
How to Differentiate a Number
... Note that a large portion of them (69 from 153) are primes, one of them (529 = 23 2 ) is a square, and some of them (e.g. 765 = 32 · 5 · 17) have at least 4 prime factors. In general it is interesting to investigate the behavior of the “integrating” function I(a) which calculates for every a the set ...
... Note that a large portion of them (69 from 153) are primes, one of them (529 = 23 2 ) is a square, and some of them (e.g. 765 = 32 · 5 · 17) have at least 4 prime factors. In general it is interesting to investigate the behavior of the “integrating” function I(a) which calculates for every a the set ...
A Brief Introduction to Propositional Logic
... least one its conjuncts is true; otherwise, the truth value is false. Note that this is the inclusive or interpretation of the ∨ operator and is differentiated from the exclusive or interpretation in which a disjunction is true if and only if an odd number of its disjuncts are false. • The truth val ...
... least one its conjuncts is true; otherwise, the truth value is false. Note that this is the inclusive or interpretation of the ∨ operator and is differentiated from the exclusive or interpretation in which a disjunction is true if and only if an odd number of its disjuncts are false. • The truth val ...
MULTIVARIATE BIRKHOFF-LAGRANGE INTERPOLATION
... In this section we study the relation between cartesian sets of nodes and the regularity of the Birkhoff-Lagrange schemes. We will show the following, whose particular case appearing in Lemma 3.1 below can be seen as an analogue of Theorem 12.3.1 of [3]. Proposition 3.1. Given two lower sets S and S ...
... In this section we study the relation between cartesian sets of nodes and the regularity of the Birkhoff-Lagrange schemes. We will show the following, whose particular case appearing in Lemma 3.1 below can be seen as an analogue of Theorem 12.3.1 of [3]. Proposition 3.1. Given two lower sets S and S ...
Full text
... which is the best companion to (31) noted at this time* Another approach would be to develop a q-bracket function (q-greatest integer function) and proceed in a manner similar to the above by expanding the binomial coefficient I . J in terms of a q-bracket function and using this in relation (2) jus ...
... which is the best companion to (31) noted at this time* Another approach would be to develop a q-bracket function (q-greatest integer function) and proceed in a manner similar to the above by expanding the binomial coefficient I . J in terms of a q-bracket function and using this in relation (2) jus ...
eprint_4_1049_36.doc
... then 3 = 2 + 1, then 4 = 3 + 1, and so on. The principle makes precise the vague phrase “and so on.” Principle of Mathematical Induction: Let S be a set of positive integers with the following two properties: (i) 1 belongs to S. (ii) If k belongs to S, then k + 1 belongs to S. Then S is the set of a ...
... then 3 = 2 + 1, then 4 = 3 + 1, and so on. The principle makes precise the vague phrase “and so on.” Principle of Mathematical Induction: Let S be a set of positive integers with the following two properties: (i) 1 belongs to S. (ii) If k belongs to S, then k + 1 belongs to S. Then S is the set of a ...
Examples of Natural Deduction
... conclusion, we could construct a new rule – given a rationale link between a premise and an inconsistency, we could construct the negation of the ...
... conclusion, we could construct a new rule – given a rationale link between a premise and an inconsistency, we could construct the negation of the ...
Mathematical proof

In mathematics, a proof is a deductive argument for a mathematical statement. In the argument, other previously established statements, such as theorems, can be used. In principle, a proof can be traced back to self-evident or assumed statements, known as axioms. Proofs are examples of deductive reasoning and are distinguished from inductive or empirical arguments; a proof must demonstrate that a statement is always true (occasionally by listing all possible cases and showing that it holds in each), rather than enumerate many confirmatory cases. An unproved proposition that is believed true is known as a conjecture.Proofs employ logic but usually include some amount of natural language which usually admits some ambiguity. In fact, the vast majority of proofs in written mathematics can be considered as applications of rigorous informal logic. Purely formal proofs, written in symbolic language instead of natural language, are considered in proof theory. The distinction between formal and informal proofs has led to much examination of current and historical mathematical practice, quasi-empiricism in mathematics, and so-called folk mathematics (in both senses of that term). The philosophy of mathematics is concerned with the role of language and logic in proofs, and mathematics as a language.