Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
9th Conference European Sociological Association Lisbona, 2-5 settembre 2009 Internet and the plot of resentment Guido Di Fraia Introduction The purpose of this paper is to present some of the provisional results emerging from research work on the theme of resentment carried out by Dr Risi and myself at the Iulm University of Milan. The theoretical conceptual coordinates of our remarks may be encapsulated as a constructionist epistemology which does not consider emotions as phenomena circumscribed to the individual and closed within the mind, but as phenomena which, whilst having a neuronphysiological root in the bios, are largely relational issues. Interior responses to experiences that have been lived, emotions are generated in situational contexts that are largely social, starting out from interpretative processes that can be activated only internally and by way of symbolic devices and of meanings that are determined culturally and socially. Being communicative acts and actions, they represent the externalised part of interpersonal relations (Mead ) through which daily life and social reality incessantly produce and reproduce themselves, playing a decisive role in social dynamics (this is, at least, the second premise for our remarks). Setting out from these considerations, the purpose of our work research program is to explore the heuristic potential of resentment regarding a series of processes and social dynamics which characterise late modernity. More particularly, using an analytical perspective that ideally refers to the “political economy of emotions” as desired by Dezin, and considering resentment as a decidedly social emotional experience (a sentiment more than an emotion), the generation of which is inevitable in any human grouping, we attempt to give certain embryonic answers with our work to the following questions. In what way have the structural changes that have accompanied the transition to late modernity had an impact on the processes of the generation and the individual and social elaboration of resentment? Is it possible to recognise in resentment the emotional motor on which certain reproductive mechanisms of contemporary western society are based, defined by some (Lipovetsky) as a society of hyper consumption, and thus also the origin of some of the “sad passions” (depressive experiences, chronic dissatisfaction, sense of confusion and inadequacy, weak planning ability, etc.)? At a more specific level, what macro-economic role may be attributed 1 to online communications and relations in processes of production, elaboration and possible „sublimation‟ of resentment? In order to tackle these points synthetically, this paper has been divided into three parts. The first outlines the phenomenological and structural characteristics of resentment, specifying its distinctive tracts compared to other neighbouring states of being such as envy and jealousy. The second focuses on certain recently developed hypotheses regarding the relationship between resentment and late modernity. The third presents the first results of empirical research currently underway by our work group on the way in which the forms of community and social life that are present on the web contribute to social processes for the elaboration of resentment. Part 1 As with envy and jealousy, with which it is often associated and confused, resentment is a complex and unmentionable state of being, subject to processes of individual and collective removal that constitute its very nature Karstic, that is tending to come to light in a discontinuous and unforeseeable way, its presence alone has been the object of analysis. Brought to light in its macro-social and cultural consequences by Nietszche and Scheler, many decades later it became the centre of attention anew in Girard‟s mimetic theory of desire, only to disappear again until recent years, when renewed interest in the theme has arisen in sociological, anthropological, psychological and juridical fields (Tomellieri, 2009; Tomellieri, 200?? Kancyper, 2002; Ansart, 2002). It is difficult to resist the impulse to see in this theoretical discontinuity not only the selective, non-accumulative overview typical of human sciences, but also to recognise the effect of the features that make up resentment itself, and the removal mechanisms alluded to above. Resentment, being that “impotent violence” concealed in the desire for revenge which poisons the spirit, constitutes part of the negative side that individuals, cultures and institutions tend to hide away, denying its existence, and so relegating it to an unconscious which one cannot liberate oneself of, and with which, sooner or later, one has to come to terms. Every society in every period has worked out symbolic-narrative systems (myth, religion, ideology, etc.) and rites with which to represent, legitimate and give a shared sense to its own architecture of power, and to hide away the violence of the negative side at the base of society itself, through which inequality of power and possession, injustice, suffering, abuse of power, violence and death are produced. To question oneself about resentment from a perspective which is not reductively intrapsychic (concerning the “resented personality” ……) but rather contextual and cultural means to seek to cast some light into the meanders of the collective unconscious. It means looking oneself in the eye 2 in an attempt to understand something of that obscure violence that stirs and moves us from deep within, both as human beings and as a collective group. Resentment is an experience of feeling that is extremely complex and protean and that insinuates itself from below into that which is visible and sayable. When it comes to light, and it rarely does so in a direct way, it manifests itself above all through episodes of a violence that is “excessive” when compared to the conditions and dynamics that are objectively in play (this demonstrating a surplus that has unexpectedly found release). For most of the time, and in the majority of cases, the repressed, controlled energy behind individual and collective resentment follows winding, transverse paths, taking on shapes which, however relevant for interpersonal and social dynamics, are prevalently symptoms, difficult to recognise and to decipher. Already Darwin, when talking about rancour in his treatise on human emotions (rancour is here, forcing things a little, taken to be a synonym of „resentment‟), affirmed that it could not be directly recognised, given that it was not accompanied by any specific behavioural or expressive pattern on the part of the subject, and could thus only be presumed from contextual elements (Bonfigli etc. p. 191??) From a philological point of view, the inescapable reference for any discussion of resentment, with the meaning of resentment, is undoubtedly represented by the Nietszche-Schelerian model. Outlined by Nietszche in the Genealogy of Morality, this model has the undoubted merit of identifying in resentment a theoretical concept which is extraordinarily effective in any attempt to describe the socio-cultural and symbolic processes that have brought modernity into being (Deleuze, 1962). Using an approach in which the socio-anthropological reconstruction of the development of such a sentiment within the Judaeo-Christian religion is carried out at a level of abstraction which doubtless gives a simplificatory outcome, Nietzsche defines resentment as an “impotent hatred”, a desire for revenge which, given the impossibility of its finding relief in any action capable of having any true effect on reality, ends up by poisoning the spirit of he who resents, and polluting his thought processes in a tendentious way. An abstract and dichotomic anthropology is among the basic features of the model that divides social – or better human – reality into two typologies, Masters and Servants. Endowed with desires and an autonomous will, and possessing the force necessary to exercise an active capacity for dominion over the outside world, the Masters are founders of noble morality, immune “by nature” to any resentment. Such resentment represents, however, the inevitable outcome of the existence of the Servant who, lacking autonomy of thought and his own free will, is destined to obey but, at the same time, also to nurture resentful feelings within himself. Given the impossibility to act with its repressed rage, the Servant populace will channel this same energy into a reactive force capable of acting at a symbolic level until subverting the principles on which the dominant moral of the Master is based. 3 The historical result of such a process of overturning values is to be seen, according to Nietszche, in the affirmation of Judaeo-Christian morals, made incarnate in the principle “Blessed are the poor in spirit: for theirs is the kingdom of heaven”. From this viewpoint resentment is therefore mechanistically attributed to a certain typology of humanity whose interior exasperation is imagined by Nietszche as a force that, although reactive, should be capable of triggering cultural processes of great breadth, such as those that have led to the formation of the morals of modernity. Whilst paying greater attention to historico-social dynamics, Scheler substantially picks up on the Nietszchian model only to reach differing conclusions. He too holds that resentment is the product of modern egalitarianism, or better of the modern contradiction between egalitarian thought and the permanence of social inequality, with regard to which individuals find themselves helpless to react, either from a collective or individual point of view. The result of the subversion of values produced by the sense of impotence felt by large masses of individuals would be, however, not Christian religion but bourgeois morality impregnated with humanitarianism and philanthropy. In both their differences and their convergences (Meltzer, Musolf, 2002), what is interesting to note is that both writers attribute to resentment a crucial role in the processes that created modernity, and in the historical transformations between the nineteenth and twentieth centuries (Tomellieri, 2009, p. 25). In more recent years this kind of feeling has been the subject of studies in the sociological, psychological and socio-psychological fields, based on empirical work which, distancing itself from the philosophical concept of resentment (as a feature belonging only to a certain, constitutionally weak class of humanity), has allowed decidedly more specific and analytical definitions of this sentiment (often conceptualised as „rancour‟) to be reached, along with its phenomenological and experiential characteristics Resentment is literally a “re-feeling” of a negative emotion already felt before, from which one cannot liberate oneself. Not by chance the term „rancour‟ (which, although forcing things a little, we may take as a synonym of resentment for the ends of our discussion) derives etymologically from the concept of „rancid‟, referring to something that has kept badly (in this case an emotion). This thing has deteriorated and risks infecting its surroundings and polluting the spirit of whatever nourishes it. From the point of view of dynamics, it is proceeding forwards with one‟s gaze fixed behind, fixed on the negative event undergone which one was not capable of opposing and from the outcome of which one is still suffering. Subject A has suffered (or believes he has suffered) wrong from subject B, a wrong to which he did not know how to, or could not, offer resistance. This episode or situation that continues through time becomes rooted in the memory of the subject in the form of a recurring thought 4 which has a negative effect on his development at an emotional, cognitive and behavioural level. The „re-feeling‟ of the injustice suffered without being able to overcome the „trauma‟ produces a pathetic, resentful, cross-eyed look in he who resents. In one sense, in fact, his gaze remains turned backwards, fixed on the humiliation experienced, whilst in another this potentially malefic gaze is projected towards an unforeseeable future painted in the colours of revenge and vendetta. With any progress blocked by this double check from the feelings, imprisoned in an emotional cage of his own construction, he who resents sees the production of his own thoughts and planning weighed down and confused by this pondering on what he should have or could have done - but did not - to avoid suffering that which he suffered, and by the fantasies of what he will do one day in order to obtain justice. From a narrative point of view, resentment is an aborted story, Whilst the prototypic formula for all stories foresees a protagonist who, acting within a certain context and using certain instruments, seeks