
Document
... Two sets A and B are equivalent if there is a 1-1 function from A onto B . Example 3 The set of odd and even integers are equivalent. ...
... Two sets A and B are equivalent if there is a 1-1 function from A onto B . Example 3 The set of odd and even integers are equivalent. ...
Introduction to proposition
... well as too many other fields of study. Many algorithms and proofs use logical expressions such as: “IF p THEN q” or “If p1 AND p2, THEN q1 OR q2” Therefore it is necessary to know the cases in which these expressions are TRUE or FALSE, that is, to know the “truth value” of such expressions. To unde ...
... well as too many other fields of study. Many algorithms and proofs use logical expressions such as: “IF p THEN q” or “If p1 AND p2, THEN q1 OR q2” Therefore it is necessary to know the cases in which these expressions are TRUE or FALSE, that is, to know the “truth value” of such expressions. To unde ...
Lesson 2
... A set of formulas {A1,…,An} is satisfiable iff there is a valuation v such that v is a model of every formula Ai, i = 1,...,n. The valuation v is then a model of the set {A1,…,An}. Mathematical Logic ...
... A set of formulas {A1,…,An} is satisfiable iff there is a valuation v such that v is a model of every formula Ai, i = 1,...,n. The valuation v is then a model of the set {A1,…,An}. Mathematical Logic ...
Section 5.1 - The First Derivative
... Example 5.1.3: Find the critical values and partitions numbers for the following functions and then determine where the function is increasing or decreasing. (a) f (x) = 3x2 − 5x + 3 ...
... Example 5.1.3: Find the critical values and partitions numbers for the following functions and then determine where the function is increasing or decreasing. (a) f (x) = 3x2 − 5x + 3 ...
Predicate_calculus
... A formal axiomatic theory; a calculus intended for the description of logical laws (cf. Logical law) that are true for any non-empty domain of objects with arbitrary predicates (i.e. properties and relations) given on these objects. In order to formulate the predicate calculus one must first fix an ...
... A formal axiomatic theory; a calculus intended for the description of logical laws (cf. Logical law) that are true for any non-empty domain of objects with arbitrary predicates (i.e. properties and relations) given on these objects. In order to formulate the predicate calculus one must first fix an ...
P Q
... It allows any expression to be substituted for every occurrence of a symbol in a proposition that is an axiom or theorem already known to be true For instance, (BB)B may have the expression A substituted for B to produce (AA)A ...
... It allows any expression to be substituted for every occurrence of a symbol in a proposition that is an axiom or theorem already known to be true For instance, (BB)B may have the expression A substituted for B to produce (AA)A ...
1 Deductive Reasoning and Logical Connectives
... 6. Let p, q, and r synbolize “0 < x”, “x < 3”, and “x = 3”, respectively. Write the following inequalities symbolically: (a) x ≤ 3 (b) 0 < x < 3 (c) 0 ≤ x < 3 Statements such as p¬ ∨ q, p ∧ ×q, and p¬q all not “grammatical” expressions. We only consider well-formed formulas or just formulas. ...
... 6. Let p, q, and r synbolize “0 < x”, “x < 3”, and “x = 3”, respectively. Write the following inequalities symbolically: (a) x ≤ 3 (b) 0 < x < 3 (c) 0 ≤ x < 3 Statements such as p¬ ∨ q, p ∧ ×q, and p¬q all not “grammatical” expressions. We only consider well-formed formulas or just formulas. ...
Discrete Random Variables, I Terminology
... • Always specify the set of values x of a p.m.f.: A formula alone, such as f (x) = p(1−p)x , is useless without knowing the set of “legal” values x for this function. You can specify the values, by either listing all of them explicitly (e.g., “x = 2, 3, 5, 7, 11”), or with notational shortcuts (e.g. ...
... • Always specify the set of values x of a p.m.f.: A formula alone, such as f (x) = p(1−p)x , is useless without knowing the set of “legal” values x for this function. You can specify the values, by either listing all of them explicitly (e.g., “x = 2, 3, 5, 7, 11”), or with notational shortcuts (e.g. ...
Principia Mathematica

The Principia Mathematica is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics, written by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. In 1927, it appeared in a second edition with an important Introduction To the Second Edition, an Appendix A that replaced ✸9 and an all-new Appendix C.PM, as it is often abbreviated, was an attempt to describe a set of axioms and inference rules in symbolic logic from which all mathematical truths could in principle be proven. As such, this ambitious project is of great importance in the history of mathematics and philosophy, being one of the foremost products of the belief that such an undertaking may be achievable. However, in 1931, Gödel's incompleteness theorem proved definitively that PM, and in fact any other attempt, could never achieve this lofty goal; that is, for any set of axioms and inference rules proposed to encapsulate mathematics, either the system must be inconsistent, or there must in fact be some truths of mathematics which could not be deduced from them.One of the main inspirations and motivations for PM was the earlier work of Gottlob Frege on logic, which Russell discovered allowed for the construction of paradoxical sets. PM sought to avoid this problem by ruling out the unrestricted creation of arbitrary sets. This was achieved by replacing the notion of a general set with the notion of a hierarchy of sets of different 'types', a set of a certain type only allowed to contain sets of strictly lower types. Contemporary mathematics, however, avoids paradoxes such as Russell's in less unwieldy ways, such as the system of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.PM is not to be confused with Russell's 1903 Principles of Mathematics. PM states: ""The present work was originally intended by us to be comprised in a second volume of Principles of Mathematics... But as we advanced, it became increasingly evident that the subject is a very much larger one than we had supposed; moreover on many fundamental questions which had been left obscure and doubtful in the former work, we have now arrived at what we believe to be satisfactory solutions.""The Modern Library placed it 23rd in a list of the top 100 English-language nonfiction books of the twentieth century.