private actors in the sense of not encountering institutional constraints on self-�interested and egoistic behaviour, while so-�called private
actors contribute to the public good. This calls for a research agenda in which the
usual distinctions of Western modernity according to which ‘the state’ equals ‘the
public’ and non-Â�state actors equal the private domain no longer make sense. Rather,
we would have to look for the governance contributions of either actors irrespective
of whether they occupy governmental positions or not.
These considerations challenge conventional foreign policy analysis as mostly
confined to the external affairs of sovereign states. Here, the governance perspective might serve as an eye-�opener in at least two ways: first, it opens up the
research agenda toward studying the external affairs of non-�state actors and
comparing them to the foreign policies of states. Second, its emphasis on hierarchical as well as non-�hierarchical modes of steering offers important distinctions
among various modes of social action and interaction which foreign policy
analysis might find useful. This is particularly relevant, since foreign policy
Foreign policy analysis and the governance turn╇╇ 183
action as defined by Walter Carlsnaes is predominantly non-�hierarchical, because
most states in the international system – not even to mention non-Â�state actors –
do not have coercive means at their disposal in external affairs.
Conclusions: foreign policy analysis and the governance turn
Almost fifty years ago, Ekkehart Krippendorff asked whether foreign policy is
actually foreign policy (1963). He argued at the time that foreign policy action
constitutes domestic politics by other means and that domestic circumstances
more or less explain the foreign policies of state. While Krippendorff was a
Marxist, Ernst-�Otto Czempiel made a similar point from a liberal perspective,
namely, that one could only understand US foreign policy during the Cold War
when taking the US political system and the struggle for power among the
various interest groups into account (Czempiel 1979). Several decades later,
there is little doubt that foreign policy analysis requires a look at domestic politics and that one has to open up the black box of the state (Carlsnaes 2013).
It is less clear, however, whether a state-�centric perspective on foreign policy
analysis (and on international relations in general) is still helpful to understand
and explain contemporary world affairs in an age of globalization. Of course,
states remain central actors in international relations. However, the state has got
company in the meantime with regard to global governance. To ask ‘who
governs’ in world affairs is to acknowledge that non-Â�state actors – whether multinational corporations or international non-Â�governmental organizations (INGOs)
– are part and parcel of rule-Â�making and rule implementation in international
politics (Avant et al. 2010). While transnational actors have always been significant and have influenced international relations as inter-�state relations, they
have now become ‘global governors’ in their own right. As a result, foreign
policy analysis needs to take the governance turn more seriously, if it wants to
remain relevant for the study of world affairs.
Notes
1 This part of the chapter builds on Risse (2004).
2 For the classic definition of transnational relations, see Keohane and Nye (1971); also
see Risse (2013).
3 One should note, however, that ‘new modes’ of governance are not new at all. There
have always been governance arrangements in transnational space that included non-�
state actors. The Hudson Bay Company or the Dutch East India Company are cases in
point, i.e. semi-�private corporations acting on behalf of colonial powers (see Conrad
and Stange 2011).
References
Avant, Deborah, Finnemore, Martha and Sell, Susan K. (eds) (2010). Who governs the
Globe? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Börzel, Tanja A. and Risse, Thomas (2005). Public–private partnerships: Effective and
legitimate tools of international governance? In E. Grande and L.W. Pauly (eds),
184╇╇ T. Risse
Complex sovereignty: Reconstituting political authority in the twenty-�first century
(pp.€195–216). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1986). Ideology and foreign policy: Problems of comparative conceptualization. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Carlsnaes, Walter (1992). The agency–structure problem in foreign policy analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 36(3), 245–270.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2002). Foreign policy. In W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B. Simmons
(eds), Handbook of International Relations (pp.€331–349). London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2004). Where is the analysis of European foreign policy going? European Union Politics, 5, 495–508.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2013). Foreign policy. In W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B. Simmons
(eds), Handbook of International Relations, 2nd ed. (pp. 298–325) London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter and Smith, Steve (eds) (1994). European foreign policy: The EC and
changing perspectives in Europe. London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter, Risse, Thomas and Simmons, Beth (eds) (2002). Handbook of International Relations. London: Sage.
Carlsnaes, Walter, Sjursen, Helene and White, Brian (eds) (2004). Contemporary European foreign policy. London: Sage.
Conrad, Sebastian and Stange, Marion (2011). Governance and colonial rule. In T. Risse
(ed.), Governance without a state? Policies and politics in areas of limited statehood
(pp.€39–64). New York: Columbia University Press.
Cutler, Claire A., Haufler, Virginia and Porter, Tony (eds) (1999). Private authority and
international affairs. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Czempiel, Ernst-Â�Otto (1979). Amerikanische Außenpolitik. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.
Czempiel, Ernst-�Otto and Rosenau, James (eds) (1992). Governance without government:
Order and change in world politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Easton, David (1965). A systems analysis of political life. New York: Wiley.
Habermas, Jürgen (1981). Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp.
Hall, Rodney Bruce and Biersteker, Thomas J. (eds) (2002). The emergence of private
authority in global governance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haufler, Virginia (1993). Crossing the boundary between public and private: International
regimes and non-�state actors. In V. Rittberger (ed.), Regime theory and international
relations (pp.€94–111). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Held, David and McGrew, Anthony (eds) (2002). Governing globalization: Power,
authority and global governance. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hurd, Ian (1999). Legitimacy and authority in international politics. International Organization, 53(2), 379–408.
Keohane, Robert and Nye, Joseph (1971). Introduction. In R. Keohane and J. Nye (eds),
Transnational relations and world politics (pp.€ XII–XVI). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Keohane, Robert O. (1989). International institutions and state power. Boulder, CO:
Westview.
Kooiman, Jan (ed.) (1993). Modern governance: New government–society interactions.
London: Sage.
Krasner, Stephen D. (1999). Sovereignty: Organized hypocrisy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Krippendorff, Ekkehart (1963). Ist Außenpolitik Außenpolitik? Politische VierteljahresÂ�
schrift, 4, 243–266.
Foreign policy analysis and the governance turn╇╇ 185
Lederer, Markus and Müller, Philipp S. (eds) (2005). Criticizing global governance. New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P. (1989). Rediscovering institutions. New York: Free
Press.
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P. (1998). The institutional dynamics of international
political orders. International Organization, 52(4), 943–969.
Mayntz, Renate (1998). New challenges to governance theory. Jean Monnet Chair Papers,
50. Florence: Robert Schuman Centre at the European University Institute.
Mayntz, Renate (2002). Common goods and governance. In A. Heritier (ed.), Common
goods: Reinventing European and international governance (pp.€ 15–27). Lanham,
MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Pierre, J. and Peters, B. Guy (2000). Governance, politics, and the state. London: Macmillan.
Reinicke, Wolfgang H. (1998). Global public policy: Governing without government?
Washington, DC: Brookings Institute.
Reinicke, Wolfgang H. and Deng, Francis (2000). Critical choices: The United Nations,
networks, and the future of global governance. Ottawa: International Development
Research Centre.
Risse, Thomas (2000). â•›“Let’s Argue!” Communicative action in International Relations.
International Organization, 54(1), 1–39.
Risse, Thomas (2004). Global governance and communicative action. Government and
Opposition, 39(2), 288–313.
Risse, Thomas (ed.) (2011). Governance without a state? Policies and politics in areas of
limited statehood. New York: Columbia University Press.
Risse, Thomas (2013). Transnational actors and world politics. In W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse
and B. Simmons (eds), Handbook of International Relations, 2nd ed. (pp. 426–452)
London: Sage.
Rosenau, Pauline Vaillancourt (ed.) (2000). Public–private policy partnerships. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Schäferhoff, Marco, Campe, Sabine and Kaan, Christopher (2009). Transnational public–
private partnerships in international relations: Making sense of concepts, research
frameworks, and results. International Studies Review, 11(3), 451–474.
Wallerstein, Immanuel (1989 [1974/1980]). The modern world-Â�system, Vols. 1–3. San
Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Waltz, Kenneth (1979). Theory of international politics. Reading, MA: Addison-�Wesley.
Weber, Max (1980 [1921]). Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr.
Wendt, Alexander (1999). Social theory of international politics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Williamson, Oliver E. (1975). Markets and hierachies: Analysis and anti-�trust. New
York: Free Press.
World Commission on Environment and Development (1987). Our common future: From
one earth to one world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
15 Apostleship
A South African national role
conception
Deon Geldenhuys
Apart from Walter Carlsnaes’ special interest in foreign policy analysis, two
other ‘Carlsnaesian’ markers help to demarcate this contribution to the Festschrift. One is provided by Walter’s response when, in 1994, I told him of the
strongly ethical thrust of the foreign policy that the ‘new’ South Africa was
about to pursue. ‘I’ve heard that one before,’ was his sceptical response. The
present chapter investigates the record of democratic South Africa’s ethical
foreign policy over the past 16 years. The other marker is a question I heard
Walter ask of work produced by political scientists: ‘Where is the theory?’
Here, an individualist interpretative approach to the study of foreign policy
(Carlsnaes 2002: 341) will be used. Known as national role conceptions, this
under-�utilised approach developed out of role theory which, in turn, originated
in the fields of social psychology and sociology (Aggestam 1999: 11; Adigbuo
2007: 88–89).