to follow certain objectives, overcoming all that gets in his way, with resentment it is the formula itself that stalls, given the incapacity of the protagonist to meet the expectations on him. The sense of inadequacy that psychology recognises as one of the experiences most closely associated with resentment springs from this, as does its unmentionable nature. To declare oneself resentful (or envious) means, in fact, admitting one‟s own weakness, openly declaring that one is not up to it. Resentment, however, has also to do with feelings of justice and with the perception of inequality intervening within social, moral or ethical order. The resentful subject, in fact, often lives the injustice suffered as fruit of an action which, beyond harming him or placing him at a disadvantage, represents an abuse of power and so a transgression of some universal reference value. Accepted this way, it is evident that resentment may represent a positive force capable of contributing to the moralisation of society and history by keeping alive memories of, and condemning, abuses of power that have come about. (Améry, 1987; Risari, 2002). At a level yet more abstract and general, resentment is a triadic socio-relational situation in which the following actors are found. A “victim” A, a valued object or state O, and a third entity B (not necessarily a human being), recognised by the subject as to be blamed for his own lack of success in reaching the valued object. It is also possible to recognise a social reference group outside the triad, from whom the values in play originate and under whose judgemental gaze the dynamics that give rise to the resentment are produced. The fault of B may be the result of his deliberate action, more or less violent in damaging A (an attack, an obstacle), but also the lack of any intervention by B on behalf of A (lack of support), or indeed the result of total indifference on the part of B regarding A and his desires (indifference). It 5 is clear that the role of B may be played by any „agent‟ whatever (human beings, but also groups, organisations, institutions, etc.). Such an agent must be equipped with power (this being understood as the capacity that can condition the possibilities that A may reach his goal) and must be imputable of a “not innocent” fortuitousness regarding the episode at the origin of the resentment. Equally evident is that it is not necessary that B is truly responsible for the humiliation suffered by A when trying to reach his goal, but it is sufficient that A is convinced that this is so. A crucial aspect to consider in order to differentiate resentment from other similar emotional states is that the game played at the table of resentment is a lop-sided one (given that by definition B is more powerful than A, being able to impede the latter in his attempt to reach his goal), and not a zero sum game. This means that the wrong suffered by A because of B is not necessarily transformed into an advantage for the latter. The promotion that the boss offers to a colleague, and which A perceives as an injustice to him, causes B no advantage. To define the formal structure of resentment in such a detailed way should allow us to see more clearly its outline, and thus make us better able to distinguish it from envy and jealousy, with which it tends to be confused and overlain, as much in individual and social experiences as in theoretical treatment. Envy too, in fact, is a feeling with a triangular structure (A the envious, B the envied, O the valued object). The difference, subtle at the level of dynamics but substantial at a conceptual level, is that whilst in the case of resentment the valued object is available “on the market” and A may legitimately hope to obtain it (or keep it), and assert his rights in that sense, in the case of envy it is the recognised property of B, and the envious cannot stake any valid claim to, or legitimate hope of, it. That underlying envy is, at least at a first phenomenological level, not a sum-zero game. It is not a given fact that the popularity or the sports car possessed by B, and object of envy by A, may not be possessed by the latter one day1. Beyond this, on the motivational level the purpose of resentment is that of gaining revenge for the wrong suffered and obtaining justice, whilst the objective of the envious is rather that of reducing the inequality between himself and the envied by the use of strategies that devalue his person or his possessions to the point of being able to destroy them (if it can‟t be mine then it mustn‟t be anybody‟s). It is true, however, that envy and resentment often find themselves united in a single emotional experience that is produced when A interprets the possession of a valued object by B as an injustice towards himself 1 Things are in reality more complex, although it is not possible to go into them here. If, from the level of the infinite objects of value that may arouse resentment or envy, we pass to the more abstract one of aims that orient subjective behaviour with relation to certain macro-ordinators that are common to all individuals (such as that of the need to have a good perception of oneself – the need for self-esteem, the need to generate positive impressions in others – the need for adoption, etc.), we may discover that in reality also envy may take on the form of a zero-sum game. The envious gaze concerning, for example, the beauty of B may in fact derive from the overriding need of A to “be better” than B, or at least “not to be inferior” to B in the eyes of the reference group to which they both belong (and not the specific object of contention). These aims may evidently only be met to the detriment of B. (cfr. Castelfranchi…??) 