Download Gandhi, Ahimsa, and the Self

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts
Transcript
GANDHI, AHIMSA, AND THE SELF1
(Gandhi Marg 15:1 [April-June, 1993], pp. 24-36)
Individuality is and is not even as each drop in the ocean is an individual and is not. It is
not because apart from the ocean it has no existence. It is because the ocean has no
existence if the drop has not, i.e., has no individuality. They are beautifully interdependent. And if this is true of the physical law, how much more so of the spiritual world!
--M. K. Gandhi, Letter to P. G. Mathew, September 8, 1930
At least six book-length studies and one journal volume have been devoted to ahimsa, but
none of them have related the principle to the ontology of self.2 In his Ahimsa: Non-Violence in
Indian Tradition, the best book on the subject, Uno Tahtinen notes the differences among the
upanishadic, Jain, and Buddhist doctrines of self, but he concludes that these differences are "irrelevant
for the practice of non-violence."3 It seems to me, however, that one's view of the self obviously affects
one's social practices. If individual agency is unreal, as Advaita Vedanta maintains, then it is difficult to
see how a dynamic and engaged practice of ahimsa can be possible. On the other hand, if the self is
real but exhorted to detach itself from other selves and from an unredeemable nature (the Jain and
Sankhya-Yoga view), then it is uncertain how either real engagement with others or ecological values
can be supported. In another work I have argued these points in some detail, and I have concluded
that Buddhism, primarily because of its relational view of the self, is better able to present ahimsa as a
positive virtue in the framework of a comprehensive social ethics.
Gandhi did not have a consistent doctrine of the self--his fervent individualism was always in
tension with his Hindu pantheism--and I believe that contemporary Gandhians should take a middle
way between these extremes. In Section I, I examine the influence of Jainism, Buddhism, Christianity,
and Socrates on Gandhi's view of the self. Section II contains an argument that ahimsa should not
have absolute value, as the Jains imply, but should be made, as Gandhi intimated, an enabling virtue for
higher values. Section III is a discussion of Gandhi's eccentric definition of Advaita Vedanta and
Ramashray Roy's misguided attempt to interpret Gandhi's view of the self in terms of this philosophy.
Finally, in Section IV, I analyze Gandhi's "drop and the ocean" analogy, and I suggest that an organic
analogy would better support his belief in a reformed caste system and his view that individual selfrealization is prior to the salvation of the whole.
Writing to a Burmese friend in 1919, Gandhi said that "when in 1890 or 1891, I became
acquainted with the teaching of the Buddha, my eyes were opened to the limitless possibilities of nonviolence."4 When he speaks of "Gandhi's profound reinterpretation of Hindu values in the light of the
message of the Buddha,"5 Raghavan Iyer sees, more than any other Gandhi scholar I have read, the full
scope of the Buddha's influence on Gandhi. My thesis is that Gandhi's principles of nonviolence can be
best interpreted using Buddhist philosophy.
I
Gandhi's greatest contribution to the concept of nonviolence was to build a bridge, principally
through action and only afterward by thought, between its application for the social good as well as
individual spiritual development. This involved synthesizing Vedic and ascetic views of nonviolence and
making ahimsa a powerful political tool. Gandhi transformed ahimsa's earlier world-denying
expressions into a world-affirming Realpolitik, one that drove an imperial power from India. Gandhi
claimed that ahimsa is not "a resignation from all real fighting. . . . On the contrary, . . . nonviolence . . .
is more active and more real fighting against wickedness than retaliation whose very nature is to
increase wickedness."6 The culmination of Gandhi's philosophy was the principle of "soul force"
(satyagraha), and his main contention was that soul force will always, in the end, win over brute force.
The influence of Jainism on Gandhi was not as great as he or others have claimed.7 His
decision, on several occasions, to fast unto death, given its political motivations, is very different from
the exclusively spiritual goal of the Jain fast-death. In a letter to Gandhi, a Jain phrased the difference
very aptly: "Whereas your view of ahimsa is based on the philosophy of action, that of the Jains is
based on that of renunciation of action."8 Gandhi responded, following the karma yoga of the
Bhagavad-gita, by saying that he had melded renunciation and action into one force.
One might attribute this difference to the resepctive concepts of the self: the isolation of the Jain self
versus the relational and other-regarding elements of Gandhi's Buddhist-like compassion. Spiritual
suicide would constitute the ultimate release of the Jain jiva from the corrupting influences of matter.
On the other hand, a Buddhist, because of a nonsubstantial view of the self, would learn not to crave a
pure self free from matter and would be more concerned about the karmic effects of suicide as the
ultimate violence to the self.
