Download The concise argument - Journal of Medical Ethics

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Declaration of Helsinki wikipedia , lookup

Medical ethics wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on July 31, 2017 - Published by group.bmj.com
The concise argument
doi:10.1136/jme.2010.040048
History and consent
This issue contains two papers related
to the historical dimensions of medical
ethics. The first and most straightforwardly historical paper is the short paper
by Selek in which he reports a formal
contract for medical services signed before
the court in Gaziantep, Turkey in 1539
(see page 639). In the contract the
patient’s illness and the surgery to be
performed are described, the fee stated
and the surgeon absolved from responsibility if the patient dies. This contract is
in many ways different from current
consent forms, but even if it only
contains 8 lines of text it still shows that
modern legal ideas about consent have
ancient roots, and that these roots can be
found in many different legal systems.
The second paper by Kaufmann and
Rühli is concerned with the ethics of
research on ancient mummies (see page
608). In these cases there is obviously no
consent to research, but there may still be
ethical issues that need to be resolved.
The authors argue that while we may not
J Med Ethics October 2010 Vol 36 No 10
Søren Holm, Editor
be able once and for all to reconcile the
many different interests that are at play,
we can put in place a reflective process
that ensures that all important stakeholders and all important interests are
identified and reflected upon. A particularly interesting part of the paper analyses
the importance of bodily integrity into
four distinct categories of bodily wholeness and discusses the implications for the
evaluation of the methods by which we
do research on ancient mummies.
Moral conflicts in hospice care
Hospice care is supposed to help terminal
patients to experience a better way of dying
than they would experience in a normal
hospital. As such we might think that
hospices are also places where moral
conflicts are rare, but the study by Salloch
and Breitsamer shows that this is not
necessarily true (see page 588). Based on
qualitative interviews with hospice staff
and volunteers in Germany they find that
moral conflicts occur when the virtue
ethics orientation and the commitment to
holistic care at the end of life that is characteristic of the hospice movement is
confronted by patients who do not accept
that they have an incurable disease or when
there are disagreements among the
patients’ families.
Theory and the teaching of
medical ethics
One of the perennial bones of contention
in the teaching of medical ethics is the role
of moral theory. Should moral theory be
taught, and if so to what extent? In the
JME we have had a number of papers
arguing on both sides of this debate. In the
current issue Ben Saunders suggests that
the debate has, at least in part not been
about the teaching of moral theory as
such, but about whether teaching should
be theory-led (see page 635). He agrees
with the critics of theory that teaching
should not be theory-led in any uncritical
way, but points out that moral theory can
be taught nevertheless. There is nothing
that prevents us from starting with practical cases and then drawing on theory, if
and when it becomes relevant to students.
Such an approach will, he suggests lead to
a situation where ‘., theories are taught
but students do not take them to be the
a and u of moral thinking.’
I think I agree with him.
Teaching professionalism and
scientific integrity
The authors of another paper in this
issue are also likely to agree with Saunders. Jones et al report on the design
and implementation of a problem-based
learning (PBL) curriculum for professionalism and scientific integrity training for
biomedical graduate students (see page
614). The authors explain the rationale
behind choosing a PBL approach and shows
that the opportunities for active learning
that this approach opens were welcomed
by both staff and students. Each part of
a PBL curriculum is fundamentally case
based, but this does not entail that theory
plays no role. In the current context cases
where designed to elicit reflection on the
‘. underlying philosophies for the ethical
practice of science.’.
577
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on July 31, 2017 - Published by group.bmj.com
The concise argument
J Med Ethics 2010 36: 577
doi: 10.1136/jme.2010.040048
Updated information and services can be found at:
http://jme.bmj.com/content/36/10/577
These include:
Email alerting
service
Topic
Collections
Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article. Sign up in the
box at the top right corner of the online article.
Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections
Research and publication ethics (490)
Hospice (121)
End of life decisions (ethics) (344)
End of life decisions (geriatric medicine) (344)
End of life decisions (palliative care) (344)
Notes
To request permissions go to:
http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions
To order reprints go to:
http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/reprintform
To subscribe to BMJ go to:
http://group.bmj.com/subscribe/