6 (why him and not me?). This is an injustice for which B himself, or other external bodies (often abstract and illusory, like fortune, destiny, the system, etc.), are held responsible. A promotion which A believes he deserves and which is instead given to B triggers at the same time feelings of envy (towards B) and of resentment (towards B or towards, for example, a system where who you know counts more than what you know). We intend to call “envious resentment” that which has its origins in competition for a valued object in B‟s possession so as to distinguish it from that which is triggered by situations in which the responsibility for the wrong that A blames B for has nothing to do with the ownership of possessions by B. Part 3 Although all emotions have a relational and social nature, resentment, as with envy or jealousy, are states of feeling that are decidedly social in that they have their sole generative source in the relationship with another. The group of sentiments to which resentment belongs may be considered “comparative”, given that they are produced by way of affective-cognitive processes that are connected with the comparison that the subject carries out between his own condition and that of others, in relation to the possession of resources, attributes, qualities, status, fortune and so on. The distinctly social nature of this bunch of sentiments induces one to make hypotheses as much regarding their adaptive function with regard to the evolution of the species as their social functions connected with the unequal distribution of resources within human groups (families, social classes, communities, etc.). It is also a characteristic that suggests the impossibility of imagining human formations freed from resentment or envy. Where two or more human beings live in the same social space, subterranean themes of rancour and envy will be lodged in a more or less intense and self-aware manner. Aware of the potentially splintering, negative energy of resentment and of envy which human cohabitation inevitably produces, cultures have always worked out symbolic devices, ritual practices and institutions aimed at giving voice to, interpreting, channelling and containing such dark forces. These have been devices, practices and institutions that evolved alongside the evolution of the economic and political structures and the historical social forms of human society (Elias, 1988). In archaic, rural societies, for example, characterised by scant resources, reduced social complexity and direct interpersonal relationships, resentment and envy were perceived as ever-present forces that dominated relational and social dynamics (…..speaking of institutionalised resentment), Characterised by symbolic interpretative universes centred on magic and superstition, these societies linked the majority of negative experiences that struck individuals or the community to 7 the malefic energy produced by the envy and resentment of other components of the group. To explain any inauspicious event (from sickness to a bad harvest, to poor fortune during the hunt, etc.) it was brought into a narrative where a person‟s luck and material well-being would have triggered the envy and resentment of others whose evil looks (sometimes channelled into precise magic practices) would be translated into malign influences capable of bringing disgrace to whoever had dared to be or to have more than others. Underlying this type of thought there is evidently a vision of the social world regulated by a zero sum distributive “economic” dynamic (typical of societies dominated by shortages), where the total quantity of any asset whatever (material possessions or good fortune) was imagined to be finite (and limited), and consequently each individual acquisition (of goods, health, power, happiness, etc.) was held to be possible only at another‟s expense (Foster). To contain the resentful rivalry and to repel the danger contained in the malign energy of the resentful or envious look, these same subsistence societies laid down a series of ritual and behavioural practices, some of which survived in rural areas of Italy until a few generations ago, or have remained encapsulated as survivals in customs that still live on. Just to give some examples, one might think of the rules of good manners that advise that one should not boast of good fortune or display one‟s good luck, to dress one‟s children a little less well than one could, to conceal pregnancy as late as possible and to talk about it in a modest way as though it were a misfortune, or, again, not to make compliments and praise the luck or possessions of others exceptionally, this being open to interpretation as an expression of envious tendencies (263). At a more general level, the persecutional and depressive elaborations represent two different and particularly effective, “transcultural” forms for the curbing and social dislocation of resentment (Alberoni). Through the former type of elaboration, the identification of an enemy internal or external to the group to whom to assign the blame for every ill (individual or collective) allows the negative energy and aggressive resentment of individuals to be diverted, whilst at the same time consolidating the ties of belonging and sense of identification that each member has with the group. The process of victimising a scapegoat, as described by Girard at the base of archaic societies, the ideological justification of the majority of wars that have devastated the history of humanity and accompanied the development of national states (Tomellieri), indeed, the growing wave of rancorous and violent intolerance towards immigrants in many western countries, their being blamed as the cause of violence, social insecurity and the lack of work (Barman….) – all of these are examples of the persecutional forms of social elaboration of resentment. The depressive mechanism, probably more “modern” in that it is possible only within the vision of a world which recognises the capacity of self-determination in a subject, is a mechanism through which the 8 subject is induced to take upon himself the blame for his complete negative condition, even when it has social and structural origins. The current widespread diffusion of depressive forms in complex societies is probably linked to this, as is the search for personal solutions to the systemic dysfunctions described by Beck ( ). Emotional experiences and the motivational energy connected with the perception of social inequalities and with the awareness that the abuses of which one has been victim are structural in origin, and also strike other individuals with whom one shares certain characteristics, certainly play a role in the processes of class pretensions and collective movements (Coser, Runciman, etc.). Although there are few specific studies on the role played by the emotions (micro dimensions) on the processes of collective mobilisation (macro dimensions), it is our belief that the interpretative viewpoint for this type of phenomenon should be placed exactly at the meeting point of affective and cognitive dimensions on the one hand