
CHAPTER III - MARKOV CHAINS 1. General Theory of Markov
... Hence limn→∞ Zn exists with probability 1, and it is easy to see that the limit must ...
... Hence limn→∞ Zn exists with probability 1, and it is easy to see that the limit must ...
The Difference Between Selection and Drift: A Reply
... processes can result in changes in gene and genotype frequencies across generational time, but our best theories of these processes differ in that theories of selection can predict the direction, as well as rate, of cross-generational change, while our theories of drift can predict only the rate, but ...
... processes can result in changes in gene and genotype frequencies across generational time, but our best theories of these processes differ in that theories of selection can predict the direction, as well as rate, of cross-generational change, while our theories of drift can predict only the rate, but ...
3 column 7th grade
... with numbers in any form; convert between forms as appropriate o M07.B-E.1.1.1 o 7.E.E.2 Solve word problems leading to equations of the form px+q=r and p(x+q) = r, where p,q,and r are specific rational numbers o M07.B-E.2.2.1 o 7.EE.4a Solve world problems leading to inequalities of the form px ...
... with numbers in any form; convert between forms as appropriate o M07.B-E.1.1.1 o 7.E.E.2 Solve word problems leading to equations of the form px+q=r and p(x+q) = r, where p,q,and r are specific rational numbers o M07.B-E.2.2.1 o 7.EE.4a Solve world problems leading to inequalities of the form px ...
Computation and Thermodynamics
... Kolmogorov complexity The Kolmogorov complexity of n ∈ N is the length of the shortest string x with U(x) = n. Intuitively, it’s the length of the shortest program that prints out n. We can also talk about the Kolmogorov complexity of a string, since we can encode strings as natural numbers. Indeed ...
... Kolmogorov complexity The Kolmogorov complexity of n ∈ N is the length of the shortest string x with U(x) = n. Intuitively, it’s the length of the shortest program that prints out n. We can also talk about the Kolmogorov complexity of a string, since we can encode strings as natural numbers. Indeed ...
8.1 the binomial distributions
... (a) Does X satisfy the requirements for a binomial setting? Explain. If X = B(n, p), what are n and p? (b) Describe P(X = 0) in words. Then find P(X = 0) and P(X = 1). (c) What is the probability that 2 or more of the 100 children have a parent behind bars? 8.7 DO OUR ATHLETES GRADUATE? A university ...
... (a) Does X satisfy the requirements for a binomial setting? Explain. If X = B(n, p), what are n and p? (b) Describe P(X = 0) in words. Then find P(X = 0) and P(X = 1). (c) What is the probability that 2 or more of the 100 children have a parent behind bars? 8.7 DO OUR ATHLETES GRADUATE? A university ...
1 Approximate Counting by Random Sampling
... (b) Using the random generator Rand[0,1], design a randomized algorithm to achieve the desired goal. Give the number of black box accesses to the function f and the number of accesses to Rand[0,1] used by your algorithm. 2. Estimating the (Unknown) Fraction of Red Balls. Suppose a bag contains an un ...
... (b) Using the random generator Rand[0,1], design a randomized algorithm to achieve the desired goal. Give the number of black box accesses to the function f and the number of accesses to Rand[0,1] used by your algorithm. 2. Estimating the (Unknown) Fraction of Red Balls. Suppose a bag contains an un ...
Approximations of upper and lower probabilities by measurable
... shall sometimes use the notation PΓ∗ := P ∗ and P∗Γ := P∗ , if there is ambiguity about the random set inducing the upper and lower probabilities. It is easy to see that A∗ ⊆ U −1 (A) ⊆ A∗ for every A ∈ A0 and every U ∈ S(Γ). This implies that the class P(Γ) defined in Eq. (2) is included in M (P ∗ ...
... shall sometimes use the notation PΓ∗ := P ∗ and P∗Γ := P∗ , if there is ambiguity about the random set inducing the upper and lower probabilities. It is easy to see that A∗ ⊆ U −1 (A) ⊆ A∗ for every A ∈ A0 and every U ∈ S(Γ). This implies that the class P(Γ) defined in Eq. (2) is included in M (P ∗ ...
A Sharp Test of the Portability of Expertise ∗ Etan A. Green
... perform nearly the same task in which they are experienced. This analogous task differs from our subjects’ domain of expertise on a minimal set of contextual cues; on formal dimensions, it is isomorphic. Our main finding is that these experts fail to apply their expertise in the unfamiliar environme ...
... perform nearly the same task in which they are experienced. This analogous task differs from our subjects’ domain of expertise on a minimal set of contextual cues; on formal dimensions, it is isomorphic. Our main finding is that these experts fail to apply their expertise in the unfamiliar environme ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.