
Fast Iterative Coding Techniques for Feedback Channels
... which the receiver passes the transmitter its observations—generally enables schemes for communicating over the forward channel to have lower computational complexity, higher reliability, higher capacity, or a combination of these advantages, in comparison to feedback-free communication schemes. The ...
... which the receiver passes the transmitter its observations—generally enables schemes for communicating over the forward channel to have lower computational complexity, higher reliability, higher capacity, or a combination of these advantages, in comparison to feedback-free communication schemes. The ...
Inference without significance: measuring support for hypotheses
... small P-value meant that the data did not support the hypothesis, but Fisher was not dogmatic about a 0.05 cutoff for significance (see Hurlbert & Lombardi 2009 for changes in Fisher’s thinking), nor did he view the outcome of any single experiment as decisive. Neyman and Pearson, on the other hand, ...
... small P-value meant that the data did not support the hypothesis, but Fisher was not dogmatic about a 0.05 cutoff for significance (see Hurlbert & Lombardi 2009 for changes in Fisher’s thinking), nor did he view the outcome of any single experiment as decisive. Neyman and Pearson, on the other hand, ...
ece11 Buchholz 16734994 en
... which normative objectives ("values" ) can be incorporated by this approach. So, in particular, it can be asked whether the use of specific von Neumann-Morgenstern (vNM) utility functions is able to generate outcomes that conform with ethical intuition in particular situations. If this is possible, ...
... which normative objectives ("values" ) can be incorporated by this approach. So, in particular, it can be asked whether the use of specific von Neumann-Morgenstern (vNM) utility functions is able to generate outcomes that conform with ethical intuition in particular situations. If this is possible, ...
Relevant Explanations: Allowing Disjunctive Assignments
... first constraint and Mv at all. We could allow any dis junction, as long as the second constraint, that condi tional independence hold, is obeyed. In fact, this seems equivalent to an argument of the following form: we ...
... first constraint and Mv at all. We could allow any dis junction, as long as the second constraint, that condi tional independence hold, is obeyed. In fact, this seems equivalent to an argument of the following form: we ...
pdf
... each level; we must keep that random as well. Having done this, we can use simple Chernoff bounds to show that, for almost all combinations of graphs and restrictions, the degree at each level will not be much smaller than the expected degree, so the pigeonhole principle will remain far from trivial ...
... each level; we must keep that random as well. Having done this, we can use simple Chernoff bounds to show that, for almost all combinations of graphs and restrictions, the degree at each level will not be much smaller than the expected degree, so the pigeonhole principle will remain far from trivial ...
PDF
... Suppose that a new alien species is presented for risk assessment. It is not part of the experiment, so we do not know its true threat status, but we have the score sk(v) for the single risk component, and appropriate estimates of the prior probabilities Pr(V) and Pr(¬V). The posterior probabilities ...
... Suppose that a new alien species is presented for risk assessment. It is not part of the experiment, so we do not know its true threat status, but we have the score sk(v) for the single risk component, and appropriate estimates of the prior probabilities Pr(V) and Pr(¬V). The posterior probabilities ...
document
... The analysis of these algorithms has focused on proving the existence of “good” local minima of the cost function (those leading to separation), the absence of undesired local minima (not associated to separation), computational complexity, suitable step sizes in gradient descent implementations, an ...
... The analysis of these algorithms has focused on proving the existence of “good” local minima of the cost function (those leading to separation), the absence of undesired local minima (not associated to separation), computational complexity, suitable step sizes in gradient descent implementations, an ...
A Monotonicity Result for a G/GI/c Queue with Balking or
... For the ith arrival, let Vi and Ui be uniform random variables taking values between 0 and 1, independent of everything else. First, if Vi < p then the arrival is labelled as type 1, and if p < Vi < p + ε then it is labelled as type 2. In the (p, ε) system, if the queue length is x at the time of th ...
... For the ith arrival, let Vi and Ui be uniform random variables taking values between 0 and 1, independent of everything else. First, if Vi < p then the arrival is labelled as type 1, and if p < Vi < p + ε then it is labelled as type 2. In the (p, ε) system, if the queue length is x at the time of th ...
Probability interpretations

The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.