and socio-structural ones on the other (Alberoni, ). As noted above, Nietszche and Scheler identified the social control strategies and symbolic dislocation of resentment that came into being in the transition to modernity as having an active, structural role with regard to the evolution of social forms of cohabitation. Thus as far as resentment may be an impotent sentiment, potentially negative in that it is associated with a desire for revenge that may easily take on the form of vendetta, the mechanisms of containment and sublimation that society activates to contain it may give rise to processes which valorise the system. According to some (Tomellieri), the realisation of systems of social protection and the patriotism of modern national states have been results of this mechanism. It therefore appears both legitimate and inevitable to ask from a macro social point of view what the relations are that late modernity has woven with individual and collective resentment. What, in other words, are the effects that the socio-economic structures and concrete forms of life in advanced western societies have with regard to the subjective probability of living experiences that potentially generate resentment? And what, on the other hand, are the symbolic and social control mechanisms of this sentiment? In brief synthesis, our hypothesis, which picks up on and articulates some recent work on the subject (Tomellieri, …. ), is that the subject of late modernity, living in a cultural symbolic universe which transmits to him a conviction that everyone is free, and may with equal legitimacy aspire to a boundless self-realisation, free to express his own desires with regard to the infinite possibilities that the market offers, is constantly at risk of seeing his expectations (often unrealistic) disappointed. As such, more than in any other historical era, he ends up being potentially subject to the insidious growth of feelings of resentment. In other words, it seems to us that the situation in which the late modern subject finds himself is in some ways intrinsically destined for resentment, in that it tends to set formal liberty, which recognises the equal legitimacy 9 of desire for everyone, against the growing economic-structural inequality of effective possibilities for satisfying desire, condemning in this way the great majority of subjects to a lack of satisfaction and a resentful desire of revenge which, though remaining latent, can find no peace (Tommellieri 12). What should surprise us, in other words, is not so much that there is latent resentment beneath human relationships, but rather how it is possible that contemporary society can survive without breaking apart under the centrifugal thrust of the resentment brought about by the frequent frustration of desire that is produced by the incapacity of the system itself to maintain the infinite promises of well-being, self-realisation and happiness that it tends to generate within individuals. To outline at least the fundamental structure of the argument in favour of this hypothesis, we may recall some of the most characteristic features of late modernity, limiting ourselves to their simple enunciation, which seem to us to have a role regarding the dynamics underlying the generation of experiential situations that risk causing resentment, Amongst these we may recall hyper-individualism (lipo) which, by taking to extremes the process of emancipating of the subject from the bounds of belonging (religious, traditional, class), gives to the individual total responsibility for his own destiny and thus for his possible failure. The subject, discovering himself perforce to be free to forge his own destiny, ends up discovering ever more often from direct experience the impossibility of reaching those objectives (of work, earnings, consumerism, etc.) that he had set himself, pressed by a highly competitive context and a cultural symbolic system that lauds the total satisfaction of desire. The very ideology of rampant competition and attention to performance, faced with reward mechanisms that are but rarely based on merit and personal capacity (Sennet), not infrequently winds up leaving dysphoric emotional trails, envious of “those who made it” and resentful for the injustices held to have been meted out. Running parallel to this, economic development in a global context accentuates the differences and social inequalities (at a global level and within each individual country) between an ever-more restricted number of the super rich and the group of the poorer, towards which the crisis of the last few months has pushed a significant number of the middle classes, even in more advanced countries. On the other hand, the crisis of welfare systems that has accompanied the consolidation of modernity has meant a notable reduction in the number of mechanisms of social protection and attenuation of hardship, weakening the social shock absorbers (for resentment). All of this has come about whilst, in recent generations, the consumer society that had become consolidated between the end of the war and the close of the „70s took a significant leap forward to 10 reach what Lipovetsky defined as “phase III” of the system, and thus from mass consumption to individual hyper-consumption. This phase has further legitimised the processes of acquisition and the satisfaction of desire, moreover diffusing the right to luxury, to the superfluous, to high quality brands and to goods and situations of post-materialist consumption. This consumption is marked by a rampant cult of hedonism and by a further privatisation of life and an accentuated acquisition of autonomy by the individual with regard to collective institutions. (Consumption processes certainly represent one of the mechanisms, probably the most important, for the social sublimation of resentment that were brought to light by Gans, amongst others, following on from the Giradian mimetic theory which, however, cannot be entered into here for reasons of space (to continue). Finally, the abandonment of the pyramidical company model typical of modernity (Sennet), capable of accompanying and containing in an almost total way the life experiences of employees and guaranteeing their future, the diffusion of flexible work, processes of delocalisation, the lack of efficient mechanisms for the retraining and placement of unemployed workers, the scant linkage between scholastic-formative