With its flexibility and this-worldly emphasis, Gandhi's view of nonviolence is definitely more in
line with Buddhism. Iyer states that "Gandhi was, in fact, following in the footsteps of the Buddha in
showing the connection between the service of suffering humanity and the process of self-purification."9
Albert Schweitzer concurs: "Gandhi continues what the Buddha began. In the Buddha the spirit of love
sets itself the task of creating different spiritual conditions in the world; in Gandhi it undertakes to
transform all worldly conditions."10 Gandhi said that the Buddha was the greatest teacher of ahimsa
and that the "Buddha taught us to defy appearances and trust in the final triumph of Truth and Love."11
Like the Buddhists, Gandhi believed that ashimsa without compassion is nothing, just as gold is an
amorphous material without goldsmith's artistic shape or the root is nothing without the magnificent
tree.12 This means that for both Gandhi and Buddhism ahimsa is an enabling virtue in the context of a
comprehensive social ethics.
Gandhi actually allowed many exceptions to ahimsa, based on very realistic and pragmatic
considerations, exceptions that scandalized many Hindus and Jains. His view is summed up in the
surprising qualification that "all killing is not himsa,"13 and his equally provocative imperative that it is
better to fight an aggressor than to be a coward. In contrast to the Jain position, Gandhi's ahimsa is
reactive and flexible not passive and absolute. Throughout October 1928, Gandhi carried on a lively
debate with various respondents in Young India. Gandhi defended his decision to euthanize an
incurable calf, and even went on to list the conditions for human euthanasia that do not violate ahimsa.
He also thought that tigers, snakes, and rabid dogs might have to be killed if they threaten human life.
The vow of ahimsa is indeed absolute, but the exigencies of human finitude force us, tragically, to
violate this vow every day. Unlike the casuistry of the Vedic tradition, which somehow transformed the
himsa of animal sacrifice or military conquest into the highest forms of ahimsa, Gandhi insisted that we
must accept all the injury we do as culpable.
In a response to queries about apparent inconsistencies--e.g., holding to advaita and dvaita at
the same time--Gandhi answered that he believed in Jain view of the many-sidedness (anekantavada)
of reality, and that his "anekantavada is the result of the twin doctrine of satya and ahimsa."14 If one
thinks of Gandhi's view of relative truth and how this would preclude one thinking ill of others with
differing beliefs, then the alliance with Jain anekantavada is a natural one. In the same passage Gandhi
continues: "Formerly I used to resent the ignorance of my opponents. Today I can love them because I
am gifted with the eye to see myself as others see me and vice versa."
Although the practical effects of such a view are obvious and salutary, it is, I believe,
philosophically unsatisfactory. Ironicly, anekantavada does not seem to have prevented Jains from
holding a rather one-sided dualism, from imputing perfect knowledge to their Tirthankaras, and giving
absolute value to ahimsa. Rather than an extremely loose "I am everything" position, I suggest that an
early Buddhist agnosticism, using what I call a "neither/nor" dialectic, would have better served Gandhi's
purposes.15 Buddhist agnosticism led to a "contextual pragmatism," a phrase David Kalupahana uses to
describe early Buddhist ethics,16 but it would also be an appropriate label for Gandhian ethics as well.
Gandhi's view of the self is an interesting amalgam of the Socratic daimon, the Jain jiva, and
the upanishadic atman. Unlike the Jains, the Vedantic Gandhi viewed the ideal self as inextricably
bound up in its relations with others and society. But Jain individualism, most likely learned from
Raichand, may have persuaded Gandhi to revise Vedanta in a significant way. (Gandhi claimed that
Raichand, a diamond merchant and early intellectual friend, was just as much an influence on him as
Tolstoy and Ruskin.) Although nominally a Jain, and taken by some even to be the 25th Tirthankara
(even Raichand indulged the thought), Raichand's view of the soul is much like Gandhi's: a mix of
Jainism, Vedanta, and Vaishnavism.
The Raichand connection alerts us not to think of Advaita
Vedanta every time Gandhi uses the word atman. When Gandhi says that "atman can be liberated
only by itself," D. K. Bedekar is convinced that, because of Raichand's view that atman is the individual Jain jiva, this statement could be read as: "true autonomy of the human spirit can only be
attained by the human mind which breaks through snares and repressions."17 Consistent with the thesis
of this essay, Gandhi and Raichand parted ways on the question of social involvement, with Raichand
advocating and living strict disengagement from the world. The influence of Raichmand can help us
appreciate, but not condone, Gandhi's relative ease in affirming both individualism and pantheism at the
same time.
Regarding the self, one might think that Christianity must have influenced Gandhi's views.
Except for using the phrases "special creation of God" and "image of God,"18 this does not seem to
have been the case. Iyer contends that the principal western influence on Gandhi was Socrates, from
whom he derived a view of an inviolable and fiercely independent conscience. (Gandhi translated
Plato's Apology into Gujarati.) In an impressive two-page analysis, Iyer demonstrates that there is no
Indian equivalent to Socrates' daimon,19 an "inner voice" that claims, as Gandhi said often during his
campaigns, an authority higher than the laws of the land.
