
Lecture 09
... j with 2 ≤ j ≤ k. To show that P(k + 1) must be true under this assumption, two cases need to be considered: • If k + 1 is prime, then P(k + 1) is true. • Otherwise, k + 1 is composite and can be written as the product of two positive integers a and b with 2 ≤ a ≤ b < k + 1. By the inductive hypothe ...
... j with 2 ≤ j ≤ k. To show that P(k + 1) must be true under this assumption, two cases need to be considered: • If k + 1 is prime, then P(k + 1) is true. • Otherwise, k + 1 is composite and can be written as the product of two positive integers a and b with 2 ≤ a ≤ b < k + 1. By the inductive hypothe ...
basicCounting - CSE@IIT Delhi
... We form the subsets by picking one element at a time. • There are n choices for the first element. • For each of these, there are n − 1 remaining choices for the second element. • There are n – k + 1 remaining choices for the last element. • Thus, there are a total of n · (n − 1) · (n − 2) · · · (n ...
... We form the subsets by picking one element at a time. • There are n choices for the first element. • For each of these, there are n − 1 remaining choices for the second element. • There are n – k + 1 remaining choices for the last element. • Thus, there are a total of n · (n − 1) · (n − 2) · · · (n ...
Constraint Propagation as a Proof System
... constraints. OBDDs possess many desirable algorithmic properties and have been used successfully in many areas, most notably in formal verification (see [Bry92,BCM 92]). We compare the strength of refutations by OBDDs with other proof systems for propositional logic. We show that OBDD-based refutati ...
... constraints. OBDDs possess many desirable algorithmic properties and have been used successfully in many areas, most notably in formal verification (see [Bry92,BCM 92]). We compare the strength of refutations by OBDDs with other proof systems for propositional logic. We show that OBDD-based refutati ...
Full text
... The references that follow include mainly papers that have been referred to above8 Vandiver in his expository paper [22] remarks that some 1500 papers on Bernoulli numbers have been published! For Fermat's last theorem, the reader is referred to Vandiver 1 s expository paper [21] as well as Dickson ...
... The references that follow include mainly papers that have been referred to above8 Vandiver in his expository paper [22] remarks that some 1500 papers on Bernoulli numbers have been published! For Fermat's last theorem, the reader is referred to Vandiver 1 s expository paper [21] as well as Dickson ...
a pdf file - The Citadel
... can not be factored as a product of two Gaussian Integers except by using a unit {±1, ±i}. For example, since 13 32 2 2 3 2i 3 2i we see 13 is not a Gaussian Prime even though it is a prime in Z. Definition: An element α in G = {a + bi : a,b Z}is prime iff α is not a unit and whenev ...
... can not be factored as a product of two Gaussian Integers except by using a unit {±1, ±i}. For example, since 13 32 2 2 3 2i 3 2i we see 13 is not a Gaussian Prime even though it is a prime in Z. Definition: An element α in G = {a + bi : a,b Z}is prime iff α is not a unit and whenev ...
Algebraic Symmetries I Just as we can factor z 3 − 1=(z − 1)(z + z + 1
... Some of these terms are purely fictive, those in which ai appears with i larger than n or bj with j larger than m. If a0 or b0 appear they are taken to be 1. For example, if n = 5, m = 3 then the coefficient of Z 4 is a4 + a3 b1 + a2 b2 + a1 b3 In general, the coefficient of Z k+l is supposed integr ...
... Some of these terms are purely fictive, those in which ai appears with i larger than n or bj with j larger than m. If a0 or b0 appear they are taken to be 1. For example, if n = 5, m = 3 then the coefficient of Z 4 is a4 + a3 b1 + a2 b2 + a1 b3 In general, the coefficient of Z k+l is supposed integr ...
Herbrands Theorem
... It is infeasible to consider all interpretations over all domains in order to prove unsatisfiability Instead, we try to fix a special domain (called a Herbrand universe) such that the formula, S, is unsatisfiable iff it is false under all the interpretations over this domain ...
... It is infeasible to consider all interpretations over all domains in order to prove unsatisfiability Instead, we try to fix a special domain (called a Herbrand universe) such that the formula, S, is unsatisfiable iff it is false under all the interpretations over this domain ...
Lower Bounds for Relatively Prime Amicable Numbers of Opposite
... opposite parity then mn > 48 • 1058.The present author showed in [2] that mn > 107\ The purpose of the present paper is to establish a still better lower bound for mn. Thus, we shall prove the following Theorem. // m and n are a pair of relatively prime amicable numbers of opposite parity then mn > ...
... opposite parity then mn > 48 • 1058.The present author showed in [2] that mn > 107\ The purpose of the present paper is to establish a still better lower bound for mn. Thus, we shall prove the following Theorem. // m and n are a pair of relatively prime amicable numbers of opposite parity then mn > ...
PARADOX AND INTUITION
... mean that we at the same time establish any structure-preserving correspondence between the objects from the initial model and arithmetical objects. Hilary Putnam’s paper Models and Reality (Putnam 1980) has become one of the most frequently quoted works discussing problems connected with determinac ...
... mean that we at the same time establish any structure-preserving correspondence between the objects from the initial model and arithmetical objects. Hilary Putnam’s paper Models and Reality (Putnam 1980) has become one of the most frequently quoted works discussing problems connected with determinac ...
classden
... to, and can in fact be identified with, the function space [D → D] of all continuous functions from D to D. This guarantees that any object d ∈ D is also a function d : D → D and hence that it is meaningful to talk about d(d). Scott domains thus support the interpretation of self-application and in ...
... to, and can in fact be identified with, the function space [D → D] of all continuous functions from D to D. This guarantees that any object d ∈ D is also a function d : D → D and hence that it is meaningful to talk about d(d). Scott domains thus support the interpretation of self-application and in ...
Mathematical proof

In mathematics, a proof is a deductive argument for a mathematical statement. In the argument, other previously established statements, such as theorems, can be used. In principle, a proof can be traced back to self-evident or assumed statements, known as axioms. Proofs are examples of deductive reasoning and are distinguished from inductive or empirical arguments; a proof must demonstrate that a statement is always true (occasionally by listing all possible cases and showing that it holds in each), rather than enumerate many confirmatory cases. An unproved proposition that is believed true is known as a conjecture.Proofs employ logic but usually include some amount of natural language which usually admits some ambiguity. In fact, the vast majority of proofs in written mathematics can be considered as applications of rigorous informal logic. Purely formal proofs, written in symbolic language instead of natural language, are considered in proof theory. The distinction between formal and informal proofs has led to much examination of current and historical mathematical practice, quasi-empiricism in mathematics, and so-called folk mathematics (in both senses of that term). The philosophy of mathematics is concerned with the role of language and logic in proofs, and mathematics as a language.