• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
pdf
pdf

pdf [local copy]
pdf [local copy]

Classical first-order predicate logic This is a powerful extension of
Classical first-order predicate logic This is a powerful extension of

... • ∀x(bought(Tony, x) → bought(Susan, x)) ‘Susan bought everything that Tony bought.’ • ∀x bought(Tony, x) → ∀x bought(Susan, x) ‘If Tony bought everything, so did Susan.’ Note the difference! • ∀x∃y bought(x, y) ‘Everything bought something.’ • ∃x∀y bought(x, y) ‘Something bought everything.’ You ca ...
lecture notes in logic - UCLA Department of Mathematics
lecture notes in logic - UCLA Department of Mathematics

... “singleton operation”, i.e., for every x, x ∈ z =⇒ {x} ∈ z. (7) Choice: for every set x whose members are all non-empty and pairwise disjoint, there exists a set z which intersects each member of x in exactly one point, i.e., if y ∈ x, then there exists exactly one u such that u ∈ y and also u ∈ z. ...
pdf
pdf

An Introduction to Mathematical Logic
An Introduction to Mathematical Logic

... Reconsidering the above we recognize the following three “ingredients”: 1. a theorem (which is nothing but a sentence in a formalised language) 2. the claim that this theorem is a logical consequence of other sentences (here: the group axioms) 3. the proof of the theorem ,→ Mathematical logic is the ...
HONEST ELEMENTARY DEGREES AND DEGREES OF RELATIVE
HONEST ELEMENTARY DEGREES AND DEGREES OF RELATIVE

PPT
PPT

... not faster than itself for problem size n.” i  N, n  N, n > i  ~Faster(a, a, n) Consider an arbitrary (positive integer) i. Let n = ??. (Must be > i; so, at least i+1.) So, we need to prove: “a is not faster than itself for problem size ?? (for an arbitrary positive integer i)” ...
PPT - UBC Department of CPSC Undergraduates
PPT - UBC Department of CPSC Undergraduates

... not faster than itself for problem size n.” i  N, n  N, n > i  ~Faster(a, a, n) Consider an arbitrary (positive integer) i. Let n = ??. (Must be > i; so, at least i+1.) So, we need to prove: “a is not faster than itself for problem size ?? (for an arbitrary positive integer i)” ...
Classical first-order predicate logic This is a powerful extension
Classical first-order predicate logic This is a powerful extension

... • ∀x(bought(Tony, x) → bought(Susan, x)) ‘Susan bought everything that Tony bought.’ • ∀x bought(Tony, x) → ∀x bought(Susan, x) ‘If Tony bought everything, so did Susan.’ Note the difference! • ∀x∃y bought(x, y) ‘Everything bought something.’ • ∃x∀y bought(x, y) ‘Something bought everything.’ You ca ...
thèse - IRIT
thèse - IRIT

... Here-and-there (HT) logic is a three-valued monotonic logic which is intermediate between classical logic and intuitionistic logic. Equilibrium logic is a nonmonotonic formalism whose semantics is given through a minimisation criterion over HT models. It is closely aligned with answer set programmin ...
Cichon`s diagram, regularity properties and ∆ sets of reals.
Cichon`s diagram, regularity properties and ∆ sets of reals.

Mathematical Logic
Mathematical Logic

... are represented corresponds very much to the way a careful mathematician writing out all details of an argument would go anyway. Second, formal proofs in natural deduction are closely related (via the so-called CurryHoward correspondence) to terms in typed lambda calculus. This provides us not only ...
The Foundations
The Foundations

Boolean Logic - Programming Systems Lab
Boolean Logic - Programming Systems Lab

Computability theoretic classifications for classes of structures
Computability theoretic classifications for classes of structures

LPF and MPLω — A Logical Comparison of VDM SL and COLD-K
LPF and MPLω — A Logical Comparison of VDM SL and COLD-K

... In Section 2, these logics are described in broad outline. Some other logics which handle partial functions are discussed in Section 3. Sections 4–8 constitute the body of this paper. In Section 4 we present ML= , many-sorted classical logic with equality, by giving definitions of the language, the ...
CS 208: Automata Theory and Logic
CS 208: Automata Theory and Logic

... – Introduced by Alan Turing as a simple model capable of expressing any imaginable computation – Turing machines are widely accepted as a synonyms for algorithmic computability (Church-Turing thesis) – Using these conceptual machines Turing showed that first-order logic validity problem a is non-com ...
Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 8(4:19)2012, pp. 1–28 Submitted Oct. 27, 2011
Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 8(4:19)2012, pp. 1–28 Submitted Oct. 27, 2011

Logic in Nonmonotonic Reasoning
Logic in Nonmonotonic Reasoning

Document
Document

Document
Document

... – If we can enumerate all of the possible cases, and prove that the statement is true in each case, then we have proven the statement – For example, if we want to prove that one proposition P implies another proposition Q, then looking at the truth tables for P and Q gives us one way of enumerating ...
THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE PRINCIPAL GENUS
THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE PRINCIPAL GENUS

Section 1: Propositional Logic
Section 1: Propositional Logic

... • The first is the depth to which we explore the structure of statements. The study of the basic level of structure is called propositional logic. First order predicate logic, which is often called just predicate logic, studies structure on a deeper level. • The second direction is the nature of tru ...
Language, Proof and Logic
Language, Proof and Logic

< 1 ... 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 ... 72 >

Mathematical logic

Mathematical logic is a subfield of mathematics exploring the applications of formal logic to mathematics. It bears close connections to metamathematics, the foundations of mathematics, and theoretical computer science. The unifying themes in mathematical logic include the study of the expressive power of formal systems and the deductive power of formal proof systems.Mathematical logic is often divided into the fields of set theory, model theory, recursion theory, and proof theory. These areas share basic results on logic, particularly first-order logic, and definability. In computer science (particularly in the ACM Classification) mathematical logic encompasses additional topics not detailed in this article; see Logic in computer science for those.Since its inception, mathematical logic has both contributed to, and has been motivated by, the study of foundations of mathematics. This study began in the late 19th century with the development of axiomatic frameworks for geometry, arithmetic, and analysis. In the early 20th century it was shaped by David Hilbert's program to prove the consistency of foundational theories. Results of Kurt Gödel, Gerhard Gentzen, and others provided partial resolution to the program, and clarified the issues involved in proving consistency. Work in set theory showed that almost all ordinary mathematics can be formalized in terms of sets, although there are some theorems that cannot be proven in common axiom systems for set theory. Contemporary work in the foundations of mathematics often focuses on establishing which parts of mathematics can be formalized in particular formal systems (as in reverse mathematics) rather than trying to find theories in which all of mathematics can be developed.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report