courses and work openings, and the ever greater areas of more or less institutionalised, underpaid, precarious work which, particularly in Italy, involve a relevant percentage of intellectual workers – all these are mechanisms that certainly tend to diffuse a generalised climate of uncertainty and a fear for the future, as has been widely theorised and discussed (CITA). However, these also constitute further objective conditions in which painful and frustrating life experiences to come about, lived as unjust (with regard to one‟s merits, one‟s behaviour, one‟s aspirations) and of which the subject may feel himself victim. It may be difficult or impossible to react against these situations, perhaps because of the impossibility of identifying one who is truly to blame and against whom aggression may be directed (impersonal decision-making bodies, supranational and globalised as are, for example, the boards of multinational companies), or those strong institutions through which to channel any possible protest (the crisis of the representational system and a lack of faith in politics and unions), and of symbolic systems and a more general culture of protest (the decline of revolutionary ideology) , and thus they become situations that are structurally “perfect” for the generation of resentment. If it is accepted that the synthesis given above lists some of the socio-structural phenomena typical of late modernity that may be held to be potential generators of resentment, the identification of the mechanisms of control and of symbolic and social elaboration of the suffering generated by this state of feeling seems more complex. Also in this case we shall propose certain relevant hypotheses in a very brief manner. 11 It seems to us that a first structural mechanism may be identified in the amply thematized fragmentation of experience and the subjectivity typical of late modernity…. Part 4 If that which has been all too briefly recalled may therefore represent the theoretical conceptual universe within which our research work takes place, let us now look, in brief, at the empirical work that Risi (Risi, 2008) and I have been carrying out, the main aim of which has been to understand the role played by online communication and emotional exchange within social networks on the processes of elaboration of individual and collective resentment It is our belief, in fact, that the web, and more particularly certain of its social “environments”, may be conceptualised as a socio-technological structure that, connecting individuals, ends up by generating a system whose “emergence” is represented not only by that collective intelligence which has been widely discussed in recent years – beginning from what we might call a model of cognitive derivation – but also, if not overridingly, by an emotional network that enfolds and connects individuals with their own selves and with others. As has been shown by the recent transition to web2.0, over and above a content and “data” from logical discourse, it is relationships and therefore emotions, affection, mood and individual experiences that travel through the web. These seek to be shared by others, as do collective experiences that may become individual. It is our belief that a “web emotionology”, a study of the processes by which such a technologicalrelationship structure allows emotional states to be rendered objective, elaborated and shared, would allow a better understanding to be reached both of the success gained by certain of its environments and usages (we are obviously thinking of “phenomena” such as Facebook, Twitter. etc.) and the individual, relational and social processes of generation, sharing, elaboration and dissipation of emotions. The importance of online communication in the relational processes of sharing and exhibiting emotions and the self to the other, and of the related functions in the practice of elaborating the identity, has already been the focus of recent empirical work (Di Fraia, 2007), whilst the value of the social sharing of emotions, and the role of this activity in mechanisms for attenuating subjective emotional suffering and in the reinforcement of social ties, is known from and supported by evidence from research (Rimè, 2005). Beginning from these premises, the research has been carried out through a reading and qualitative/quantitative analysis of the contents of the posts (around 700) present in 10 blogs, 5 discussion forums and 10 social networks created and/or visited by net users who have in common the fact of belonging to the category of workers with precarious job tenure. The choice of this 12 typology of subject was evidently suggested by the fact that if, as noted above, it is true that job placement represents one of the principal assets around which the process of identity construction, and more generally the concrete life experience of the subject revolves, it is also true that exactly in this field the accelerated evolution of the labour market and globalisation processes have had the greatest impact on broad population groups within advanced countries. Precarious work, in particular, constitutes a working model that is certainly functional within current economicproductive logic, but it is also a work experience of which the “victims” are often the young and well-educated, who find themselves often having to accept conditions of work that penalise their formation and are intrinsically incapable of offering them any guarantee with respect to the future, as well as (and this is what interests us most) being almost always far removed from their expectations and hopes. These are the “ideal” structural conditions for the formation of resentment. Using a narrative type of analytical approach (Bruner 1990; …..Di Fraia, 2004), the interpretative work has been carried out reconstructing the content and textual form used in recounting things and oneself on the web, with the aim of gathering the following from within this communicative and narrative material, spontaneously produced by subjects in posts entrusted to the web; more or less evident traces of resentment, both as explicitly expressed and shared content, and also as the “unspoken” that may be inferred from the enunciative form and contents of the stories told; the prototypical stories underlying the events narrated, and the correspondence (or lack of correspondence) of the elements that make these up with what