Iyer may be correct on this point, but it is not very clear if Gandhi's conscience is consistently
Socratic. One passage on Gandhi's "Inner Voice" contains an odd mix of popular Christianity and
situation ethics: "The 'Inner Voice' may mean a message from God or from the Devil, for both are
wrestling in the human breast. Acts determine the nature of the voice."20 Another passage gives
Gandhian conscience an infallible divine sanction, independent of reason or result: "For me the Voice of
God, of Conscience, of Truth or the Inner Voice . . . mean one and the same thing . . . . For me the
Voice was more real than my own existence. It has never failed me, and for that matter, any one
else."21
Bedekar contends that, when searching for a word for conscience, Gandhi deliberately avoided
the word atman and instead chose antaratman. Bedekar offers his own translation from Gandhi's
autobiography: ". . . But so long as I have not directly experienced this truth, till then that which my inner
self (antaratman) counts as true, that which is only conceived by me as true, will be counted by me as
my support, my beacon, as the foundation for the course of my life."22 This passage, besides confirming
conscience as the highest authority, also reveals a corollary maxim: as absolute truth is not available to
humans, we must act on the finite truth we find in ourselves. It also supports the first view of pragmatic
conscience above and the contextual pragramtism discussed previously.
Gandhi's commitment to individual autonomy was so strong that he unfortunately resisted the
relational and social self he found in Hegel and Marx, a position that has now been confirmed and
reformulated by 20th Century thinkers as diverse as George Herbert Mead, Martin Heidegger,
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Martin Buber. It is truly ironic that the loss of individual freedom that
Gandhi feared in Hegel is immeasurably greater in the Advaita Vedanta that he unwisely affirmed. We
shall return to this issue in Section III.
II
The ancient view of a sympathetic continuum in which all things are internally related is one that
the new ecological consciousness has rediscovered and affirmed. It also provided the basis for the Jain
view of the equality of all souls. In the Jain Uttaradhyayana Sutra ahimsa is defined as being "equalminded to all creatures and regard<ing> them as one's own self. . . ."23 Compared to Hinduism and
Buddhism, where there is a hierarchy of consideration (viz., higher "minded" creatures have priority
over the lower),24 Jainism attempts to enforce a strict egalitarianism regarding the objects of injurious
action. Simply put, every life unit (jiva) has equal value. Therefore, Jain ahimsa is based on the
equality and universal kinship of all souls.
This egalitarianism is a great Jain achievement, but its formulation is questionable. First, every
Jain jiva, just as every Sankhya purusha, is distinct and separate from every other, so a Jain cannot,
strictly speaking, regard another self as her "own self." Second, sympathy and reciprocity, along with
equality, must be necessary conditions for ahimsa. I believe that true sympathy and reciprocity are
possible only in a system of internal relations. Jain atomism, in so far as it pertains to personal salvation,
is based on external relations, i.e., the possibility of the soul to become completely independent from
everything else in the cosmos. A Jain may, theoretically, be able to recognize another soul as equal; but
it is difficult to see, given the Jains' insistence on absolute independence of the liberated soul,25 how
souls can be truly sympathetic ("feeling with" is the literal meaning) with one another. In Buddhism, on
the other hand, we find that relatedness and interdependence are the very essence of reality, so that
there is a near perfect match between ontology and ethics.
It is important to note that the virtue of compassion requires sympathy as an enabling virtue. It
is significant that N. D. Bhargava, a Jain philosopher, defends the negative formulation of ahimsa,
because "if we speak of love, we can <only> think of one form or the other of attachment. . . ."26 (To
be fair, Bhargava does insist that the use of the negative formulation does not mean that the Jain should
not love.) Bhargava is certainly correct about the dangers of self-centered love, but his extreme caution
on this point again reveals the radical nature of the Jain approach. By removing the self from its social
and ecological relations, one can obviously remove most of the dangers of attachment and the injury
that necessarily follows. But one also risks another danger: alienating people from one another and
removing the content and meaning of a whole range of virtues that are arguably more important than
ahimsa itself. Both Gandhi and the Buddha believed that without compassion ahimsa was not worth
anything at all.
When Bhargava states that ahimsa is "the intrinsic nature of man," he seems to imply that
ahimsa has absolute value. Gandhi appears to agree with Bhargava when he writes, in the words of
Vedantic absolutism, that "ahimsa is the very nature of the atman."27 More frequently, however, he
implies that ahimsa is a virtue that must be attained, and he claims that it is a means to a higher end,
usually Truth or God.28 In his interpretation of the Gita, Gandhi connects ahimsa with selfless action
(anasakti), and ahimsa is "a necessary preliminary. . . included in. . . <but> does not go beyond"
anasakti.29 Resisting the natural temptation to absolutize it, Gandhi has ascertained the proper place of
ahimsa among the virtues. Ahimsa begins in self-restraint, self-purification, and selflessness and ends
in love and compassion.
Making ahimsa a disposition rather than the essence of the soul preserves the essential element
of freedom. Gandhi frequently spoke of the animal side of human nature, and how one must struggle to
choose violence over nonviolence. If we are nonviolent by nature, then we cannot be praised for
choosing peaceful actions. On the other hand, we cannot be completely devoid of a disposition for
noninjury, for, as Gandhi says, "means to be means must always be within our reach."30 (One is
reminded of Mencius' view that the virtues exist as potentials within the soul; and, like seeds, they must
be nurtured for the good life to flower.) Furthermore, Gandhi frequently reminds us that true ahimsa
towards an attacker must combine physical nonretaliation with love and compassion. (In other words,
mere passivity without the proper disposition is not necessarily ahimsa.) Therefore, ahimsa must be a
means to the end of the spiritual life, not an end in itself. The true proponent of nonviolence would hold
that only life (Gandhi prefers Truth or God) has intrinsic value, and ahimsa obviously is the penultimate
means of preserving life.
