• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
logical axiom
logical axiom

... ponens”, which states that from formulas A and A → B, one my deduce B. It is easy to see that this rule preserves logical validity. The axioms, together with modus ponens, form a sound deductive system for the classical propositional logic. In addition, it is also complete. Note that in the above se ...
Normalised and Cut-free Logic of Proofs
Normalised and Cut-free Logic of Proofs

... The old question discussed by Gödel in 1933/38 concerning the intended provability semantics of the classical modal logic S4 and intuitionistic logic IPC was finally settled by the logic of proofs introduced by Artemov [2001]. The logic of proofs Lp is a natural extension of classical propositional ...
Discrete Computational Structures (CS 225) Definition of Formal Proof
Discrete Computational Structures (CS 225) Definition of Formal Proof

... 2. A result of applying one of the logical equivalency rules (text, p. 35) to a previous statement in the proof. 3. A result of applying one of the valid argument forms (text, p. 61) to one or more previous statements in the proof. ...
By Rule EI, it suffices to show -------------------------------------------------------
By Rule EI, it suffices to show -------------------------------------------------------

... ...
INTLOGS16 Test 2
INTLOGS16 Test 2

... Note: Here, in keeping with the new notation introduced in class, φ(y) is a formula in which y is free. In addition, we stipulate that x is not free in φ(y). Q2 As you know, we have introduced the following numerical quantifiers: ∃=k , ∃≤k , ∃≥k , where of course k ∈ Z + . This allows us for instanc ...
Normal Forms
Normal Forms

... Input: a formula F Output: an equisatisfiable, rectified, closed formula in Skolem form ∀y1 . . . ∀yk G where G is quantifier-free 1. Rectify F by systematic renaming of bound variables. The result is a formula F1 equivalent to F . 2. Let y1 , y2 , . . . , yn be the variables occurring free in F1 . ...
Howework 8
Howework 8

... P rov be a provability predicate for the theory Q and X and Y be formulas in the Q. Assume |=Q P rov(dXe) ⊃ Y and |=Q P rov(dY e) ⊃ X ...
EECS 203-1 – Winter 2002 Definitions review sheet
EECS 203-1 – Winter 2002 Definitions review sheet

... • Propositional variable and propositional expression: A propositional variable is just a name, like p, q, . . .. A propositional expression is either a propositional variable, or a formula in one of the forms P ∧ Q, P ∨ Q, ¬P , P → Q, or P ↔ Q, where P and Q are themselves propositional expressions ...
1 Quantifier Complexity and Bounded Quantifiers
1 Quantifier Complexity and Bounded Quantifiers

... So far we have used ordinary quantifiers ∀ and ∃. In order to study quantifier complexity, we now introduce bounded versions, defined here: (∀y ≤ t)A(y) ↔ (∀y)(y ≤ t → A(y)) (∃y ≤ t)A(y) ↔ (∃y)(y ≤ t ∧ A(y)) where t is a term not involving y. Define a formula to be ∆0 if all of its quantifiers are bounde ...
The Origin of Proof Theory and its Evolution
The Origin of Proof Theory and its Evolution

... last item, i.e. there cannot be two lists that agree on all but the last item and disagree on the last item. A relation is an arbitrary set of lists. A collection of objects satisfies a relation if and only if the list of those objects is a member of this set. Logical connectives are { , } for the p ...
271HWPropLogic
271HWPropLogic

... Homework Prop Logic – Inference 1. Consider the statement “The car is either at John’s house or at Fred’s house. If the car is not at John’s house then it must be at Fred’s house”. Describe a set of propositional letters which can be used to represent this statement. Describe the statement using pro ...
Propositional Calculus - Syntax
Propositional Calculus - Syntax

... → Implication, if then ↔ Double implication, if and only if ⊗ Exclusive Or ...
< 1 ... 22 23 24 25 26

Sequent calculus

Sequent calculus is, in essence, a style of formal logical argumentation where every line of a proof is a conditional tautology (called a sequent by Gerhard Gentzen) instead of an unconditional tautology. Each conditional tautology is inferred from other conditional tautologies on earlier lines in a formal argument according to rules and procedures of inference, giving a better approximation to the style of natural deduction used by mathematicians than David Hilbert's earlier style of formal logic where every line was an unconditional tautology. (This is the essence of the idea, but there are several over-simplifications here. For example, there may be non-logical axioms upon which all propositions are implicitly dependent. Then sequents signify conditional theorems in a first-order language rather than conditional tautologies.)Sequent calculus is one of several extant styles of proof calculus for expressing line-by-line logical arguments. Hilbert style. Every line is an unconditional tautology (or theorem). Gentzen style. Every line is a conditional tautology (or theorem) with zero or more conditions on the left. Natural deduction. Every (conditional) line has exactly one asserted proposition on the right. Sequent calculus. Every (conditional) line has zero or more asserted propositions on the right.In other words, natural deduction and sequent calculus systems are particular distinct kinds of Gentzen-style systems. Hilbert-style systems typically have a very small number of inference rules, relying more on sets of axioms. Gentzen-style systems typically have very few axioms, if any, relying more on sets of rules.Gentzen-style systems have significant practical and theoretical advantages compared to Hilbert-style systems. For example, both natural deduction and sequent calculus systems facilitate the elimination and introduction of universal and existential quantifiers so that unquantified logical expressions can be manipulated according to the much simpler rules of propositional calculus. In a typical argument, quantifiers are eliminated, then propositional calculus is applied to unquantified expressions (which typically contain free variables), and then the quantifiers are reintroduced. This very much parallels the way in which mathematical proofs are carried out in practice by mathematicians. Predicate calculus proofs are generally much easier to discover with this approach, and are often shorter. Natural deduction systems are more suited to practical theorem-proving. Sequent calculus systems are more suited to theoretical analysis.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report