studies suggest would be the elements that constitute the experience of resentment (both at a behavioural and emotional level), as briefly given above; the functions attributed by the subjects monitored to relational processes of sharing their own negative experiential situation and related emotional states; the more general role that such environments for sharing emotions may play in the performance of processes of “recognition” and of becoming aware of the structural origins of one‟s situation of discomfort, potentially at the basis of actions of collective mobilisation (focussing resentment on a common objective), rather than of the dissipation or sublimation of resentment. From the initial results of ongoing analysis of the collected material, it seems possible to affirm the following. The narrative, communicative and dialogue contents present in the body of texts that has been analysed, taken from blogs and social networks of those with precarious work, contain a large number of stories whose narrative dynamic and explicitly expressed emotional tonality allow them to be classified as true stories of resentment. These in fact trace out the path of “injustices 13 suffered” in the working world, characterised by asymmetrical relationships between the narrator/subject (generally protagonist of the story) and some external entity – which is rarely a person but generally a collective or abstract entity – equipped with powers which, by acting or not acting, prevents the subject from reaching his aims and constrains him to a situation of frustrating dissatisfaction. (Examples of prototypes of collected stories include – “the precarious worker deluded for years by the possibility of a permanent contract”, “the victim of mobbing threatened with the sack if he or she does not do “unpleasant” jobs or work during holidays”, “someone unemployed for years feels unease at having to account to people for a situation that he or she never sought for but had to undergo, often unpleasantly”) The continuation of such situations through time, a structural dimension of precarious work, tends to make the sense of impotence and inadequacy that the subject feels become chronic, a feeling that heavily punishes his or her self-esteem and damages the possibility of planning and undertaking alternative paths. “The unemployed man or woman of over XX feels humiliated because he finds himself in a situation of inferiority as compared to others” (nonholeta.blog.tiscali.it); “The precarious worker feels that he too is considered a mummy‟s boy as he can‟t afford to take out a mortgage, to plan for a holiday or to have children” (anagrafeprecari). This reduced ability to plan ahead is often accompanied by a looking back to the past, as is typical of those caught up in the web of resentment, which appears in many of the stories examined. (“The fifty year old unemployed manager recounted how he thought back on his entire working life, looking for the mistakes that didn‟t seem to him to justify his situation in any way”. “The precarious worker has not thought about the future for many years because he cannot find relief there for his anxiety and frustration, but thinks of the choices he made in the formation he underwent” (http://www.argonauti.it/forum/). Within these same accounts it is also possible to recognise, sometimes put into words in an exemplary manner, the action both of the persecutory mechanism “here it is full of Egyptians with families who nick your work from you” (anagrafeprecari) and of the depressive one that attributes blame and elaborates resentment - “I felt myself to be at fault and began to doubt my abilities in everything” (http://tuttosulmobbing.blogspot.com); “I‟m desperate, pissed off, depressed (…) I‟ve had panic attacks, wept, called myself stupid. I asked myself how I could have made such a choice (http://www.benessere.com/forum/); “I‟ve suffered depression because of discontent at work, precarious work for almost 11 years” (anagrafeprecari). At a verbal level, resentment is very rarely cited as a state of feeling rooted in the stories of precarious work to share with others. Probably undergoing the effects of a social process of removal which has already emerged in preceding empirical observations made by ourselves and 14 others (???), resentment is in fact evoked through the group of emotions that accompany it, in particular by anger, bitterness, shame, and those other dysphoric emotions that derive from the sense of impotence towards an experience that has been lived through, amongst which are fear, insecurity, anguish, solitude and so on – “I am, however, definitely pissed off, very pissed off”; “bitterness, every morning when I see the cars of people going to work”; “there‟s always fear, right from the first change, but it turns into anguish after 50 … the principal hardship is the solitude of being different”. At a more abstract level, an attempt by way of analysis has been made to map the “functions” of the stories entrusted by precarious workers to the social environments of the web, and of the related socio-relational dynamics. Principal among these functions seem, at the moment, to be those which are prevalently of a communicative type: a) expression of one‟s discomfort in order to try to give it form, making it objective in written practices (Di Fraia), and ease it by giving vent to it on the web (“I don‟t know if I‟ll manage to explain how I feel: I have had an anger and a pain inside me for years and it‟s truly difficult to find words to describe them (nonholeta.blg.tiscali.it); b) display of one‟s condition of discomfort in a perspective of sharing and denouncing it (“I wish this space would turn into a cry loud enough to reach the ears of those who are ignoring us” nonholeta.blg.tiscali.it; “to make aware of, denounce or more simply to communicate” generazione1000.blogspot.com; “the moment has come to expose the small and big daily problems linked to this contractual typology!” anagrafeprecari.it). To these may be added: c) the mnestic function of bearing witness and constructing a shared memory (“the blog is not intended to be a debating area for this problem but only a notice board where those who have lived through this situation can leave an account, a memory” (nonholeta.blg.tiscali.it), d) the aggregative function: “the web isn‟t a solution, it‟s true, but at least it‟s an “instrument” (…) that brings together, as much and