III
In his book Self and Society: A Study in Gandhian Thought, Ramashray Roy uses the
Catholic philosopher Jacques Maritain to elucidate Gandhi's concept of self. Roy's exposition is clear
and insightful and he introduces the concept of the relational self very effectively. Here is a sample of
Roy's summary of Maritain's view:
<Maritain> considers freedom as self-activity, autonomy and transcendence of
objective determination in which the conception of community happens to be an integral
part of the human psyche and therefore individuality and sociality become mutually
supportive.31
Roy also interprets Gandhi as an Advaitin, so it cannot be correct for him to say that "Gandhi's
conception of the self is no different from Maritain's concept of person."32 Gandhi's position should
have been more like Maritain's, but the texts reveal a radical individualism at odds with Maritain or a
pantheism that swallows up the individual.
The Vedantic Gandhi is a pantheist concerning the relationship of God and the world. The
Advaitin, as John White has reminded us,33 is not a pantheist, but a transcendental monist. For a
pantheist God and the world are identical, but an Advaitin believes that Brahman completely transcends
a fully derivative and separate world. Like a good pantheist, Gandhi constantly identifies God, the
world, and life, and he rarely says that the world is unreal. He instinctively realized how incompatible
such a view would be for his activist philosophy of nonviolence. If the world of constant change and
social engagement is ultimately an illusion, Gandhi's dynamic ahimsa cannot find support in Advaita
Vedanta.
An effective way of conceiving absolute monism is the prism analogy. If Brahman is white light,
and the color spectrum is the phenomenal world, then the prism that refracts the light stands for
ignorance. If one eliminates ignorance, then one can see that everything is just an undifferentiated one.
Due to ignorance, the world and its qualitative differences have a derivative reality only. Realizing the
identity of Atman and Brahman is like waking up from a dream and discovering that those images were
only fleeting agitations of the mind.
In the article cited above, John White has offered a criticism of Advaita Vedanta that goes very
nicely with the prism analogy. If Shankara assumes that some people are enlightened, while many
others remain in ignorance (which he must obviously hold), then clearly Shankara's transcendental
monism is untenable. The world will continue to exist for the unenlightened, but somehow it has ceased
to exist for the liberated ones. (As White points out, the only way that the Advaitin can answer his
argument is to deny the validity of the law of contradiction.) The result is that Shankara's alleged
nondualism is, at least until the liberation of all souls, a transcendental dualism, roughly similar to
Christian orthodoxy. Furthermore, it means that, if some selves are liberated and some are not, there
must also a real plurality of souls--i.e., many different soul-prisms refracting their own perspectives of
the world.
Gandhi declares allegiance to Advaita Vedanta, but he only interprets it to mean the unity of
God and humans:
I believe in the rock-bottom doctrine of Advaita and my interpretation of Advaita
excludes totally any idea of superiority at any state whatsoever. I believe implicitly that
all men are born equal. All . . . have the same soul as any other.34
Gandhi, like Shankara, also extends this unity to "all that lives."35 Everything in the universe contains
atman, and "ahimsa is the very nature of atman," so Gandhian nonviolence is not only ecological, but
also cosmic in scope. Gandhi's pantheism, however, resacralizes the world, while Sankara's
transcendental monism desacralizes it.
Roy states that Gandhi's commitment to Advaita Vedanta allows him to have "a sense of
relatedness with other determinate beings. . . which, in turn, manifests itself in compassion, the ability to
be affected by the suffering of others."36 The problem with this statement is that Shankara believed that
relations and determinations are ultimately unreal, which means that suffering is also illusory. Most
forms of pantheism, especially the personalistic panentheism of Ramanuja and process philosophy, do
affirm real differences within a unitary cosmos. Given Gandhi's love for the Bhagavad-gita, and the
fact it does support the plurality of souls and embodies a strong personal theism, he should have preferred this view over Advaita Vedanta. (After all he did come from a Vaishnava family.)