National role conceptions
In a seminal article Holsti (1970: 245–246) defined national role conceptions as
‘the policymakers’ own definitions of the general kinds of decisions, commitments, rules and actions suitable to their state, and of the functions, if any, their
state should perform on a continuing basis in the international system or in subordinate regional systems’. These role conceptions, Holsti suggested, explain to
a large extent the foreign policy behaviour of governments (i.e. decisions and
actions, or ‘national role performance’). Holsti also hypothesised that national
role conceptions have both domestic and external sources. The internal origins
are a complex mixture of location, capabilities, socio-�economic needs, national
values and ideology, public opinion, political needs and the personalities of
leaders. The external environment is the source of what Holsti termed ‘role prescriptions’, and includes the structure and values of the international system,
general legal principles, multilateral treaties, world opinion and the expectations
that other governments have of the state concerned (Holsti 1970: 243–246;
Walker 1987: 243).
Holsti (1970: 256–284) identified a set of 17 national role conceptions based
on statements by the leaders of 71 states found in nearly 1000 different sources
Apostleship╇╇ 187
during the period 1965–1967. The vast majority of these countries articulated
more than one role conception, some as many as eight. Since his inquiry was
conducted in the mid-Â�1960s, Holsti’s role conceptions understandably reflected
the state of world politics at the time. Six were typical Cold War roles, namely,
faithful ally, anti-�imperialist agent, defender of the faith, bastion of the revolution, regional protector and protectee. Non-�aligned roles were those of independent, active independent, mediator-�integrator, bridge and isolate. The
remaining six role conceptions were regionally directed, namely, liberation supporter, regional leader, regional-�subsystem collaborator, developer, internal
development and example (Adigbuo 2005: 60).
Holsti (1970: 246–247) maintained that role theory, as he transposed it to the
international context, ‘offers a framework for describing national role performance and role conceptions and for exploring the sources of those conceptions’.
Several scholars have tested and indeed confirmed these claims, while others
Â�developed Holsti’s typology of role conceptions and adapted it to the post-Â�Cold
War international environment (Walker 1987: 241–259; Aggestam 1999: 15–18;
n.d.: 3–6; Hyde-Â�Price 2000: 22–48; Hernández 2006: 3–7; Adigbuo 2007:
83–97; Adigbuo 2008: 223–245; Krotz 2010: 6–35).
Drawing on Holsti’s theoretical framework, the present inquiry offers a brief
case study of an ethical foreign policy. Advocates of such a policy typically
reject the notion that ‘ethics cease at the water’s edge’; instead, they are committed to exporting human rights and invariably also democracy to other societies
(Smith and Light 2001: 3–4). The most appropriate of Holsti’s role conceptions
is the defender of the faith, presumably derived from the title fidei defensor that
Pope Leo X in 1521 conferred on King Henry VIII for defending the Roman
Catholic faith against the Protestant Reformation (Adigbuo 2008: 227–228).
Holsti (1970: 264) portrayed the role conception as ‘defending value systems
(rather than specified territories) from attack’, adding that defenders of the faith
‘presumably undertake special responsibilities to guarantee ideological purity for
a group of other states’. President John F. Kennedy famously articulated this role
conception in his inaugural address: ‘Let every nation know .â•›.â•›. that we shall pay
any price, bear any burden, meet any hardship, support any friend, oppose any
foe to assure the survival and success of liberty’ (as cited in Holsti 1970:
264–265).
Holsti’s conceptualisation of a defender of the faith needs a two-Â�fold revision
to make it relevant to today’s world. We require not merely a reactive defence of
certain values (Western liberal democracy or communism) against a grave and
imminent threat (the Soviet bloc or the Western alliance), but also the active promotion abroad of values or a set of ideas without there necessarily being a specific enemy to be confronted. The notion of apostleship is proposed as an
alternative designation, defined as championship or leadership in propaganda.
The latter term incidentally also has religious origins: in 1622 the Catholic
Church founded a congregation called Propaganda to spread Catholicism
(de propaganda fide). The propaganda associated with apostleship involves
‘the€ spread of opinions and principles, especially to effect change or reform’
188╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
(Chambers Twentieth Century Dictionary 1974). The leadership role involved in
apostleship should, however, extend beyond the dissemination of a message.
Following Riddell-Â�Dixon’s (2005: 1067–1068) typology of leadership, we could
distinguish between the task of articulating, promoting and implementing a
secular gospel. Democracy and human rights are the heart of the ‘faith’.
In investigating South Africa’s apostleship, all three tasks Holsti claimed for
his analytical scheme will be attempted: the particular role conception will be
presented in the words of the policymakers who formulated the role (articulation); the country’s accompanying role performance will be sketched in terms of
the deeds of the policymakers (promotion and implementation); and the likely
sources of the role conception will be identified. It involves recording what
South African policymakers say, investigating why they say it, and describing
what they do (or fail to do) in terms of advancing democracy and human rights.
It should be borne in mind that apostleship is by no means the only national
role conception that South Africa has pursued since its democratic rebirth in
1994. Using Holsti’s typology, regionally directed roles – where South Africa
speaks and acts as a major power in Africa and on behalf of the continent to the
wider world – are especially pertinent. South Africa’s solidarity with countries
of the Global South resembles elements of Holsti’s anti-Â�imperialist agent of old,
just as its ‘liberatory solidarity’ with countries that had supported the ruling
African National Congress (ANC) in its struggle against apartheid bears some
similarity with Holsti’s liberation supporter. At the same time South Africa
regards itself as a bridge-Â�builder between North and South, again a role conception corresponding to one featured in Holsti’s framework.
Articulating the faith
Seven months after assuming power in 1994, the ANC issued a foreign policy
blueprint which asserted that democratic South Africa will ‘canonise human
rights in our international relations’ and assume a ‘central role’ in a ‘worldwide
human rights campaign’ (Foreign Policy Perspective 1994: 2–4). In like vein,
Foreign Minister Alfred Nzo proclaimed: ‘Human rights are the cornerstone of
our government policy and we shall not hesitate to carry the message to the far
corners of the world’ (Discussion Paper 1996: 16). That message, according to
the ANC’s 1994 policy document, was that ‘just and lasting solutions to the
problems of human kind can only come through the promotion of democracy,
worldwide’. And in donning the mantle of apostleship, ‘we shall not be selective
nor, indeed, be afraid to raise human rights violations with countries where our
own and other interests might be negatively affected’ (Foreign Policy Perspective 1994: 2–4). Nor would South Africa be swayed by claims of cultural relativism in the sphere of human rights. ‘There cannot be one system for Africa and
another for the rest of the world,’ President Nelson Mandela (1994–1999)
insisted (as cited in Vickers 2003: 85).
Mandela and especially his deputy Thabo Mbeki used the notion of an
African renaissance as a vehicle for promoting human rights and democracy on
Apostleship╇╇ 189
the continent. At a summit of the Southern African Development Community
(SADC) in 1997, Mandela referred to ‘[o]ur dream of Africa’s rebirth as we
enter the new millennium’. That ‘rebirth’, Mandela argued, was critically
dependent on African countries committing themselves to ‘the principles of
democracy, respect for human rights and the basic tenets of good governance’
(as cited in Gumede 2005: 201). For seriously errant African states, Mandela had
little mercy: ‘We must all accept that we cannot abuse the concept of national
sovereignty to deny the rest of the continent the right and duty to intervene when
behind those sovereign boundaries, people are being slaughtered to protect
tyranny’ (as cited in Landsberg 2007: 199).
Apostleship remained a feature of South Africa’s foreign policy during
Mbeki’s presidency (1999–2008). The first two principles underpinning its
foreign policy, the Department of Foreign Affairs reaffirmed in 2003, were a
commitment to the promotion of human rights and democracy (Strategic Plan
2003–2005: 11). Consider also Mbeki’s denunciation of one-Â�party rule, military
governments and personal dictatorships in Africa and his assertion that governments must ‘derive their authority and legitimacy from the will of the people’
(as cited in Landsberg 2004: 162). President Mbeki was also a stout defender of
the new sovereignty regime incorporated into the African Union founded in
2002:
We [African leaders] should not allow the fact of the independence of each
one of our countries to turn us into spectators when crimes against the
people are being committed .â•›.â•›. we will have to proceed from the position
that we are each our brothers and sisters keeper.
(Guardian 2003)
An ardent champion of an African renaissance, Mbeki regarded the establishment of democratic political systems and the protection of human rights as one
of the initiative’s principal tasks (Mbeki 1999: 3–4). It should be noted that
Mbeki made Africa the centrepiece of South Africa’s external relations, thereby
combining regionally-�directed role conceptions with that of apostleship.
The conflation of regional roles and apostleship has continued under President Jacob Zuma, who took office in May 2009 (after the interim presidency of
Kgalema Motlanthe). Maite Nkoane-Â�Mashabane, Zuma’s Minister of International Relations and Cooperation (as the earlier portfolio of Foreign Affairs was
renamed), spoke of the ‘primacy of the African continent’ in South Africa’s
foreign policy, at the core of which is a ‘developmental agenda’ (Nkoane-Â�
Mashabane 2009a: 1–2). The Strategic Plan, 2010–2013 of the Department of
International Relations and Cooperation (DIRCO) in turn allows for ongoing
apostleship by asserting that the principles underpinning South Africa’s foreign
policy have remained the same since 1994. The first two are still a commitment
to the promotion of human rights and democracy, respectively (Strategic Plan
2010–2013: 7). In June 2009 the Deputy Minister of International Relations and
Cooperation, Ebrahim Ismail Ebrahim, assured Parliament that the Zuma
190╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
Â�government will place ‘a greater emphasis on human rights’, will focus on ‘preventing gross violations of human rights’ abroad, and that ‘[w]e intend to more
robustly flex our muscles on human rights issues so that we can never be accused
of betraying the ideals on which our democracy was founded’ (Ebrahim 2009:
1,4).
