• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
A Propositional Modal Logic for the Liar Paradox Martin Dowd
A Propositional Modal Logic for the Liar Paradox Martin Dowd

... forms it has puzzled logicians and philosophers of natural language since the time of the Greeks. Within the last decade, the tools of mathematical logic have been brought to bear on this paradox. It is fair to say that a model which is satisfactory mathematically has been devised. Whether the issue ...
The strong completeness of the tableau method 1 The strong
The strong completeness of the tableau method 1 The strong

... some  <  in the well-ordering of the formulas of L+) has been left out of  , this can only mean that the corresponding set   {  } was inconsistent, hence so would be   {  } itself. On the other hand, the consistency of  alone is guaranteed by condition (2). And finally, again by the ...
Predicate_calculus
Predicate_calculus

... Jump to: navigation, search A formal axiomatic theory; a calculus intended for the description of logical laws (cf. Logical law) that are true for any non-empty domain of objects with arbitrary predicates (i.e. properties and relations) given on these objects. In order to formulate the predicate cal ...
A Logic of Explicit Knowledge - Lehman College
A Logic of Explicit Knowledge - Lehman College

... Now we drop the operator K from the language, and introduce a family of explicit reasons instead— I’ll use t as a typical one. Following [1, 2] I’ll write t:X to indicate that t applies to X—read it as “X is known for reason t.” Formally, if t is a reason and X is a formula, t:X is a formula. Of cou ...
Lecture 3
Lecture 3

... Therefore by (the contrapositives of) the two parts of F1, we conclude that he is able to prevent evil, and he is willing to prevent evil. By the implication of F0, we therefore ‘know’ that Superman does prevent evil. But this contradicts F2. Since we have arrived at a contradiction, ...
A Proof of Cut-Elimination Theorem for U Logic.
A Proof of Cut-Elimination Theorem for U Logic.

... is finding a common base for BPL and B. To make the two systems more comparable, Ardeshir and Vaezian in [1], introduced a modified version of mentioned axiomatization, and called it GBPC*. They also excluded connective ← from B and called the new system B’. They justified this action, by mentioning ...
Logic and Resolution
Logic and Resolution

... More expressive than propositional logic Distinguished from propositional logic by its use of quantifiers Each interpretation of first-order logic includes a domain of discourse over which the quantifiers range Additionally, it covers predicates Used to represent either a property or a relation betw ...
Propositional Logic
Propositional Logic

... is false, P(2) is true,…. • Examples of predicates: – Domain ASCII characters - IsAlpha(x) : TRUE iff x is an alphabetical character. – Domain floating point numbers - IsInt(x): TRUE iff x is an integer. – Domain integers: Prime(x) - TRUE if x is ...
Logic - Mathematical Institute SANU
Logic - Mathematical Institute SANU

... constants for operations and variables for numbers. The usual logical constants are the connectives and, or, if, if and only if and not, which are studied in propositional logic, and the quantifier expressions for every and for some, and identity (i.e. the relational expression equals), which, toget ...
Basic Logic - Progetto e
Basic Logic - Progetto e

... Propositional  logic  is  a  useful  tool  for  reasoning,  but  it  is  limited  because  it  cannot  see  inside   propositions  and  take  advantage  of  relationships  among  inner  elements.  For  example,  we  may   assume   that ...
mathematical logic: constructive and non
mathematical logic: constructive and non

... Much work has been done, especially by Péter since 1932, on special classes of computable functions, for which classes proofs are known t h a t all the computation procedures always terminate. To Church's thesis itself, the only suggested counterexamples involve 'computation procedures' in which the ...
slides
slides

... formulas φ, ψ, if φ ⊨ ψ, then there is a first-order formula χ with BindPatt(χ) ⊆ BindPatt(φ) ∩ BindPatt(ψ) and φ ⊨ χ ⊨ ψ. Moreover the formula χ in question can effectively constructed from a proof of φ ⊨ ψ (in a suitable proof system). ...
Propositional/First
Propositional/First

... • Logic is a great knowledge representation language for many AI problems • Propositional logic is the simple foundation and fine for some AI problems • First order logic (FOL) is much more expressive as a KR language and more commonly used in AI • There are many variations: horn logic, higher order ...
slides
slides

... A formula G is said to be a logical consequence of formulas F1 , F2 , . . . , Fn , notation F1 , . . . , Fn |= G , iff, for all interpretations I, if I |= F1 and . . . and I |= Fn then I |= G . Don’t get confused! The symbol |= is used in two different ways: I |= F F1 , . . . , Fn |= G In the first ...
CHAPTER 14 Hilbert System for Predicate Logic 1 Completeness
CHAPTER 14 Hilbert System for Predicate Logic 1 Completeness

... I | L = I. This means that we have to define cI 0 for all c ∈ C. By the definition, cI 0 ∈ M , so this also means that we have to assign the elements of M to all constants c ∈ C in such a way that the resulting expansion is a model for all sentences from SHenkin . The quantifier axioms Q1, Q2 are fi ...
on fuzzy intuitionistic logic
on fuzzy intuitionistic logic