The concept of a permanent self underlying the phenomenal self is one idea that Gandhi does
sometimes appropriate from the upanishadic tradition. Roy supports this view of self in his retelling,
from the Panchatantra, the parable of the tiger cub.37 One day a tiger, while planning an attack on a
herd of goats, saw a tiger cub among them. The tiger took the cub to a pond so that he could see in his
own reflection that he was not a goat. After some adjustment the tiger cub eventually realized his true
predatory nature. Even though brought into the greatest dramatic relief by this story, Roy does not
seem to realize the negative implications of the permanent self for the practice of ahimsa. He should
have used recent experiments that have shown that "aggressive" monkeys, raised from birth with
"pacifist" monkeys, learn the nonviolent behavior of their adopted parents and siblings.38
After explaining this story in terms of the unchanging atman, Roy inexplicably turns to Gandhi's
view that, although we have an animal nature, we can tap our spiritual natures and learn to become
nonviolent. Interestingly enough, Gandhi uses the same story (substituting a lion for the tiger and sheep
for goats), but he clearly distinguishes animals from humans, created in the image of God, who are free
and obligated to change their animal natures.39 Gandhi explicitly connects "the capacity of nonviolence"
with a rejection of "the theory of the permanent inelasticity of human nature."40 This means that Gandhi
should have rejected the Atman of the Upanishads, and all other Indian views of the self, because none
of them, except the Buddhist, offers either the agency or "elasticity" that Gandhi required. Ironicly, the
tiger cub story is not compatible with any of the Indian selves, because the spiritually pure and empty
atman, jiva, and purusha are, strictly speaking, neither predatory nor not predatory.
One of the most momentous discoveries in modern social thought-- beginning with Marx,
culminating in Sartre, and confirmed in studies of feral children--is that human beings have no "nature."
(This is "no nature" in the sense of nonsubstantiality and potentiality, not "no nature" in the sense of a
fully actualized, but empty spiritual substance.) In their concepts of no-self (anatman) and nosubstance (anitya), the Buddhists anticipated this revolutionary insight. Studies of feral children have
shown that the so-called human "essence" is so malleable and so vulnerable that children raised without
the benefit of parents and normal socialization are reduced to a state, sadly enough, lower than most
animals. All things being equal, weaned puppies and kittens grow up to be well functioning cats and
dogs, but a weaned child left completely to its own devices descends into an abyss of sensory
deprivation and debilitating dysfunction.
IV
Gandhi elucidated his pantheism with a beautifully expressed "drop and the ocean" analogy that
introduces this essay. Let us look at a similar passage before assessing the merits of this analogy for the
self-world problem.
The ocean is composed of drops of water; each drop is an entity and yet it is a part of
the whole; 'the one and the many.' In this ocean of life, we are little drops. My doctrine
means that I must identify myself with life. . . . that I must share the majesty of life in the
presence of God. The sum-total of this life is God.41
This last sentence identifying God and life, something that Shankara never did, is the most succinct
statement of Gandhian pantheism. Gandhi is certainly not the first to use water analogies to explain
pantheism, so the criticism that follows is not solely directed at him.
The positive element of Gandhi's analogy is that he attempts to uphold individuation. Gandhi
instinctively knew that political activism without individual agency is simply not possible. It is also true
that any body of water is made of individual, but interdependent, molecules of water that offer a rough
analogue of a community of persons. The problem is that individual water molecules are not
perceptible, so the individual is dissolved in the whole. Except for rain storms and turbulent seas,
separate individuation of the sort that persons experience in society is not found in water drops. Finally,
if the analogue of the ideal state is a perfectly calm sea, there would be no significant differentiation at
all. This analogy ultimately fails, for it does not present enough differentiation or qualitative difference.
Gandhi is certainly correct to say that "the drop also has the essence of the ocean, so it is no small
thing,"42 but the content of the water is a "small thing" compared to the rich diversity of life both in and
out of the ocean itself.
Spinning thread from a mass of cotton is yet another analogy of the self-world relation to which
Gandhi alluded and actually practiced everyday. He was fond of quoting a saying from Akha, a
medieval Gujarati saint: "Even as the thread spins out so be your life. Do what you may and receive the
grace of Hari." This analogy is better than the water drop image. The individual thread is clearly
separate from its origin, and its connection to that origin (for Akha it is Vishnu) is equally clear. (We
may think of the individual threads taking on various colors to symbolize qualitative differences.)
Bedekar sums up the implications of this metaphor: ". . . the image evokes in Gandhi's modern mind a
life-project of unrepressed and continuous activity leading one to an awareness of one's own being."43
Again the analogy has its problems: thread is woven into cloth, and it, just like the water drop, is lost in
the whole.
Gandhi's statement that "corporate growth is therefore entirely dependent upon individual
growth"44 implies two concessions: (1) that his adoption of Advaita Vedanta was ill-advised; and that
(2) the drop and thread analogies do not support such a crucial role for the individual. This passage
suggests another analogy for the self-society relation, viz., that of a living organism. Individuals are like
bodily organs, each with their own identity and function and each contributing to the life of the whole.
This model also keeps the Socratic Gandhi from falling into the fallacy of social atomism--personorgans separating themselves, by radical acts of conscience and protest, from the body politic.