Such unequivocal commitments to the international promotion abroad of
human rights and ipso facto democracy as desirable objectives have been rare
since Zuma assumed the presidency. More often than not, this ethical element
has lately been expressed in the context of a developmental agenda that acknowledges the importance of good governance in Africa in particular. Consider
Minister Nkoane-Â�Mashabane’s statement that South Africa’s so-Â�called African
Agenda ‘is grounded in a philosophy that recognises the inseperable, triangular
linkage between democracy and good governance, peace and security, and socioÂ�economic development’ (Nkoane-Â�Mashabane 2009b: 9–10).
Sources of the faith
South Africa’s history, especially the black majority’s denial of fundamental
human rights under apartheid, has been a major domestic source of foreign
policy since 1994. The Republic will spread the message of human rights across
the globe, Foreign Minister Nzo promised, because ‘[w]e have suffered too
much ourselves not to do so’ (Discussion Paper 1996: 16). A second and related
source was that South Africans owed their victory over apartheid to support and
solidarity from the rest of Africa. ‘That’, Deputy President Thabo Mbeki said in
1998, ‘imposes an obligation on us to use this gift of freedom .â•›.â•›. to advance the
cause of the peoples of our continent’ (Mbeki 1998: 7). In the third place the
new rulers asserted that ‘our foreign relations must mirror our deep commitment
to the consolidation of a democratic South Africa’ (Foreign Policy Perspective
1994: 2–4). A fourth source is the policymakers’ belief that South Africa’s
‘miracle’ of democratisation could and indeed should serve as a role model for
other societies suffering injustice and conflict (Foreign Policy Perspective 1994:
2–4).
The Republic’s status as a regional power provides a fifth source of its apostleship. The end of apartheid had left South Africa’s tangible power resources
largely intact. The country was still a regional power at the continental level and
a superpower in the Southern African context. In addition to its economic and
military strength, South Africa possessed non-�material resources such as exemplary political and social values, quality political leadership at home and a sound
diplomatic reputation abroad (Flemes 2007: 7–18).
A 1996 policy document of the Department of Foreign Affairs declared that
‘South Africa possesses the intrinsic capabilities to play the role of a middle
power in global terms’ (Discussion Paper 1996: 66). Herein lies a sixth source of
South Africa’s apostleship. Whereas regional powers have a geographically
restricted scope, middle powers have traditionally played their roles on a global
scale; consider Canada, Norway and Sweden in the Cold War era. These
Apostleship╇╇ 191
�
countries
exerted a measure of influence in world politics not through the projection of military might but on the basis of soft power resources like their democratic credentials, political stability, socio-�economic prosperity, diplomatic skills
and nuclear weapon-Â�free status (Breuning 2007: 150,182; Bischoff 2003: 183–4).
Since the end of the East-�West divide, so-�called emerging middle powers from
the Global South have entered the world stage. With India, Brazil and South
Africa in their ranks, the new generation of middle powers are also expected to
exercise moral authority in the world generally and to help keep their backyards
‘neat and orderly’ (Chase et al. 1996: 35). (All three the new middle powers
incidentally qualify for the status of regional powers too.)
What Holsti referred to as role prescriptions, or role expectations in Aggestam’s (1999: 12) terminology, constitute a seventh source of South Africa’s
apostleship. Not only has ‘a leadership role .â•›.â•›. been imposed on South Africa’,
as then Deputy Foreign Minister Aziz Pahad explained over ten years ago, but
the international community entertained ‘great expectations from South Africa’s
role’ (as cited in Landsberg 2004: 215). External expectations are being heeded
by the Zuma government too. ‘Our country finds itself today in a position of
responsibility as a member of the international community’, the Minister of
International Relations and Cooperation told Parliament in April 2010. ‘We are
constantly reminded .â•›.â•›. that more is expected of us. For our country, our region
and continent, this is a responsibility we can neither shirk nor fail in’ (Nkoane-Â�
Mashabane 2010a: 3). South Africa’s election to a second term as a non-Â�
permanent member of the UN Security Council (2011–2012) will add to foreign
expectations of the country’s role at the global level.
A closely related eighth source is South Africa’s vaunted moral authority. In
1996 the Department of Foreign Affairs spoke glowingly of the new South Africa’s ‘unique moral legitimacy’ in the world (Department of Foreign Affairs
1996: 66). Nearly ten years later, the Department still invoked South Africa’s
‘particular moral authority’. This was said to derive from the country’s ‘principles, policies and priorities’ that ‘provide hope not only for the people of South
Africa and Africa, but also for the [Global] South since they essentially provide
hope for humanity as a whole’ (Department of Foreign Affairs Policy, Research
and Analysis Unit 2005: 2).
Finally, South Africa’s moral standing, combined with its remarkably peaceful transition from pigmentocracy to non-Â�racial democracy, its relative prosperity and stability as well as its regional-Â�cum-middle power status, have
contributed to South Africa’s ‘exceptionalism’ in Africa and beyond. This status
in turn equips if not entitles South Africa to take on an international leadership
role. Western powers seem to share this assessment. On the eve of the EU–South
Africa summit in July 2008 in Bordeaux, an EU statement referred to South
Africa as ‘the main regional power in Africa. .â•›.â•›. It is one of the drivers of growth
in the continent and a success story that refutes Afro-Â�pessimism’ (EU–South
Africa Summit 2008).
192╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
Promoting the faith
One of the main ways in which South Africa has promoted the core ideas of its
apostleship – human rights and democracy – is in shaping Africa’s new institutions
of continental governance. South Africa, in the person of Mbeki, was one of the
leading architects of the African Union (AU). The Constitutive Act of the AU of
2000, unlike the Charter of the preceding Organisation of African Unity, lists the
promotion of ‘democratic principles and institutions, popular participation and
good governance’ as well as the protection of human and peoples’ rights among its
14 objectives. The AU is even authorised to intervene in a member state ‘in respect
of grave circumstances, namely: war crimes, genocide and crimes against humanity as well as threats to legitimate order’. At its inaugural summit in 2002, the AU
adopted the Declaration on Democracy, Political, Economic and Corporate Governance, which commits member states to uphold the rule of law; the equality of
all citizens before the law; individual and collective freedoms; equality of opportunity; individual participation in democratic political processes; periodic elections
of leaders for fixed terms of office; the separation of powers; and good governance. The African Peer Review Mechanism, also created in 2002, is an ambitious
system of partner evaluation designed to promote good governance and sustainable
development in participating states. The Peace and Security Council, the AU’s
standing decision-�making organ for the prevention, management and resolution of
conflicts, enumerates the advancement of democracy, good governance, the rule of
law and human rights among its objectives. Africa’s progressive system of continental governance is indeed a tribute to South Africa’s apostleship.
Implementing the faith
The task of implementation involves giving practical effect to policy positions,
or ‘walking the talk’. One way in which South Africa has done this, is by acceding to all major international human rights instruments, including the 1948
�Universal Declaration of Human Rights; the twin covenants on civil and political rights, and on economic, social and cultural rights of 1966; the Convention
on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination of 1966; and the 1981
African Charter of Human and People’s Rights. A keen proponent of the African
Peer Review Mechanism, South Africa submitted itself to partner evaluation.
Reference can also be made to South Africa’s adoption of the Implementation of
the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court Act 2002, to give local
legal effect to its accession to the Rome Statute of the ICC. In addition, South
Africa’s advocacy of democracy and human rights in Africa (and elsewhere) is
grounded in its compliance with these standards at home. Through such �domestic
actions, South Africa has shown that it practices at home what it preaches
abroad, and in so doing it may be trying to serve as an example to others (cf.
Holsti’s national role conception of ‘example’).
There is also another side of the ledger, containing cases of South Africa not
‘living by the faith’ when dealing with some other countries. Its relations with
Apostleship╇╇ 193
Zimbabwe, Sudan, Equatorial Guinea and Myanmar illustrate the limits of South
Africa’s apostleship.
Zimbabwe
Following his defeat in a referendum on a new constitution in February 2000,
President Robert Mugabe’s political repression and ruinous economic policies
brought Zimbabwe to the brink of state collapse. Mbeki stoutly defended Zimbabweans’ sovereign right to resolve their own problems without foreign pressure
and dictation. Foreign Minister Nkosazana Dlamini Zuma even vowed that
Mugabe would ‘never be condemned’ by South Africa as long as the ANC
remained in power (as cited in Olivier 2003: 819) – an acknowledgement of the
liberatory solidarity between the ANC and Mugabe’s Zimbabwe African
National Union (ZANU). Rather than confront or criticise Mugabe, Mbeki opted
for constructive engagement by assuming the role of mediator between opposing
political forces in Zimbabwe. As a consequence Mbeki opposed Zimbabwe’s
suspension from the Commonwealth in 2002 and he also rejected the smart sanctions that Western states imposed against Zimbabwe’s ruling elite.