... they m a y be t r u e 'in different ways'. By accepting different t r u t h values, we also break t h e true-false-dualism of classical logic. If we know t h e degree of t r u t h of a sentence we do not necessarily know t h e degree of falsehood of the sentence. In Fuzzy Intuitionistic Logic a half ...
Jean Van Heijenoort`s View of Modern Logic
Jean Van Heijenoort`s View of Modern Logic

... the proposition into subject and predicate had been replaced by its analysis into function and argument(s). A preliminary accomplishment was the propositional calculus, with a truth-functional definition of the connectives, including the conditional. Of cardinal importance was the realization that, ...
Propositional Logic Syntax of Propositional Logic
Propositional Logic Syntax of Propositional Logic

... – reasoning from a true conclusion to premises that may have caused the conclusion ...
MATHEMATICAL LOGIC CLASS NOTE 1. Propositional logic A
MATHEMATICAL LOGIC CLASS NOTE 1. Propositional logic A

... Proposition 3.1. If s1 , s2 are maps from V to a model M , and agree on all free variables in a formula φ, then M |= φ[s1 ] iff M |= φ[s2 ]. The proposition is proved using routine induction on formulas. By the proposition, without ambiguity we often write M |= φ[a1 , ..., an ] instead of M |= φ[s] w ...
A simple proof of Parsons` theorem
A simple proof of Parsons` theorem

... where we are identifying the terms with their interpretations in M. Note that all elements c, d1 , d2 , . . . are members of the above subset because the variables vj appear in the enumeration of terms. It is also clear that the above subset defines a substructure M∗ of M. Using the fact that U is a ...
Introduction to Predicate Logic
Introduction to Predicate Logic

... 2. If α is a constant, then [[α]] is specified by a function V (in the model M ) that assigns an individual object to each constant. [[α]]M,g = V (α) If P is a predicate, then [[P ]] is specified by a function V (in the model M ) that assigns a set-theoretic objects to each predicate. [[P ]]M,g = V ...
Aristotle`s particularisation
Aristotle`s particularisation

... interpretation—in a classical logic which appeals to Aristotle’s particularisation— by what he believed to be “a purely formal and much weaker assumption” of ω-consistency; introduction of which, presumably, would not invite inconsistency in any formal reasoning that appeals only syntactically to co ...
Propositional Logic
Propositional Logic

... Definition 2.1 Let Op = {¬, ∧, ∨, ⇒, ⇔ , ( , )} be the set of logical operators and Σ a set of symbols. The sets Op, Σ and {t, f } are pairwise disjoint. Σ is called the signature and its elements are the proposition variables. The set of propositional logic formulas is now recursively defined: • t ...
full text (.pdf)
full text (.pdf)

... We consider two related decision problems: given a rule of the form (1), (i) is it relationally valid? That is, is it true in all relational models? (ii) is it derivable in PHL? The paper Kozen 2000] considered problem (i) only. We show that both of these problems are PSPACE -hard by a single reduc ...
10a
10a

... Propositional logic • Logical constants: true, false • Propositional symbols: P, Q,... (aka atomic sentences) • Wrapping parentheses: ( … ) • Sentences are combined by connectives:  and [conjunction]  or [disjunction]  implies [implication / conditional]  is equivalent [biconditional]  not [ne ...
< 1 ... 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 ... 33 >

First-order logic

First-order logic is a formal system used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. It is also known as first-order predicate calculus, the lower predicate calculus, quantification theory, and predicate logic. First-order logic uses quantified variables over (non-logical) objects. This distinguishes it from propositional logic which does not use quantifiers.A theory about some topic is usually first-order logic together with a specified domain of discourse over which the quantified variables range, finitely many functions which map from that domain into it, finitely many predicates defined on that domain, and a recursive set of axioms which are believed to hold for those things. Sometimes ""theory"" is understood in a more formal sense, which is just a set of sentences in first-order logic.The adjective ""first-order"" distinguishes first-order logic from higher-order logic in which there are predicates having predicates or functions as arguments, or in which one or both of predicate quantifiers or function quantifiers are permitted. In first-order theories, predicates are often associated with sets. In interpreted higher-order theories, predicates may be interpreted as sets of sets.There are many deductive systems for first-order logic that are sound (all provable statements are true in all models) and complete (all statements which are true in all models are provable). Although the logical consequence relation is only semidecidable, much progress has been made in automated theorem proving in first-order logic. First-order logic also satisfies several metalogical theorems that make it amenable to analysis in proof theory, such as the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem and the compactness theorem.First-order logic is the standard for the formalization of mathematics into axioms and is studied in the foundations of mathematics. Mathematical theories, such as number theory and set theory, have been formalized into first-order axiom schemas such as Peano arithmetic and Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) respectively.No first-order theory, however, has the strength to describe uniquely a structure with an infinite domain, such as the natural numbers or the real line. A uniquely describing, i.e. categorical, axiom system for such a structure can be obtained in stronger logics such as second-order logic.For a history of first-order logic and how it came to dominate formal logic, see José Ferreirós (2001).
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report