The principal objection to this analogy is that it is hierarchical and authoritarian--giving, for
example, more value and authority to the brain than to the lowly gall bladder or feet, the loss of which a
person can survive. Gandhi, comparing organs of the body to the four castes, disagrees: "Is the head
superior to the arms, the belly and the feet, or the feet superior to the other three? What will happen to
the body if these members quarrel about rank?"45 One might well answer "Yes" to the first question
and strongly advise the lower parts to obey the brain. If the brain did not outrank the rest of the organs,
occasionally suppressing the actions of errant members, then Gandhi's ahimsa would never be
possible. Eschewing the hierarchy of the body, Gandhi's ideal of an egalitarian body politic is the
ashram, where, as I personally witnessed in Pondicherry, people, for no salary, were happily doing
everything from washing dishes to speculating on Aurobindo's philosophy. Perhaps this is the way in
which we ought to look at Gandhi's controversial support for a reformed caste system. "Caste" he
explains, "does not connote superiority or inferiority. It simply recognizes different outlooks and
corresponding modes of life."46 But if Gandhi means something more rigid--something like the tiger cub
locked into his role--then Gandhi's defense of varna as true to the "laws of Nature" is more problematic.47 The following passage is typical of this more conservative view:
Some people are born to teach and some to defend, and some to engage in trade and
agriculture and some to manual labor, so much so that these occupations become
hereditary. The Law of Varna is nothing but the Law of Conservation of Energy. Why
should my son not be a scavenger if I am one?48
Gandhi's view here is completely consonant with the hierarchical body analogy, but it also here where
most of us want to break with it. The philosophers at Pondicherry, I was told, sometimes wash dishes
to clear their heads. In the human body, however, the liver or other organs have no such liberty or
flexibility--nor presumably does Gandhi's scavenger who might want to become a philosopher.
The more Roy expounds on the ideal relationship of the self and society, the more it becomes
clear that his preference, Advaita Vedanta, is not the correct ontological base. Shankara's philosophy
does not allow us, as Roy rightly proposes, to extend "individuality in a way that all such extensions,
while preserving the uniqueness, autonomy and reality of individuality, converge in a way that produces
a viable social order subserving the good of all."49 After such a cogent description of plural but
relational selves, it is disheartening to find Roy lapsing back into absolute monism:
the prior existence of a centre and all particulars are thought to be its manifestation.
This centre manifests in the particulars which, in turn, are seen to be reflecting in it. . . .
And it is this commonality that constitutes the ground for the self to treat others as distinct but not different. It is this shareability in a commonality that constitutes the
foundation of sociality.50
In Advaita Vedanta, individuals are, strictly speaking, neither distinct nor different. Roy's statement is
closer to a holographic analogy, anticipated beautifully in the story of Indra's pearls. Each holograh is
indeed a distinct piece, but it is not different from the whole. This produces, however, a rather bland
view of sociality--almost like the drops in the ocean--each individual person, by analogy, essentially no
different from the other.
Roy introduces George Herbert Mead's view that our evolving selves are constituted in
dialogue with "significant others." Roy complains that the most we can get from Mead's dialectical
model is a partial sociality, "which divides the world into the near and dear ones, and those who either
do not count, or count only marginally."51 Roy contends that only the universal egalitarianism of Advaita
Vedanta can overcome these divisions. But what if Shankara was wrong, as I believe he was, about
the illusory nature of qualitative differences and the ultimate unreality of selves in society?
Roy's use of the Confucian model (which is not compatible with Vedanta as he implies) offers
him a way out of Mead's dilemma. The extension from "near and dear" to the "far and alien" is made by
sages and leaders such as Confucius, the Buddha, Ashoka, and Gandhi. Roy does not seem to
appreciate the emphasis that Gandhi placed on human finitude and its limitations. It is certainly not unGandhian to conclude that the best that the rest of us can hope for is to emulate the sages through a
process of intensive moral education focusing on the ideals of compassion and nonviolence.
If the equality of all souls is our goal, then, returning to analogies of the self-world relationship, a
revised prism analogy is preferable over the living body metaphor. In contrast to Advaita Vedanta, the
prism no longer stands for an ignorance that must be removed, but a permanent window on reality that
refracts our own perceptions of the world. Following Ramanuja, this aperture of the soul remains for all
incarnations and after liberation as well. Finally, the revised analogy still confirms the validity of mystical
experiences: through spiritual exercise soul-prisms are able to make themselves, momentarily, transparent to the One.
ENDNOTES
1. I want to thank Dr. Rashmi Sudha Puri and Dr. Ashok Rattan of the Department of Gandhian Studies at Panjab
University for helpful comments and for graciously aiding me in locating research materials.
2. Shree Chand Rampuria, The Cult of Ahimsa: A Jain View-Point (Calcutta: Sri Jain Setamber Terapanthi
Mahasabha, 1947; Atulya Ghosh, Ahimsa and Gandhi (Calcutta: Congress Bhawan, 1954); George Kotturan,
Ahimsa: Gautama to Gandhi (New Delhi: Sterling Publishers, 1973); Koshelya Walli, The Conception of Ahimsa in
Indian Thought According to the Sanskrit Sources (Varanasi: Bharata Manisha, 1974); Unto Tahtinen, Ahimsa:
Non-Violence in Indian Tradition (London: Rider and Company, 1976); Indu Mala Ghosh, Ahimsa: Buddhist and
Gandhian (Delhi: Indian Bibliographies Bureau, 1988). There is also a special issue of Journal of Dharma 16:3 (JulySeptember, 1991) devoted to ahimsa. Nathaniel Altman's Ahimsa: Dynamic Compassion (Wheaton: Theosophical
Publishing House, 1980) is just an anthology of materials relating to nonviolence.
