
The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski
... Padoa lists a number of notions that he considers as belonging to general logic such as class (“which corresponds to the words: terminus of the scholastics, set of the mathematicians, common noun of ordinary language”). The notion of class is not defined but assumed with its informal meaning. Extens ...
... Padoa lists a number of notions that he considers as belonging to general logic such as class (“which corresponds to the words: terminus of the scholastics, set of the mathematicians, common noun of ordinary language”). The notion of class is not defined but assumed with its informal meaning. Extens ...
Scientific Notation
... A. Definition of Scientific Notation Sometimes scientists need to write very big or very small numbers that contain many zeros, such as the number of molecules of a substance in one mole of the substance, known as Avogadro Constant, which is 602,214,179,000,000,000,000,000; or, the radius of an elec ...
... A. Definition of Scientific Notation Sometimes scientists need to write very big or very small numbers that contain many zeros, such as the number of molecules of a substance in one mole of the substance, known as Avogadro Constant, which is 602,214,179,000,000,000,000,000; or, the radius of an elec ...
It is in Secondary Mathematics III that students pull together and
... algebra. Rational numbers extend the arithmetic of integers by allowing division by all numbers except 0. Similarly, rational expressions extend the arithmetic of polynomials by allowing division by all polynomials except the zero polynomial. A central theme of this unit is that the arithmetic of ra ...
... algebra. Rational numbers extend the arithmetic of integers by allowing division by all numbers except 0. Similarly, rational expressions extend the arithmetic of polynomials by allowing division by all polynomials except the zero polynomial. A central theme of this unit is that the arithmetic of ra ...
The Uniform Continuity of Functions on Normed Linear Spaces
... (Def. 2)(i) X ⊆ dom f, and (ii) for every r such that 0 < r there exists s such that 0 < s and for all x1 , x2 such that x1 ∈ X and x2 ∈ X and kx1 − x2 k < s holds |fx1 − fx2 | < r. The following propositions are true: (1) If f is uniformly continuous on X and X1 ⊆ X, then f is uniformly continuous ...
... (Def. 2)(i) X ⊆ dom f, and (ii) for every r such that 0 < r there exists s such that 0 < s and for all x1 , x2 such that x1 ∈ X and x2 ∈ X and kx1 − x2 k < s holds |fx1 − fx2 | < r. The following propositions are true: (1) If f is uniformly continuous on X and X1 ⊆ X, then f is uniformly continuous ...
Lectures on Proof Theory - Create and Use Your home.uchicago
... arithmetical truths might be inconsistent—but that was simply an empty skepticism. On the other hand, as we now know, in view of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, there is no relevant sense in which we can refute it. Surely, if we are to judge by how long it took for the various successive extension ...
... arithmetical truths might be inconsistent—but that was simply an empty skepticism. On the other hand, as we now know, in view of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, there is no relevant sense in which we can refute it. Surely, if we are to judge by how long it took for the various successive extension ...
Python in Education
... We need a big picture of the OO design at first, to make sense of dot notation around core objects such as lists i.e. “these are types, and this is how we think of them, use them.” Use lots of analogies, metaphors. Write your own classes a little later, after you’ve defined and saved functions in mo ...
... We need a big picture of the OO design at first, to make sense of dot notation around core objects such as lists i.e. “these are types, and this is how we think of them, use them.” Use lots of analogies, metaphors. Write your own classes a little later, after you’ve defined and saved functions in mo ...
The Art of Ordinal Analysis
... Corollary 1.7. A contradiction, i.e. the empty sequent ∅ ⇒ ∅, is not deducible. Proof : According to the Hauptsatz, if the empty sequent were deducible it would have a deduction without cuts. In a cut-free deduction of the empty sequent only empty sequents can occur. But such a deduction does not ex ...
... Corollary 1.7. A contradiction, i.e. the empty sequent ∅ ⇒ ∅, is not deducible. Proof : According to the Hauptsatz, if the empty sequent were deducible it would have a deduction without cuts. In a cut-free deduction of the empty sequent only empty sequents can occur. But such a deduction does not ex ...
Document
... When a function f is defined with a rule or an equation using x and y for the independent and dependent variables, we say “y is a function of x” to emphasize that y depends on x. We use the notation ...
... When a function f is defined with a rule or an equation using x and y for the independent and dependent variables, we say “y is a function of x” to emphasize that y depends on x. We use the notation ...
Assignment and Arithmetic expressions
... If an arithmetic operator is combined with int operands, then the resulting type is int If an arithmetic operator is combined with one or two double operands, then the resulting type is double If different types are combined in an expression, then the resulting type is the right-most type on the fol ...
... If an arithmetic operator is combined with int operands, then the resulting type is int If an arithmetic operator is combined with one or two double operands, then the resulting type is double If different types are combined in an expression, then the resulting type is the right-most type on the fol ...
Principia Mathematica

The Principia Mathematica is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics, written by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. In 1927, it appeared in a second edition with an important Introduction To the Second Edition, an Appendix A that replaced ✸9 and an all-new Appendix C.PM, as it is often abbreviated, was an attempt to describe a set of axioms and inference rules in symbolic logic from which all mathematical truths could in principle be proven. As such, this ambitious project is of great importance in the history of mathematics and philosophy, being one of the foremost products of the belief that such an undertaking may be achievable. However, in 1931, Gödel's incompleteness theorem proved definitively that PM, and in fact any other attempt, could never achieve this lofty goal; that is, for any set of axioms and inference rules proposed to encapsulate mathematics, either the system must be inconsistent, or there must in fact be some truths of mathematics which could not be deduced from them.One of the main inspirations and motivations for PM was the earlier work of Gottlob Frege on logic, which Russell discovered allowed for the construction of paradoxical sets. PM sought to avoid this problem by ruling out the unrestricted creation of arbitrary sets. This was achieved by replacing the notion of a general set with the notion of a hierarchy of sets of different 'types', a set of a certain type only allowed to contain sets of strictly lower types. Contemporary mathematics, however, avoids paradoxes such as Russell's in less unwieldy ways, such as the system of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.PM is not to be confused with Russell's 1903 Principles of Mathematics. PM states: ""The present work was originally intended by us to be comprised in a second volume of Principles of Mathematics... But as we advanced, it became increasingly evident that the subject is a very much larger one than we had supposed; moreover on many fundamental questions which had been left obscure and doubtful in the former work, we have now arrived at what we believe to be satisfactory solutions.""The Modern Library placed it 23rd in a list of the top 100 English-language nonfiction books of the twentieth century.