In no mood for compromise, Mugabe resorted to a new and singularly brutal
crackdown on opposition parties and groups in March 2007. Britain in response
urged the UN Security Council to accelerate punitive action against Zimbabwe.
South Africa, then a non-�permanent member of the Council, was adamant that
the Security Council should not deal with the matter as Zimbabwe did not constitute a threat to international peace and security. Instead, South Africa insisted
that SADC was the appropriate multilateral forum for dealing with the problems
in Zimbabwe by diplomatic means. SADC duly gave Mbeki a mandate to continue his diplomatic endeavours in Zimbabwe (Kagwanja 2009: 294–295).
It took a further deterioration of the situation to give international mediation a
new impetus. The uncontested presidential election of June 2008, which Mugabe
won by default, prompted African states to invite representatives from both the
AU and UN to assist Mbeki. The increasingly multilateral character of the mediation effort seemed to pay off: within weeks ZANU and the two factions of the
MDC began talks on forming a government of national unity based on power
sharing. Although the so-�called Global Political Agreement was signed in September 2008, continuing discord between the protagonists delayed implementation until February 2009. By then Mbeki had been ousted from the presidency.
As main mediator and co-Â�guarantor (with the AU and SADC) of Zimbabwe’s
Global Political Agreement, Zuma acknowledged, South Africa has a vested
interest in advancing political reconciliation and economic reconstruction in its
neighbouring state (Zuma 2009; Ebrahim 2009: 3). Zuma is, however, unlikely
to adopt a more forceful approach to Mugabe than previously, despite the latter’s often obstructive behaviour in the multiparty cabinet. For one thing, political debts weigh with Zuma. Speaking in Harare in August 2009, the president
mentioned ‘the critical incidents in our history which will forever bind us for
generations to come’. The Zimbabweans ‘never ceased to provide material and
194╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
political support to us during the struggle against apartheid’, Zuma recalled
(Zuma 2009).
In sum, its involvement in the Zimbabwe situation since 2000 reflected very
little of South Africa’s apostleship role conception. Far from prioritising the restoration of democracy and human rights in Zimbabwe, South Africa’s engagement was informed by the need to stabilise the situation there and help rebuild
the devastated economy, not least to contain the negative spill-Â�over of Zimbabwe’s
near implosion on surrounding countries. South Africa also drew on its status as
a continental power (and sub-Â�regional superpower) and on sentiments of liberatory solidarity with Mugabe’s party.
Sudan
In 2003 a civil war broke out in the Darfur region of Sudan between two rebel movements, the Sudan Liberation Movement (SLM) and the Justice and Equality Movement (JEM), on the one side, and the Sudanese Armed Forces and their Arab
Janjaweed proxies, on the other. Sudanese and Janjaweed forces have been accused
of the deliberate destruction of between 80 and 90 per cent of black African villages,
scorched earth tactics, bombing and murdering civilians, attacks on refugees, racially
targeted sexual violence, abduction of children, obstruction of humanitarian relief
operations and ethnic cleansing (Human Rights Watch 2007). By the time the Darfur
Peace Agreement (DPA) was concluded in May 2006 under the auspices of the AU,
estimates of the death toll from the six-�year war ranged between 200,000 and
400,000. Violence continued despite the peace accord, albeit on a lesser scale than
before (De Waal 2009). In June 2009 the US Agency for International Development
(USAID) reported that since 2003 the humanitarian emergency in Darfur has
affected over 4.7 million people, of whom 2.7 million were internally displaced.
South Africa opposed moves in the UN Human Rights Council and the
Security Council to censure the Bashir government or subject it to punitive
measures (Nathan 2008: 2). The Republic’s loyalties became even clearer when
President Omar al-Bashir paid the country an official visit in 2007. Mbeki lauded
Sudan as a strategic partner of South Africa and the two leaders concluded
agreements on defence, economic ties and trade cooperation. On the Bashir government’s widespread atrocities in Darfur, Mbeki was conspicuously silent.
In July 2008 the Darfur saga took a new turn when the chief prosecutor of the
ICC asked the court to issue a warrant of arrest for President Bashir on charges
of genocide, war crimes and crimes against humanity in Darfur. The Arab
League and the AU’s Peace and Security Council wanted the UN Security
Council to stop the ICC action against Bashir in the interests of peace in Darfur.
Mbeki shared this view (News24.com 2008).
Mbeki’s response to Darfur suggests that South Africa’s apostleship was subordinated to other considerations. The old code of solidarity among African
leaders featured, as did the tenet of African solutions for African problems. More
pragmatically, economic factors may have weighed with Mbeki, not the least of
which is Sudan’s abundant oil reserves (Nathan 2008: 5).
Apostleship╇╇ 195
Under Zuma South Africa has adopted a new tone by acknowledging that
continuing human rights violations against civilians in Darfur and the humanitarian crisis there ‘are of such magnitude that we cannot afford to dissociate
ourselves from this ongoing conflict’ (Ebrahim 2009: 4). While South Africa
still took care not to apportion any blame, the International Criminal Court
(ICC) had no doubt about the identity of the main perpetrator of the mass
abuses. In March 2009 the Court issued an arrest warrant for President Bashir
on two counts of war crimes and five of crimes against humanity; there were
no charges of genocide, as in the 2008 application. In July 2009 the AU
Assembly decided that member states would not cooperate with the ICC in
arresting Bashir and surrendering him to the court. South Africa again supported this position. Nkoane-�Mashabane (2009b: 11) in October reiterated that
‘the imperatives of justice should not undermine equally important efforts to
promote lasting peace’ in Sudan. The Director-Â�General of the Department of
International Relations and Cooperation (DIRCO), however, conceded that the
refusal to cooperate with the ICC over Bashir meant that South Africa violated
both its constitutional values and obligations under the Rome Statute and so
harmed its international reputation (Ntsaluba 2009: 4, 6). In due course Zuma
gave notice that if the Sudanese president visited South Africa, he would be
arrested (Nkoane-�Mashabane 2010b: 1). This may not represent a change of
heart on South Africa’s part, but may merely indicate a grudging acceptance of
its obligations under international law.
Equatorial Guinea
The tiny West African state of Equatorial Guinea has been ruled by President
Obiang Nguema Mbasogo ever since the coup d’état that brought him to power
in 1979. Although nominally a multiparty democracy, the country’s elections
have been marked by fraud and irregularities and its human rights record is one
of the worst in Africa. In May 2010 a large group of international human rights
organisations branded Nguema Mbasogo ‘a cruel and corrupt despot’ whose
government resorts to arbitrary arrests, incommunicado detentions and unfair
trials. The human rights watchdogs accused the president and his immediate
family of diverting vast amounts of oil revenue (Equatorial Guinea is sub-�
Saharan Africa’s third-Â�largest oil producer) to their private benefit. Such is the
scale of official corruption that Transparency International recently ranked Equatorial Guinea among the world’s 12 most corrupt states. Nguema Mbasogo’s
government also has to contend with the challenges of a separatist movement
and a government in exile. Early in 2009 the presidential palace in the capital
Malabo came under armed attack (Human Rights Watch 2010: 1–3; BBC News
2010: 1–3).
Unperturbed, Zuma paid an official visit to Equatorial Guinea in November
2009 aimed at ‘strengthening the excellent relationship of friendship and
cooperation’ between the two countries. According to a joint communiqué,
Zuma
196╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
renewed his support for his friend and brother Obiang Nguema Mbasogo’
and the two leaders renewed their profound adherence to the principles of
democracy, respect of human rights, rule of law and good economic and
political governance, which are core values of any economic and social
development policy.
They also agreed on the need to respect the UN Charter and shared a conventional view of sovereignty by endorsing ‘independence and sovereignty of states
and non-Â�interference in the internal affairs of other countries’ (Department of
International Relations and Cooperation 2009: 1–2). In evidently upholding
this€ principle on his visit to Equatorial Guinea – by not questioning Nguema
Mbasogo’s style of government – Zuma was probably influenced by the dictates
of intra-Â�Africa fraternity and solidarity as well as his host country’s oil riches.
Myanmar
Myanmar’s dismal human rights record has been under the international spotlight for nearly 20 years, with the fate of Aung San Suu Kyi taking centre stage.
In the general election of May 1990 Suu Kyi’s opposition National League for
Democracy (NLD) scored a resounding victory, but the military rulers refused to
surrender power to the NLD. Instead, opposition figures were persecuted and
Suu Kyi remained under house arrest – to which she had been confined in 1989.
During this first bout of incarceration she received the 1991 Nobel Peace Prize.
The UN General Assembly, the Commission on Human Rights (and its successor, the Human Rights Council) and the International Labour Organisation
have since the early 1990s repeatedly taken issue with Myanmar’s military junta
over gross human rights violations. In 2005 the Security Council for the first
time declared that it could no longer ignore the wholesale abuse of human rights
in Myanmar. The EU and America have resorted to punitive economic measures
against the military dictatorship. Even the Association of South East Asian
Nations (ASEAN) member states have roundly condemned political repression
in Myanmar, while at the same time pursuing ‘constructive engagement’ with
the errant regime (Geldenhuys 2006: 165–168).