3. Tahtinen, op. cit., p. 44. He argues that the inconsistencies among the three views can be overcome by moving
from ontology to axiology, where Vedantist totality is seen as "an ideal to be observed in action, not as a fact of
reality" (ibid.) Tahtinen himself realizes that this is not the view of Vedanta, at least in its nondualist versions.
4. Quoted in Raghavan Iyer, The Moral the Political Thought of Mahatma Gandhi (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1973), p. 226. In a speech in Mandalay in 1929 Gautama told his audience that using Buddhism they should
"explore the limitless possibilites of nonviolence" (The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi <New Delhi: Government of India Publications, 1959>, vol. 40, p. 159). It should be mentioned that Gandhi viewed both Jainism and
Buddhism as reform movements within Hinduism, not separate religions. Gandhi declared that he was proud of the
accusation (lodged by his own son) that he was a closet Buddhist, and that Buddhism is to Hinduism as Protestanism is to Roman Catholicism "only in a much stronger light, in a much greater degree" (Collected Works, vol. 40,
p. 104).
5.
Iyer, op. cit., p. 49.
6.
Gandhi, Non-Violence in Peace and War (Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1942), vol. 1, p. 48.
7. Stephen N. Hay is the principal proponent of Jain influences on Gandhi. While his two articles are wellresearched, his conclusion that Gandhi learned the importance of spiritual self-purification from Jainism is not
convincing. This goal is of course one that is common to the major religions of India. See Hay's "Jain Influences on
Gandhi's Early Thought" in Gandhi, India, and the World, ed. S. Ray (Bombay: Nachiketa Publishers, 1970), pp. 1423; and "Jaina Goals and Disciplines in Gandhi's Pursuit of Swaraj" in Rule, Protest, and Identity, ed. Peter Robb and
David Taylor (London: Curzon Press, 1978), pp. 120-132.
8. Young India (October 25, 1928), p. 356.
9.
Iyer, The Moral and Political Thought, p. 49.
10. Albert Schweitzer, Indian Thought and Its Development, trans. Mrs. Charles E. B. Russell (Bombay: Wilco
Publishing House, 1960), p. 231.
11. Gandhi, Collected Works, vol. 40, p. 160; speech at a Buddha Jayanti meeting in Bombay on May 18, 1924 in
The Collected Works, vol. 24, p. 86. Also significant is his passion for Sir Edwin Arnold's The Light of Asia, a
popular life of the Buddha. In his autobiography he tells of his vain attempt to persuade some Christian friends that
the Buddha's compassion was greater than Jesus'. See The Story of My Experiments with Truth, trans. M. Desai
(Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1989), pp. 133-34.
12. Navajivan (March 31, 1929), trans. in Collected Works, vol. 40, pp. 191-92.
13.
Collected Works, vol. 13, p. 232.
14.
Young India (January 21, 1926), p. 30.
15. See my "Dialectic: East and West," Indian Philosophical Quarterly 10(January, 1983), pp. 207-218.
16. David J. Kalupahana, A History of Buddhist Philosophy: Continuities and Discontinuities (Honolulu:
University of Hawaii Press, 1990), p. 174.
17. Bedekar, op. cit., p. 80. In a very insightful analysis, Bedekar suggests that Gandhi discovered that the "spell"
of Vedanta had compromised his commitment to individual agency and engagement (p. 115). According to Stephen
Hay, Raichand uses the term atman only to start a dialogue with the Hindu Gandhi, not to adopt it as his own ("Jain
Influences on Gandhi's Early Thought", p. 19). In terms of Hay's thesis of Jain influence it is significant that Gandhi
did not adopt Jain terminology.
18.
Young India (February 13, 1930), p. 56; Young India (July 8, 1926), p. 244.
19. Iyer, The Moral and Political Thought, pp. 131-32. There is no equivalent to Socratic daimon in Buddhism
either, at least in the Pali scriptures. See I. B. Horner, The Early Buddhist Theory of Man Perfected: A Study of the
Arahan (London: Williams & Norgate, 1936), p. 146.
20. Young India (February 13, 1930), p. 56. "My claim to hear the Voice of God is no new claim. Unfortunately,
there is no way that I know of proving the claim except through results" (Harijan, May 6, 1933, p. 4).
21. Gandhi, Harijan (July 8, 1933), p. 4. "Before one is able to listen to that Voice, one has to go through a long
and fairly severe course of training, and when it is the Inner Voice that speaks, it is unmistakable" (Harijan, March
18, 1933, p. 8). When Gandhi describes the Voice as coming upon him and causing "a terrific struggle" in him, this is
more in line with a new view of Socrates' daimon as the voice of God. This interpretation challenges the view that
Socrates saw his inner voice as the dictates of autonomous moral reason. (See Giovanni Reale, A History of Ancient
Philosophy: From the Origins to Socrates, ed. and trans. John R. Catan <Albany: SUNY Press, 1987>, vol. 1, pp.