more than any single group” “if the web didn‟t exist we wouldn‟t be able to talk about our problems and be able to compare ourselves with such a number. We know there are lots of us and we all have the same problems” (generazione1000.blogspot.com). and finally, e) the propositional one, singing the praises of the possibility of starting up collective mobilisation, either within or outside the web, in order to reclaim one‟s own rights “let‟s send an e-mail to Damiano: don‟t be concerned about the increase in pensionable age, think about young people”; “they‟re organising a strike and have started up a blog to talk about the problem, stimulate attention and gather agreement and solidarity”; “it‟s the case to get thousands of pissed off people out on the streets so as to make others aware of the problem, make it visible, otherwise you just don‟t exist”; “strikes come and go, movements don‟t. We need to start up some kind of national movement of precarious workers” (anagrafeprecari). 15 The capacity of communication within the social networks that allows processes of “recognition” and awareness of a common condition on the basis of which to identify oneself with the other, and to stimulate a sense of belonging to a social formation capable of having some effect on reality, is decidedly more problematic: “the person who finds himself in this situation tends not to want to recognise himself as being such. It‟s difficult for someone to say “I‟m unemployed”” (nonholeta.blogspot); “we precarious workers belong to the same category. Our limit is our diversity, our intrinsic plurality. To be aware of this is the first step forward” (anagrafeprecari). At the root of this difficulty there certainly lie some well known components structural and cultural in character, amongst which are: the decline of ideologies capable of transferring individual stories into shared macro-narrations; the crisis of faith in representative institutions in the political and unionist world; the widespread individualist culture driving people toward the discovery of individual solutions to systemic dysfunction, etc. It is reasonable to hypothesise that the intermediary dimension of communication on the web acts on this difficulty of recognition and of the construction of a sense of belonging, generating weak links and sharing situations at a distance (….). To conclude by briefly looking at other elements of the detailed results obtained up until now, it seems to us that we may say that personal blogs and social networks centring on the condition of precarious work represent virtual environments into which subjects tend to pour their own stories and emotions, benefiting from the opportunity to “meet” that the web offers to spatially and socially dispersed subjects (a structural condition of being in precarious work) who would otherwise have been very unlikely to come into contact with each other in any other way. Within these, resentment is frequently evoked and made a common theme by way of the expression of the emotions that accompany it, and of the narrative plots that characterise it. Comparing and sharing with others the discomfort and suffering produced from being in the condition of a precarious worker stimulates the production of proposals for action that could come into being inside and outside the web, in order to draw attention to the theme of precarious work and to bring on motions to claim one‟s proper rights. As far as it has been possible to know by way of the observations we have made up until now, these proposals remain inactivated in almost all cases, however, individual voices which, although saying the same thing as the others, do not manage to come together as a single voice and generate a project destined to produce a result. In this way they end up taking on a ruminatory tone, that is just that of the process that creates resentment, in which the subject who is incapable of, or prevented from, acting in order to assert his rights continues to fantasise on the actions that he could (one day) carry out in order to have justice and see those rights recognised. At a more general level, and in extreme synthesis, it seems to us that we may 16 therefore state that social networks and sharing environments on the web, giving rise to weak, “expressive” communities and allowing emotions to be shared by way of processes of objectivisation (mediated by writing and by the web itself), which end up by generating “distance” between the subject itself and his own feelings, tend to play a prevalently expressive and dissipatory role regarding resentment, facilitating the processes of rumination which characterise its experiential structure. On the other hand, they seem less capable of constituting phenomena of recognition, identification and delineation of common plans which are the precondition for the activation of processes of collective mobilisation, and thus of the reinforcement and focussing of resentment itself. 17 Bibliography Mead, G.H., 1982 . Denzin, N. K., 1990 Alberoni F., 1989 The Individual and the Social Self. Unpublished Work of George Herbert Mead, edited by Miller D.L. Chicago: University of Cicago Press. “On Understanding Emotions: The Interpretative-Cultural Agenda.” in Research Agendas in Sociology of Emotions, ed. Kemper, T.D. Albany, State University of New York Press, pp85116. Genesi. Milano, Garzanti Libri, Bruner, J., 2005 (trad. It. La mente a più dimensioni. Bari, Laterza). Di Fraia G., 2004 Storie con-fuse. Pensiero narrativo, sociologia e media. Milano Franco Angeli. Benasayag M., Schmit G., 2005 (trad. It. L’epoca delle passioni tristi. Milano, Feltrinelli). Runciman W.G., 1972 Ineguaglianza e coscienza sociale. L'idea di giustizia sociale nelle classi lavoratrici. Torino, Edizioni Enaudi. Scheler M., 1975 (trad. It. Il risentimento nella edificazione delle morali. Milano, Vita e Pensiero). Tomelleri S., 2004 La società del risentimento. Roma, Meltemi. Nietzsche F., 1975 (trad. It. Genealogia della morale, Milano. Mondatori). Girard R., 1999 (trad. It. Il risentimento. Lo scacco del desiderio nell’uomo Contemporaneo. Milano, Raffaello Cortina Editore). Coser 1975 (trad. It. Introduzione a: Scheler, M., Il risentimento nella costruzione della morale. Milano, Vita e Pensiero). Lipovetsky, G., 2006 Le bonheur paradoxal, Paris, Galimard. (trad. It. Una felicità paradossale. Sulla società dell’iperconsumo. Milano, Raffaele Cortina Editore,) 18 19