When Suu Kyi was freed from house arrest in 1995 (after nearly six years),
South Africa publicly praised her for her ‘dedicated perseverance in striving for
a democratic dispensation in Myanmar’ and expressed the hope that her release
signalled Yangon’s intention to engage in serious dialogue with the opposition
to normalise the democratic process (quoted by Geldenhuys 2006: 168). Instead,
the military rulers placed her under renewed house arrest in 2000. Her release in
2002 was welcomed by South Africa’s Department of Foreign Affairs as a major
development giving significant momentum to the process of restoring democracy
and human rights in Myanmar. It was wishful thinking: Suu Kyi was again condemned to house arrest in 2003. An evidently disillusioned Aziz Pahad, Deputy
Foreign Minister, described the move by ‘the military government’ of Myanmar
as a ‘blow’ to efforts at achieving national reconciliation and democracy. Pahad
Apostleship╇╇ 197
joined scores of foreign governments in calling for Suu Kyi’s immediate release
and the urgent resumption of talks to resolve the political future of Myanmar
(quoted by Geldenhuys 2006: 169).
Despite Pahad’s critical utterance, South Africa refrained from voting in UN
organs on resolutions concerning Myanmar or making statements in debates on
the situation in that country. The Department of Foreign Affairs in 2006 depicted
this as a principled stance followed across the board. ‘South Africa recognises
that each country has specific issues and challenges that will be resolved only by
participation of all domestic stakeholders’, a policy document declared. South
Africa accordingly took ‘a position of consistent support for no-Â�action motions
where resolutions have been tabled by countries seeking to rectify human rights
issues in other countries’. Where such motions have been voted on, South Africa
chose to abstain (Geldenhuys 2006: 169). Myanmar was one of the cases in
which South Africa applied this combination of moral neutrality and political
inaction, also during its two-Â�year term on the UN Security Council (2007–2008).
It was the very antithesis of apostleship. In a redeeming move of sorts, the
Department of Foreign Affairs in October 2007 summoned the ambassador of
Myanmar in Pretoria to protest against the crushing of peaceful protest by monks
in Yangon (Fritz 2009: 17).
Since Zuma’s became president, more signs of apostleship have been noticeÂ�
able in South Africa’s dealings with Myanmar. In 2009 the new Minister of
International Relations and Cooperation publicly condemned the latest trial of
Aung San Suu Kyi and called for her immediate release. Nkoane-Â�Mashabane’s
deputy also conveyed South Africa’s concern about Suu Kyi’s trial to Myanmar’s ambassador and offered to send a South African delegation to that country
to facilitate negotiations between local political parties (Fritz 2009: 16). When
Suu Kyi was subsequently convicted on charges of subversion and sentenced to
further house arrest, South Africa was swift in joining the international community in ‘unequivocally condemning’ this decision of the Myanmar authorities.
South Africa also called for Suu Kyi’s immediate release and for an inclusive
dialogue between all parties in Myanmar to create the necessary conditions for
free and fair elections there in 2010 (Department of International Relations and
Cooperation 2009).
Conclusion
A modern-�day defender of the faith, like South Africa, assumes a foreign policy
role involving much more than defending a value system from attack. For this
reason the notion of apostleship was proposed, focusing on a state’s promotion
of democracy and human rights abroad. Although the fervour with which the
new South Africa initially articulated this role has since been tempered, its
foreign policy still carries a strongly ethical content. The policymakers keep
drawing on the sources from which the role originally sprang, namely, a combination of internal experience, regional pre-�eminence and global expectation.
South Africa’s actual role performance has been rather mixed. Its greatest
198╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
�
successes
in promoting the gospel of democracy and human rights is to be found
in the AU’s embodiment of universal standards of human rights. However, in
dealing with individual states that openly violate these very norms – for instance,
Zimbabwe, Sudan, Equatorial Guinea and Myanmar – South Africa has compromised its lofty commitments.
Democratic South Africa is of course not alone in facing the dilemma of
trying to be an exemplary state in an imperfect world. Countries proclaiming to
act ethically in the world arena, like Britain and America, are often criticised ‘for
not living up to their own rhetoric’ by being inconsistent and selective in tackling ethical issues written into their foreign policy agendas (Smith and Light
2001: 10). Based on his personal experience in the Carter administration,
Brzezinski (1985: 547) recorded that ‘rigid moral consistency is not possible in a
complicated world’. States typically have to marry judgements of desirability
with assessments of feasibility, often resulting in what Niebuhr called ‘uneasy
compromises’ (quoted by Howard 1977: 375). This has not surprisingly been
true also of South Africa’s interaction with errant states. Yet the Republic can be
faulted for being unnecessarily ‘soft’ in dealing with such countries, especially
human rights abusers in Africa. There is a case to be made for a more robust
apostleship on South Africa’s part, which would require both greater political
will and a harmonisation of the disparate national role conceptions being
pursued.
References
Adigbuo, E. Richard (2005). Nigeria’s national role conceptions: The case of Namibia,
1975–1990. Unpublished PhD dissertation, University of Johannesburg.
Adigbuo, E. Richard (2007). Beyond IR theories: The case for national role conceptions.
Politikon, 34(1),€83–97.
Adigbuo, E. Richard (2008). Defender of the faith: The challenges of Nigeria’s 2007
presidential election. Politikon, 35(2),€223–245.
African National Congress (1994). Foreign policy perspective in a democratic South Africa.
ANC policy document. Retreived from www.anc.org.za/ancdocs/policy/foreign.html.
Aggestam, Lisbeth (1999). Role conceptions and the politics of identity in foreign policy.
ARENA Working Papers, WP 99/8.
Aggestam, Lisbeth (2004). A European foreign policy? Role conceptions and the politics
of identity in Britain, France and Germany. Edsbruk: Akademitryk.
BBC News (2010). Country profile: Equatorial Guinea. 6 May. Retrieved from http://
newsvote.bbc.co.uk/mpapps/pagetools/print/news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/africa/countryâ•›.â•›.â•›.
Bischoff, Paul-�Henri (2003). External and domestic sources of foreign policy ambiguity:
South African foreign policy and the projection of pluralist middle power. Politikon,
30(2),€183–201.
Breuning, Marijke (2007). Foreign policy analysis: A comparative introduction. New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Brzezinski, Zbigniew (1985). Power and principle: Memoirs of the National Security
Adviser 1977–1981. New York: Farrar, Strauss, Giroux.
Carlsnaes, Walter (2002). Foreign policy. In Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse and Beth A.
Simmons (eds), Handbook of International Relations. London: Sage.
Apostleship╇╇ 199
Chambers Twentieth Century Dictionary. (1974) Edinburgh: Chambers.
Chase, Robert, Hill, Emily B. and Kennedy, Paul (1996). Pivotal states and US strategy.
Foreign Affairs, 1,€33–51.
De Waal, Alex (2009). A ceasefire in prospect. SSRC Blogs, 19 February. Retreived from
http://blogs.ssrc.org/darfur..
Department of Foreign Affairs (1996). South Africa’s foreign relations. Discussion paper.
Pretoria: Department of Foreign Affairs.
Department of Foreign Affairs Policy, Research and Analysis Unit (2005). A strategic
appraisal of South Africa’s foreign policy in advancing the agenda of Africa and the
south. Pretoria: Department of Foreign Affairs.
Ebrahim, Ebrahim Ismael (2009). Reply to the budget vote by Deputy Minister of International Relations and Co-�operation, Ebrahim Ismail Ebrahim, to the National Assembly, 18 June, South African Government Information. Retreived from www.search.gov.
za/info/previewDocument.jsp?dk.
EU–South Africa Summit (2008). Database of press releases related to Africa, 25 July,
Bordeaux, France. Retreived from http://appablog.wordpress.com/2008/07/23/eu-�
south-africa-�summit.
Flemes, Daniel (2007). Conceptualising regional power in international relations: Lessons
from the South African case. In GIGA Working Paper Series 53. Hamburg: GIGA
German Institute of Global and Area Studies.
Fritz, Nicole (2009). Presentation at the Human Rights Dialogue Series. Johannesburg:
Helen Suzman Foundation.
Geldenhuys, Deon (2006). South Africa and Myanmar: Beware the politics of perfidy.
South African Journal of International Affairs, 13(2), 161–173.
Guardian (2003). Conscience, nurtured by truth, 6 December.
Gumede, William M. (2005). Thabo Mbeki and the battle for the soul of the ANC. Cape
Town: Struik.
Hernández, Javier M. (2006). The influences of identities on national interests: The case
of Russia’s security policy. Paper for the 47th International Studies Association Annual
Convention, San Diego, California, 22–25 March.
Holsti, K.J. (1970). National role conceptions in the study of foreign policy. International
Studies Quarterly, 14(3), 233–309.
Howard, Michael (1977). Ethics and power in international policy. International Affairs,
53(3),€364–376.
Human Rights Watch (2007). Darfur 2007: Chaos by Design, September. Retreived from
www.unhcr.org/refworld/docid/46f373912.
Human Rights Watch (2010). UNESCO: End alliance with corrupt dictator, 10 May.
Retrieved from www.hrw.org/en/news/2010/05/10/letter-�unesco?print.
Hyde-�Price, Adrian (2000). Reflections on security and identity in Europe. In Lisbeth
Aggestam and Adrian Hyde-�Price (eds), Security and identity in Europe: Exploring the
new agenda. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Department of Foreign Affairs. (2003). Strategic Plan 2003–2005. Pretoria: Department
of Foreign Affairs.
Department of International Relations and Cooperation (2009). Joint communiqué:
Working visit by President Jacob Zuma to Equatorial Guinea, 4 November. Pretoria:
DIRCO.