232-35.) Gandhi's theism is especially strong in one article where he says that although some may call conscience
the "dictates of reason," it is really God's direct command (The Bombay Chronicle, November 18, 1933 reprinted in
Truth is God, ed. R. K. Prabhu <Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1955>, p. 29).
22.
Bedekar, op. cit., p. 117. Gandhi, The Story of My Experiments with Truth, p. xi.
23. Quoted in Kotturan, op. cit., p. 13. "No matter whether he is Svetambara, or Digambara, a Buddhist or
follower of any other creed, one who looks on all creatures as his own self, attains salvation" (quoted in ibid., p. 12).
24. See A. Siddhatissa, Buddhist Ethics: Essence of Buddhism (London: Allen & Unwin, 1970), p. 88; Bhagavada
Purana 3.29.28-32. Jainism does allow that if one cannot uphold the vow of noninjury to immobile beings, then one
must at least maintain it for mobile beings.
25. N. D. Bhargava states that "the world of relationship is a world of attachment and aversion. But nonviolence is possible and possible only without interrelationship, because interrelationship is dependent on others
and cannot be natural." See Bhargava's "Some Chief Characteristics of the Jain Concept of Nonviolence" in The
Contribution of Jainism to Indian Culture, ed. R. C. Divivedi (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1975), p. 124.
26.
Ibid., p. 122.
27. Gandhi, letter to Bhai Prithvi Singh, October 2, 1941 in Raghavan Iyer, ed., The Moral and Political Writings
of Mahatma Gandhi (Oxford University Press, 3 vols., 1986), vol. 2, p. 251.
28. "Nevertheless, Ahimsa is the means, Truth is the end" (From Yeravda Mandir, trans. V. G. Desai
<Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1945>, p. 8). In his autobiography, Gandhi says that the "only means for the realization of
Truth is Ahimsa. . . ." (The Story of My Experiments with Truth, p. 419; cf. p. 230). For ahimsa as a virtue see
Harijan (October 8, 1939), p. 282.
29. Harijan (September 1, 1940), p. 266. He also says that anasakti "transcends ahimsa." Elsewhere he states:
"We find that the fulfilment of Ahimsa is impossible without utter selflessness. Ahimsa means Universal Love"
(From Yeravda Mandir, p. 10).
30.
Gandhi, From Yeravda Mandir, p. 8.
31.
95.
Ramashray Roy, Self and Society: A Study in Gandhian Thought (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 1985), p.
32.
Ibid., p. 108.
33. John D. White, "God and the World from the Viewpoint of Advaita Vedanta: A Critical Assessment,"
International Philosophical Quarterly 30:2(June, 1981), pp. 185-193.
34. Gandhi, Speech at Tanjore on September 16, 1927 in Collected Works, vol. 35, p. 1. Feeling "one with God" is
"the principle of advaita" (a letter to Chi. Maganlal, May 18, 1918 in Iyer, The Moral and Political Writings, vol. 2,
p. 290).
35.
Gandhi, Young India (December 4, 1924), p. 398.
36.
Roy, op. cit., p. 74.
37. Ibid., p. 66.
38. Lovers of the orangutan will not appreciate Gandhi's reference to this peaceful creature as an example of
what will happen to us if we do not practice ahimsa! See Harijan (October 8, 1938), p. 282.
39.
Young India, July 8, 1926, p. 244.
40.
Harijan (June 7, 1942), p. 177.
41.
Harijan (February 15, 1948), p. 33.
42.
Gandhi, letter to Bhai Prithvi Singh (October 2, 1941) in Iyer, Moral and Political Writings, vol. 2, p. 250.
43.
Bedekar, op. cit., p. 81.
44. Gandhi, The Hindu (September 12, 1927) in Collected Works, vol. 34, p. 505. The preceding sentence "there
is no distinction whatever between individual growth and corporate growth" might imply absolute monism, but the
sentence cited makes it clear what Gandhi's meaning is.
45.
Harijan (September 28, 1934), p. 258.
46.
Gandhi, The Collected Works, vol. 19, p. 175.
47. Gandhi, Young India (January 21, 1926), p. 30. The long passage here is filled with unfortunate implications
of differences "inherent in human nature" and the "law of heredity." These comments mitigate the effect of his
otherwise laudable comments about a brahmin doing a sudra's work.
48. Harijan (March 6, 1937), p. 27. In the same source a questioner counters that, according to this logic,
Abraham Lincoln should not have aspired to become president of the United States. Gandhi only deflects the
question by answering, unsatisfactorily, that the scavenger, as long as he keeps his profession, can otherwise be
anything that he wants to be. Gandhi does allow one exception to the Law of Varna: we must follow the professions
of our fathers "in so far as that traditional calling is not inconsistent with fundamental ethics" (Young India, October
20, 1927, p. 355).
49.
Roy, op. cit., p. 92.
50. Ibid., p. 93.
51.
Ibid., p. 100.