• Study Resource
  • Explore
    • Arts & Humanities
    • Business
    • Engineering & Technology
    • Foreign Language
    • History
    • Math
    • Science
    • Social Science

    Top subcategories

    • Advanced Math
    • Algebra
    • Basic Math
    • Calculus
    • Geometry
    • Linear Algebra
    • Pre-Algebra
    • Pre-Calculus
    • Statistics And Probability
    • Trigonometry
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Astronomy
    • Astrophysics
    • Biology
    • Chemistry
    • Earth Science
    • Environmental Science
    • Health Science
    • Physics
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Anthropology
    • Law
    • Political Science
    • Psychology
    • Sociology
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Accounting
    • Economics
    • Finance
    • Management
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Aerospace Engineering
    • Bioengineering
    • Chemical Engineering
    • Civil Engineering
    • Computer Science
    • Electrical Engineering
    • Industrial Engineering
    • Mechanical Engineering
    • Web Design
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Architecture
    • Communications
    • English
    • Gender Studies
    • Music
    • Performing Arts
    • Philosophy
    • Religious Studies
    • Writing
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Ancient History
    • European History
    • US History
    • World History
    • other →

    Top subcategories

    • Croatian
    • Czech
    • Finnish
    • Greek
    • Hindi
    • Japanese
    • Korean
    • Persian
    • Swedish
    • Turkish
    • other →
 
Profile Documents Logout
Upload
Continuous Homophily and Clustering in Random Networks
Continuous Homophily and Clustering in Random Networks

... Wasserman and Pattison, 1996; Watts and Strogatz, 1998; Barabási and Albert, 1999). The most commonly used until today is the BRG model, where connections between any two agents are established with the same constant probability. It has been shown that for large networks this model is almost equal ...
A Parallel Repetition Theorem for Any Interactive Argument
A Parallel Repetition Theorem for Any Interactive Argument

Chance, Luck and Statistics
Chance, Luck and Statistics

Adaptive Directional Stratification for controlled
Adaptive Directional Stratification for controlled

Probabilistic Horn abduction and Bayesian networks
Probabilistic Horn abduction and Bayesian networks

... Determining what is in a system from observations (diagnosis and recognition) is an important part of AI. There have been many logic-based proposals as to what is a diagnosis 17, 57, 13, 45, 12]. One problem with all of these proposals is that for any diagnostic problem of a reasonable size there a ...
XC-BK5 - Eclectic Anthropology Server
XC-BK5 - Eclectic Anthropology Server

... entirely without grounds. For example, Ember and Ember (1971) show that the presence of internal warfare strongly predicts patrilocal residence, defined as residence after marriage with the family of the groom. But imagine that you live in such a society with a high level of internal warfare. Does t ...
More Efficient PAC-learning of DNF with Membership Queries Under
More Efficient PAC-learning of DNF with Membership Queries Under

paper
paper

... error exponents in the case of Poisson traffic with i.i.d. losses. Having error exponents is important as it allows us to quantify the rate of decay of the probability of error with coding delay and to determine the parameters of importance in this decay. Our work draws upon results from the usually ...
ENTROPY, SPEED AND SPECTRAL RADIUS OF RANDOM WALKS
ENTROPY, SPEED AND SPECTRAL RADIUS OF RANDOM WALKS

Learning Sums of Independent Integer Random Variables
Learning Sums of Independent Integer Random Variables

... variable X that is supported on the k-element finite set {0, 1, . . . , k − 1}. Throughout the paper we refer to such a random variable as a k-IRV (for “Integer Random Variable”). Learning an unknown k-IRV is of course a well understood problem: it has long been known that a simple histogram-based a ...
Improving and extending the testing of distributions
Improving and extending the testing of distributions

Adaptive Designs of Experiments for Accurate
Adaptive Designs of Experiments for Accurate

Efficient Fully-Simulatable Oblivious Transfer∗
Efficient Fully-Simulatable Oblivious Transfer∗

Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach
Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach

Preprint - Math User Home Pages
Preprint - Math User Home Pages

TAIL BOUNDS FOR GAPS BETWEEN EIGENVALUES 1
TAIL BOUNDS FOR GAPS BETWEEN EIGENVALUES 1

The Sample Complexity of Exploration in the Multi
The Sample Complexity of Exploration in the Multi

Population Recovery and Partial Identification
Population Recovery and Partial Identification

... Noisy samples. Let −1 < ν < 1, and for simplicity assume Σ = {0, 1}. A ν-noisy sample v 0 is generated as follows. First, an element v ∈ V is picked at random with probability π(v). Then, independently at random, every bit vi of v is flipped with probability (1 − ν)/2, and left untouched with probab ...
Saving Schr¨odinger`s Cat: It`s About Time (not
Saving Schr¨odinger`s Cat: It`s About Time (not

yeti_stat_1 - Centre for Particle Physics
yeti_stat_1 - Centre for Particle Physics

On Random Line Segments in the Unit Square
On Random Line Segments in the Unit Square

Draft: Coherent Risk Measures
Draft: Coherent Risk Measures

Old notes from a probability course taught by Professor Lawler
Old notes from a probability course taught by Professor Lawler

... The mathematical foundations of probability theory are exactly the same as those of Lebesgue integration. However, probability adds much intuition and leads to different developments of the area. These notes are only intended to be a brief introduction — this might be considered what every graduate ...
T E C H N I C A L R E P O R T 10024 Prudence, temperance
T E C H N I C A L R E P O R T 10024 Prudence, temperance

7•5  Lesson 1 Problem Set
7•5 Lesson 1 Problem Set

... Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License. ...
< 1 ... 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 ... 305 >

Probability interpretations



The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical tendency of something to occur or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.There are two broad categories of probability interpretations which can be called ""physical"" and ""evidential"" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as the dice yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or ""relative frequency"", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. Thus talking about physical probability makes sense only when dealing with well defined random experiments. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn, Reichenbach and von Mises) and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability (or subjectivist probability), can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's) interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti and Savage), the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey, Cox) and the logical interpretation (Keynes and Carnap).Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of ""frequentist"" statistical methods, such as R. A. Fisher, Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the existence and importance of physical probabilities, but also consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word ""frequentist"" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, ""frequentist probability"" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view ""frequentist statistics"" as an approach to statistical inference that recognises only physical probabilities. Also the word ""objective"", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what ""physical"" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.
  • studyres.com © 2025
  • DMCA
  • Privacy
  • Terms
  • Report