Department of International Relations and Cooperation (2009). South African government regrets decision of Myanmar authorities to convict Aung San Suu Kyi of subversion. Pretoria: DIRCO.
200╇╇ D. Guldenhuys
Department of International Relations and Cooperation (2010). Strategic Plan,
2010–2013. Pretoria: DIRCO.
Kagwanja, Peter (2009). Cry sovereignty: South Africa in the UN Security Council,
2007–2008. In Peter Kagwanja and Kwandiwe Kondlo (eds), State of the nation: South
Africa 2008. Cape Town: HSRC Press.
Krotz, Ulrich (2010). National role conceptions and foreign policies: France and Germany
compared. Program for the Study of Germany and Europe, Harvard University,
Working Paper 02.1.
Landsberg, Chris (2004). The quiet diplomacy of liberation: International politics and
South Africa’s transition. Johannesburg: Jacana Media.
Landsberg, Chris (2007). South Africa and the making of the African Union and NEPAD:
Mbeki’s ‘progressive African agenda’â•›. In Adekeye Adebajo et al. (eds), South Africa
in Africa: The post-�Apartheid era. Scottsville: University of KwaZulu-�Natal Press.
Mbeki, Thabo (1998.) The African Renaissance, South Africa and the world. South
African Deputy President Thabo Mbeki speaks at the United Nations University, 9
April. Retrieved from www.unu.edu/unupress/mbeki.html.
Mbeki Thabo (1999). Speech of the President of South Africa, Thabo Mbeki, at the
launch of the African Renaissance Institute, Pretoria, 11 October. Retrieved from www.
au2002.gov.za/docs/speeches/mbeki991011.htm.
Mbeki, Thabo (2003). Guardian lecture of the President of South Africa. Nigerian Institute of International Affairs, Lagos, 4 December. Retrieved from http://0-biblioline.
nisc.com.raulib.rau.ac.za.
Nathan, Laurie (2008). Explaining South Africa’s position on Sudan and Darfur. London:
Chatham House.
News24.com (2008). Mbeki, Mubarak oppose ICC, 29 July. Retrieved from www.24.
com/news/?p=pafrica&i=983170.
Nkoane-�Mashabane (2009a). Statement by Minister Maite Nkoane-�Mashabane on the
Name Change to Department of International Relations and Coooperation, 14 May.
Pretoria: DIRCO.
Nkoane-�Mashabane, Maite (2009b). Speech delivered by Minister Maite Nkoane-�
Mashabane during the Ministerial Outreach Programme at University of Limpopo, 16
October. Pretoria: DIRCO.
Nkoane-�Mashabane, Maite (2010a). Budget vote speech of the Minister of International
Relations and Cooperation, Honorable Maite Nkoane-�Mashabane, to the National
Assembly, 22 April. Pretoria: DIRCO.
Nkoane-�Mashabane (2010b). International Relations and Cooperation Minister Mate (sic)
Nkoane-�Mashabane held a bilateral meeting with her French counterpart, Minister
Bernard Kouchner, 31 May. Pretoria: DIRCO.
Ntsaluba, Ayanda (2009). Notes following the Briefing of Department International Relations and Cooperation’s Director-Â�General, 31 July. Retrieved from www.dfa.gov.za/
docs/speeches/2009/ntsa0731.html.
Olivier, Gerrit (2003). Is Thabo Mbeki Africa’s saviour? International Affairs,
79(4),€815–828.
Riddell-Â�Dixon, Elizabeth (2005). Canada’s human security agenda. International Journal,
60(4), 1067–1092.
Smith, Karen E. and Light, Margot (2001). Introduction. In Karen E. Smith and Margot
Light (eds), Ethics and foreign policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
USAID (2009). Sudan – Complex Emergency, situation Report #9, 5 June. Retrieved
from www.usaid.gov/our_work/humanitarian_assistance.
Apostleship╇╇ 201
Vickers, Brendan (2003) From human rights to wealth and security: The discursive
changes in South Africa’s foreign policy from 1994 to 1999. Unpublished MA dissertation, Johannesburg: Rand Afrikaans University.
Walker, Stephen G. (1987). Role theory and foreign policy analysis: An evaluation. In
Stephen G. Walker (ed.), Role theory and foreign policy analysis (pp.€ 241–259).
Durham: Duke University Press.
Zuma, Jacob (2009). Address by His Excellency Mr Jacob Zuma .â•›.â•›. to the Harare Agricultural Society Showâ•›.â•›.â•›., 28 August. Retrieved from www.politicsweb.co.za/politicsweb/view.
Part IV
Select publication list
Bibliography
Walter Carlsnaes
The Concept of Ideology and Political Analysis: A Critical Examination of its Usage by
Marx, Lenin and Mannheim (Westport, CT/London: Greenwood Press, 1981).
Foreign Policy and the Democratic Process (1981). Scandinavian Political Science
Review, 4, 1981, pp.€81–108.
Can Perceptions Be Ideological? Cooperation and Conflict, Vol. XVI (1981),
pp.€183–188.
Ideology and Foreign Policy: Problems of Comparative Conceptualization (Oxford/New
York: Basil Blackwell, 1986).
Energy Vulnerability and Swedish National Security: The Energy Crises, Domestic Policy
Responses and the Logic of Swedish Neutrality (London/New York: Frances Pinter
Publishers, 1988).
The Agency–Structure Problem in Foreign Policy Analysis. International Studies Quarterly, 26( 3), 1992, pp.€245–270.
On Analyzing the Dynamics of Foreign Policy Change, Cooperation and Conflict, 28(1),
1993, pp.€5–30.
Sweden Facing the New Europe: Whither Neutrality? European Security, 2(1), 1993,
pp.€71–89.
Co-�editor (together with Steve Smith), European Foreign Policy: The EC and Changing
Perspectives in Europe (London: Sage, 1994).
Founding editor, European Journal of International Relations, 1995–1999.
Co-�editor (with Marie Muller), Change and South African External Relations (Johannesburg: International Thompson Publishing, 1997).
The Compatibility of EU Membership with Neutrality. In Bill McSweeney (ed.). Morality
in International Affairs: Problems in European Integration (London: Macmillan,
1998).
Co-�editor (with Beth Simmons and Thomas Risse), Handbook of International Relations
(London: Sage, 2002; paperback 2005; 2nd edition, 2012).
Co-�editor (with Helene Sjursen and Brian White), Contemporary European Foreign
Policy (London: Sage, 2004).
Co-�editor (with Philip Nel), In Full Flight: South African Foreign Policy after Apartheid
(Johannesburg: Institute for Global Dialogue, 2006).
European Foreign Policy, in Knud Erik Jörgensen, Mark A. Pollack and Ben Rosamond
(eds), Handbook of European Union Politics (London: Sage, 2006).
Actors, Structures and Foreign Policy Analysis. In Steve Smith, Amelia Hadfield and Tim
Dunne (eds), Foreign Policy: Theories, Actors, Cases (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2007; 2nd edition 2012).
206╇╇ W. Carlsnaes
Co-�editor (with Pernille Rieker), Nye utfordringer for europeisk sikkerhetspolitikk (Oslo:
Universitetsforlaget, 2009).
Associate editor, Encyclopedia of Political Science (Los Angeles: Sage, 8 volumes,
2010).
Co-�editor (with Stefano Guzzini), Foreign Policy Analysis (London: Sage Library of
International Relations, 5 volumes, 2010).
Index
Page numbers in italics denote tables, those in bold denote figures.
Adler, Emanuel 152
Adorno, Theodor 51
African National Congress (ANC) 188
African Union 192
Agency Structure Problem in Foreign
Policy Analysis, The (Carlsnaes) 31
agent-structure theory 31, 32–6, 37, 42–3,
45; Bourdieu’s theories 85–6; and
discourse 72–3; interpretations of
actions 77; plays 73–4; problems of
68–9; rituals 70, 72, 73, 74; social
performances 73–4; social scientists
reflections on 69; Wendt’s discussion of
32–3; Westphalian system 75; see also
European Union foreign policy practices
Agents, Structures and International
Relations: Politics as Ontology (Wight)
37
American Social Science, An:
International Relations (Hoffman) 20
Amsterdam, Treaty of (1999) 83, 159
anarchy 69, 74, 75, 77
Anderson, Jan J. 143
Apel, Karl-Otto 55n9
apostleship 187–8, 189; implementation
192–3; promotion of core ideas 192;
sources of apostleship in South Africa
190–1
Archer, Margaret 32, 34–5, 43n3, 46
Arendt, Hanna 134n7
Ashoka, Emperor 17
Ashton, Catherine, Baroness Ashton 138,
154; see also High Representative for
Foreign Affairs and Security Policy
ATHENA 156
Bailey Conference 22
Baldwin, David 3
Banks, Michael 17
Barnett, Michael 143, 152
Beer, Samuel H. 116
Behnke, Andreas 96
Bennett, Andrew 12
Berlin, Isaiah 62–3
Bernstein, Eduard 59
Bhaskar, Roy 35, 46, 53
bicameral mind 48, 54n3
Bismarck, Otto von 65
Blair, Tony 168–71
Bourdieu, Pierre 82, 85–6, 92n10, n11, n12
Brazil 26
British International Studies Association
(BISA) 22
Broek, Hans van den 90–1
Brook, Elmar 130
Brooks, David 62
Brown, Michael E. 55n6
Brzezinski, Zbigniew 198
Bull, Hedley 20
Bulmer, Martin 4
Burton, John 20
Butterfield, Herbert 20
Buzan, Barry 20, 22, 26, 151
Bynander, Fredrik xiii, 163–75
Campbell, Alistair 168–9
capitalism 18
Carlsnaes, Walter xvii–xviii, 68, 161n1,
186; agent-structure problem 31, 32–6,
37, 42–3, 45; agent-structure
relationship in EU foreign policy 81–2,
100; concept of ideology 9;
Contemporary European Foreign Policy
150; contribution to IR as an academic
208╇╇ Index
Carlsnaes, Walter continued
discipline 15, 21–5, 137; early studies of
conceptualisation 4; editor of European
Journal of International Relations 24–5;
essentially contested concepts 7;
European Foreign Policy: The EC and
Changing Perspectives in Europe xviii;
foreign policy analysis (FPA) 9–12, 10;
foreign policy, definition of 181;
interpretivism 10–11; materialism,
analysis of 8–9; pre-theory 65;
relationship between foreign policy and
international politics 36–7; structural
dispositions 114; tensions between
history and meta-theory 5–7; theories,
classification of 8; understanding of
conceptual analysis 5
Carr, E.H. 117
Cassirer, Ernst 4
causal complex 46
Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) 166
Chayes, Abram 147
child learning 49–51
China 17, 26; European diplomats at the
Chinese court 69–70; koutou 70, 71,
74–7, 78; rituals 70, 72, 73, 74
Code of Hammurabi 48–9, 51
Common Foreign and Security Policy
(CFSP) 131–2, 150–62; ability of EU to
formulate objectives 154–5; CFSP
budget 156; civilian and military
capabilities 157; EU as a multi-level
governance system 152–3; EU as a
security actor 150–1, 153; EU as a
tightly coupled security community 152;
organisational skills, lack of 159–60;
rules, rights and authorities, existence of
155–6; security and integration 151–2;
security policy expertise 157–8; staffing
resources 157; see also research on EU
foreign and security policy
Common Security and Defence Policy
(CSDP) 83, 131–2, 141–3, 150; political
dynamics 143–6
conceptual analysis 3; Carlsnaes, influence
of 4; distinction between levels of action
and observation 5; distinction between
words and concepts 5; essentially
contested concepts 7; meta-theoretical
dependence of theorisation and
conceptualisation 8; theory dependency
7; Weber, influence of 4
conservative internationalism 114–15
conservative nationalism 115
Contemporary European Foreign Policy
(Carlsnaes) 150
context 41–2
culture 68, 69, 78–9
Czempiel, Ernst-Otto 176, 183
Daimler 181, 182
Declaration on Democracy, Political,
Economic and Corporate Governance
192
defender of the faith concept 187–8
Derrida, Jacques 54n2
Deutsch, Karl 20, 152
Diez, Thomas 112, 127–8
discourse ethics 52–3, 72–3
Durkheim, Emile 51, 55n5
Duvall, Raymond 143
Eberwein, Wolf-Dieter 24
Ebrahim, Ebrahim Israel 189–90
Economy and Society (Weber) 4
egocentrism 49–50, 54–5n3
Ekengren, Magnus xiii–xiv, 81–94
emancipatory politics 32, 43n1
emotions 49
empirical analysis and theory 3–4
English language 16
Equatorial Guinea 195–6
Eurasian tradition see Russian tradition
Europe: diplomatic relations with China
69–70; European diplomats at the
Chinese court 71
European Commission 155, 158
European Consortium for Political
Research (ECPR) 23–4; Standing Group
Committee 24
European Evaluation Society 128
European External Action Service (EEAS)
150, 153, 154, 156
European Foreign Policy: The EC and
Changing Perspectives in Europe
(Carlsnaes and Smith) xviii
European Journal of International
Relations xviii, 15, 21; establishment of
24–5
European Neighbourhood Policy 151
European Parliament (EP) 130
European Political Cooperation (EPC) 140
European Security and Defence Policy see
Common Security and Defence Policy
(CSDP)
European Security Strategy 150, 153, 154
European Union foreign policy 81–94,
137–49; agency ability 140–1; agency
Index╇╇ 209
and crisis management 90–2; agentstructure relationship 81–2, 91–2, 138;
candidate countries 139; civil protection
83–4; consultation between member
states 138; crisis management, agentstructure relationship 86–7; crisis
management, theory of practice 85–6;
current situation, description of 138–40;
decision making processes 139; foreign
policy tools 137–8; humanitarian aid 84;
institutional power 143; international
actors in crisis management 88–9, 89;
military power, need for 146–7;
security, political dynamics of 143–6;
structural power 140–1; structure and
crisis management 87–90; trade policy
139; Turkish earthquakes 90–1; unitary
action, lack of 141; see also Common
Security and Defence Policy (CSDP)
Fauconnier, Gilles 54n1
Fearon, James 36–7
Finland 144
First Pan-European International Relations
Conference (1992) 23
First World War 18, 51; aftermath 18–19
foreign policy analysis (FPA) 9–12, 10,
176–85; agency, issue of 35–6;
Carlsnaes’ definition of foreign policy
181; and global governance perspective
181–3; governance, definition of 176–7;
governance structures based on private
authority 177; ideas, importance of
163–4; international regime significance
177; levels of analysis 37–42, 38, 39;
modes of political steering 178, 180;
morphogenetic cycles 35; multinational
corporations, external affairs 181–2;
non-governmental organisations,
external affairs 181–2; relationship with
international politics 36–7; sovereignty
issues 182; transnational governance
177–8, 179, 181; see also European
Union foreign policy
Foreign Policy Analysis (Smith et. al.) 137
foreign policy traditions 109–22; attitudes
of American leaders 112; conservative
internationalism 114–15; conservative
nationalism 115; Hamiltonian priorities
118; Holbraad’s analysis of European
political ideologies 114–15; horizontal
perspectives on European foreign policy
110–11; isolationism 118; liberal
internationalism 115, 117–18;
multilateralism 117; public philosophies
111, 116, 118–19; socialist
internationalism 115; socialist
nationalism 115; US foreign policy
traditions 113, 116–17; vertical versus
horizontal perspectives 109–10
Foucault, Michel 51
France: language 16; security relationship
with UK 141–2, 145–6
Frei, Christopher 60
Future of Power, The (Nye) 146–7
Gallic tradition 17
Galtung, Johan 16
Geldenhuys, Deon xiv, 186–201
George, Alexander 12
German language 16
‘Getting Iraq Wrong’ (Ignatieff) 63
Giddens, Anthony 31, 34, 46, 102n16
Gilligan, Andrew 168
Goldmann, Kjell xiv, 59–67
Goldstein, Judith 163
Graduate Institute of International Studies
19
Great War see First World War
Groom, A.J.R. xiv, 15–27
Guzzini, Stefano xiii, 3–14
Haas, Ernst B. 98
Habermas, Jürgen 52–3
habitus 85, 88, 92n11
Haine, Jean-Yves 117–18
Hallonen, Tarja 90–1
Hasenclever, Andreas 101n6
Held, David 130
High Representative for Foreign Affairs and
Security Policy 138, 153, 154, 155–6
Hill, Christopher 109, 151, 160
historians of ideas 3
history, tensions with meta-theory 5–7
Hoffman, Stanley 20, 96
Holbraad, Carsten 114–15, 119
Holland 75–6
Hollis, Martin 8, 33, 37, 38
Holsti, Ole 64, 111, 112, 186–8, 190
Honneth, Axel 128
Horkheimer, Max 51
Howarth, Jolyon 142
human development 47–9; learning,
individual and collective 49–51, 53;
stages of moral reasoning 51–3
human rights 18, 128, 130, 188–90;
Equatorial Guinea 195; Myanmar
195–6; Sudan 194–5; Zimbabwe 193–4
210╇╇ Index
Hungary 139
Hussein, Saddam see Iraq, invasion of
Iberians 16
Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs,
Institutions and Political Change
(Keohane and Goldstein) 163
Ignatieff, Michael 63
‘Imperialism: the Highest Form of
Capitalism’ (Lenin) 18
India 17, 26
individuals 39–41
Institute for Intellectual Cooperation 19
institution building 15
integration theory 20
intelligence services see Iraq, invasion of
interaction, dynamics of 40–1
International Atomic Energy Agency
(IAEA) 98, 99, 102n16
International Criminal Court 130
international organisations (IO) 177; ability to
act 97–8, 102n11; use of, as arenas 143–6
international politics, relationship with
foreign policy 36–7
international power, theory of 59–62,
66n1; Berlin’s hedgehogs and foxes
theory 62–3, 64; offensive realism 64–5;
pre-theory 64–5; theories of power as
tools 65; see also power
international regime significance 95–106;
agent-structure relationship 100;
compliance, relationship with
significance 95; institutions, regimes and
organisations, use of terms in literature
97–8, 102–3n7; international
organisations, ability to act 97–8,
102n11; regimes as enabling and
constraining institutions 99–100;
regimes, conception of 96–7; regimes,
relationship with organisations 98–9
international relations (IR): as an academic
discipline 19–21; agent-structure
problem 31, 32–6, 42–3, 45; Carlsnaes’
contribution to IR as an academic
discipline 21–5; culture, role of 78–9;
development of 16; First World War,
effects of 18–19; global development
25–6; institutionalisation of IR studies
21–2; international power, theory of
59–62, 66n1; languages, influence of
16–17; see also international power,
theory of
International Studies Association (ISA) 22,
23
International Studies Quarterly 68
internationalism, concept of 114–15
Internet Corporation for Assigned Names
and Number (ICANN) 177
interpretivism 5, 8, 10–11
Iraq, invasion of 154, 163–75; CIA lack of
intelligence 166; CIA, relations with
Bush administration 166; decision to
intervene in Iraq 164–5; defiance of
sanctions 170; errors of judgement in
US intelligence cycle 167–8, 172–3;
importance of ideas to foreign policy
163–4; relationship between Blair and
Bush 170–1; UK intelligence
controversies 168–70, 171–2; UN
weapons inspections 165–6
Jachtenfuchs, Markus 112
Jaynes, Julian 47–8, 49
Jesuits 75
Jørgensen, Knud Erik xiv–xv, 109–22
Josephus, Flavius 66n3
Jung, Sabine 112
Kane, John 113
Kant, Immanuel 52, 53
Katzenstein, Peter J. 101n2
Kelly, David 168
Keohane, Robert 62, 96, 97, 98, 163, 181
Koenig-Archibugi, Mathias 145
Kohlberg, Lawrence 51–2, 55n7, n8
koutou 70, 71, 74–7, 78
Krasner, Stephen 181
Kratochwil, Friedrich 99
Krippendorf, Ekkehart 183
Kuhn, Thomas 7
Lakatos, Imre 7
language 16–17; development of 47–8,
54n1
Language and Thought of the Child, The
(Piaget) 49–50
Layder, Derek 39
League of Nations 18–19
learning, individual and collective 49–51,
53
Lenin, Vladimir 18
liberal internationalism 115, 117–18
liberal nationalism 115
Libya 146
Lisbon, Treaty of (2009) 83, 84, 155,
159–60
Little, Richard 20
Lyotard, Jean-Francois 51
Index╇╇ 211
Maastricht, Treaty of (1992) 155
Mandela, Nelson 188–9
Mann, Michael 20
Manners, Ian 109
Manning, C.A.W. 20
March, James G. 97, 155, 159, 160
Marx, Karl 17, 18, 59
materialism 8–9
Matlary, Janne Haaland xv, 137–49
Mbasogo, Obiang Nguema 195–6
Mbeki, Thabo 188–9, 190, 192; and Sudan
194; and Zimbabwe 193
Mead, Walter Russell 113, 117, 119
Mearsheimer, John J. 61, 64–5, 117
media reporting of military operations
144–5
meta-theory, tensions with history 5–7
Mitrany, David 20
Moral Judgement of the Child, The
(Piaget) 50
moral learning 50–1; stages of moral
reasoning 51–3, 55n7, n8
Morgenthau, Hans 60, 66n5, 117
morphogenesis 34–5, 41
Morrison, James V. 60
Moscow State Institute of International
Relations 23
Mugabe, Robert 193
Muslims 16
Myanmar 196–7
national role conceptions 186–8
nationalism 115
NATO 142, 145, 146
Nau, Henry 113, 117, 119
neutrality 144
Nipponic tradition 17
Nkoane-Mashabane, Maite 189, 190, 191,
195
Norway 140, 143
Nye, Joseph 146–7, 181
Nzo, Alfred 188, 190
offensive realism, theory of 64–5
Olsen, Johan P. 97, 155, 159, 160
O’Neill, Bob 22
Onuf, Nicholas 39
Operation ARTEMIS 83
Oppenheim, Felix E. 5, 6
Organisation for the Prohibition of
Chemical Weapons (OPWC) 98, 99,
102n16
Parker, Charles xv, 95–106
Patomäki, Heikki xv, 40, 45–58
Peloponnesian War, The (Thucydides)
59–60
Pfetsch, Frank 23
Piaget, Jean 49–50, 54–5n3, 55n4
Plame, Valerie 166
pluralist tradition 17, 18
political thought, traditions of 17–19
Politics Among Nations (Morgenthau) 60
Popper, Karl 51
population growth 48
Portugal 75–6
power: institutional power 143; and
legitimacy 129–30, 134n7; military
power 146–7; see also international
power, theory of
public philosophies 111, 116, 118–19
Putnam, Robert 144–5
Rapid Reaction Mechanism 159
rational actions 72
rational choice theory 20–1
realist tradition 17–18, 144
regimes see international regime
significance
research on EU foreign and security policy
123–36; actors’ rationality conception
128–9; bargaining resources 132;
‘Brusselisation’ process 131; collective
action, possibilities of 131–3;
communicative rationality 130–1;
consultation between member states
132–3; cosmopolitanism 125–6, 134n3;
deliberation 132, 134n8; EU as a
normative or ethical power 124; moral
and ethical norms, distinction between
126–7; normativity standards 127–8;
power and legitimacy 129–30, 134n7;
pursuit of norms 124–5; sovereignty
130–1; voting 132
Ricci, Matteo 75
Riddell-Dixon, Elizabeth 188
Rieker, Pernille xv, 150–62
Ringmar, Erik xv, 68–80
Risse, Thomas xvi, 176–85
rituals 70, 72, 73, 74
Rø, Johannes 65
role theory 187
Roper, John 22
Rosenau, James 20, 64, 96, 111, 112, 176
Russia 17, 76
sameness, idea of 16
Sartori, Giovanni 6
212╇╇ Index
Saxonic tradition 17
Schumaker, Paul 116
settings 41
Shapiro, Ian 163
Singer, David 37, 38, 43n4
situated activity 40–1
Sjursen, Helene xvi, 123–36
Smith, Steve xviii, 8, 33, 37, 38
Snyder, R.C. 64
social ontology, historicising 46–9
socialist internationalism 115
socialist nationalism 115
Solana, Javier 138
South African foreign policy 186–201,
187–8; African Union 192; apostleship
187–8, 189; defender of the faith
concept 187–8; Equatorial Guinea,
relations with 195–6; human rights,
promotion of 188–90, 197–8;
implementation of apostleship 192–3;
Myanmar, relations with 196–7; national
role conceptions 186–8; promotion of
core ideas of apostleship 192; sources of
apostleship 190–1; Strategic Plan
2010–2013 (DIRCO) 189; Sudan,
relations with 194–5; Zimbabwe,
relations with 193–4
Southern African Development
Community (SADC) 193
sovereignty 16, 130–1, 182
Spence, Jack 22
Stability Instrument 156, 159
Strategic Plan 2010–2013 (DIRCO) 189
Straw, Jack 170, 172
structuralist tradition 17, 18
structuration theory 32–3, 34, 35, 85–6
Sudan 194–5
Sun Tsu 17
Suu Kyi, Aung San 195–6
Sweden 144
Swedish National Defence College 82
Tenet, George 164, 173
Teutonic tradition 17
Theories of International Regimes
(Hasenclever et. al.) 101n6
Theory of International Politics (Waltz)
36, 60, 61–2, 64
Thies, Cameron T. 62
Thucydides 59–60, 66n2
Tickner, Arlene B. 26
Transformational Model of Social Activity
(TMSA) 35
Treaty on European Union (Maastricht)
155
Turkey 90–1
Turner, Mark 54n1
UN Global Compact 177
Union of Soviet Socialist Republics
(USSR) 18
United Kingdom (UK): international
relations development 19; relations with
China 77, 78–9; security relationship
with France 141–2, 145–6; see also Iraq,
invasion of
United States (US): foreign policy attitudes
of leaders 112; increased academic
parochialism 20; international relations
development 19; power and legitimacy
129–30; relations with China 76–7;
studies of foreign policy traditions 113,
116–17; see also Iraq, invasion of
Wæver, Ole 26
Walker, R.B.J. 37
Wall, Sir Stephen 169
Waltz, Kenneth 36, 60, 61–2, 64, 66n5,
100, 102n17
Watson, Adam 20
weapons of mass destruction (WMDs) see
Iraq, invasion of
Weber, Max 4, 5, 51, 55n5
Weir, Margaret 116
Wendt, Alexander 31, 32–3, 36, 37, 38
Westermarck, Edward 51, 55n5
Westphalian system 16, 75, 76
Whitman, Richard 109
Wight, Colin xvi, 31–44
Wight, Martin 17, 20
Wilson IV, Joseph 166
Workshop on International Relations
(1989) 23
World International Studies Committee
(WISC) 26
writing, development of 48–9, 54n2
Zimbabwe 193–4
Zuma, Jacob 189, 193–4, 195–6
Taylor & Francis
eBooks
FOR
liBRARIES
Over 23,000 eBook titles in the Humanities,
Social Sciences, STM and Law from some of the
world's leading imprints.
Choose from a range of subject packages or create your own!
~ Free MARC records
~ COUNTER-compliant usage statistics
~ Flexible purchase and pricing option s
~ Off-site, anytime access via Athens or referring URL
~ Print or copy pages or chapters
~ Full content search
~ Bookmark, highlight and annotate text
~ Access to thousands of pages of quality research
at the click of a button
For more information, pricing enquiries or to ord er
a free trial, contact your local online sales team .
UK and Rest of World: online.sales®tandf.co.uk
US, Canada and Latin America:
e-reference®taylorandfrancis.com
www.ebooksubscriptions.com