Download Prosocial Behavior and Empathy: Developmental Processes

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Impression formation wikipedia , lookup

Lawrence Kohlberg wikipedia , lookup

Albert Bandura wikipedia , lookup

Social perception wikipedia , lookup

Altruism wikipedia , lookup

Psychological egoism wikipedia , lookup

Victim blaming wikipedia , lookup

Sympathy wikipedia , lookup

Empathy wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Prosecution
the differing protections of liberty and equality in the criminal
justice system. Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly 24: 665
Langbein J H 1974 Prosecuting Crime in the Renaissance:
England, Germany, France. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA
Langbein J H, Weinreb L L 1977 Continental criminal procedure: ‘myth’ and reality. Yale Law Journal 87: 1549–69
Leo R 1996 Inside the interrogation room. Journal of Criminal
Law and Criminology 86(2): 266–303
Nduka-Eze C 1995 The CPS and independence from the police.
New Law Journal 1843–4
Sessar K 1979 Prosecutorial discretion in Germany. In:
Macdonald W F (ed.) The Prosecutor. Sage, Beverly Hills,
CA, pp. 255–76
Sigler J 1979 The prosecutor: a comparative functional analysis.
In: Macdonald W F (ed.) The Prosecutor. Sage, Beverly Hills,
CA, pp. 53–74
Skolnick J 1975 Justice Without Trial: Law Enforcement in
Democratic Society (2nd edn.), Wiley, New York
Utz P 1979 Two models of prosecutorial professionalism. In:
Macdonald W F (ed.) The Prosecutor. Sage, Beverly Hills,
CA, pp. 99–124
Vera Institute of Justice 1981 Felony Arrests: Their Prosecution
and Disposition and New York City’s Courts. Longman,
New York
Weigand T 1999 Germany. In: Bradley C M (ed.) Criminal
Procedure: A Worldwide Study. Carolina Academic Press,
Durham, NC, pp. 187–211
K. Levine and M. Feeley
Prosocial Behavior and Empathy:
Developmental Processes
Research on helping others in distress took off with the
brutal murder of a young woman in Queens, New
York in the mid-1960s, which was witnessed by 30
people from their apartment windows. The initial
research on why witnesses do not help (Latane and
Darley 1970) focused on the context and found that
the presence of other bystanders can interfere with a
person helping by activating certain assumptions—‘diffusion of responsibility’ (I’m sure someone
has called the police) or ‘pluralistic ignorance’ (no one
is doing anything, so it can’t be an emergency). There
was also research on when people do help, which
showed among other things that the tendency of
bystanders to help increases with age.
Recent research has focused more on prosocial
motivation and emotion. It highlights empathic
emotion, sympathy, and guilt. This article is concerned
with developmental processes in empathic emotions
and their contribution to helping. Also covered is the
role of cognition in arousing, developing, and shaping
empathic emotion and enlarging the individual’s
perspective on prosocial behavior. Finally, the article
deals with the contribution of socialization especially
by parents and peers, and gender differences.
12230
1. Definition of Empathy
Empathy has been defined in two ways: (a) the
cognitive awareness of another person’s internal states
(thoughts, feelings, perceptions, intentions); (b) the
vicarious affective response to another person. This
chapter deals with affective empathy, because of its
motive properties (see Ickes 1997 for cognitive empathy).
Affective empathy was initially defined as a match
between the observer’s and the model’s feeling. It is
now defined as it is here, more in terms of the processes
that make an observer’s feelings congruent with the
model’s situation not his own (Hoffman 1978, 2000).
There may be a match, but not necessarily as
when one feels empathic anger on seeing someone
attacked even when the victim feels sad or disappointed rather than angry. Most of the research on
affective empathy as a prosocial motive focuses on
empathic distress because prosocial moral action
usually involves helping someone in discomfort, pain,
danger, poverty, and the like.
2. Modes of Empathic Arousal
Five empathy-arousal modes have been identified
(Hoffman 1978). Three are primitive, automatic, and
preverbal. (a) Mimicry, which has two steps: one
spontaneously imitates another’s facial, vocal, or
postural expressions of feeling, producing changes in
one’s own facial or postural musculature; these
changes trigger afferent feedback to the brain, which
results in feelings that resemble the other’s feelings. (b)
Classical conditioning, in which empathic distress
becomes a conditioned response to distress in others
through observing others in distress at the same time
that one is in actual distress. (c) Direct association of
cues from others or their situation with one’s own
painful past experience. The empathy aroused by these
three modes is passive, involuntary, based on the pull
of surface cues, and requires little cognitive processing.
Nevertheless, these modes are important because (a)
they show that a person’s distress can indeed result
from someone else’s painful experience; (b) they make
empathy arousal possible in the early preverbal years
of childhood; and (c) they give empathy an involuntary
dimension throughout life.
Two empathy-arousing modes are higher order
cognitive. (a) Verbally mediated association: language
communicates the other’s distress and connects the
other’s situation to one’s own painful past experience.
(b) Perspective-taking: one feels something of the
victim’s distress by imagining how one would feel in
the victim’s place and\or trying to imagine directly
how the victim feels by using information one has
about him or her. These higher order cognitive modes
may be drawn out over time and subject to voluntary
control, but they may also be triggered immediately on
witnessing another’s distress. What they contribute to
Prosocial Behaior and Empathy: Deelopmental Processes
empathy is scope; they also allow one to empathize
with others who are not present.
Multiple modes are important because they enable
observers to respond empathically to whatever distress
cues are available (Hoffman 2000). Cues from the
victim’s face, voice, or posture can be picked up
through mimicry, situational cues, through conditioning or association. If a victim expresses distress
verbally or in writing, or someone else describes the
victim’s situation, one can empathize through verbally
mediated association or perspective-taking. Empathic
distress is thus a multidetermined hence reliable
human response, which fits the argument that it
survived natural selection and has a hereditary component (Hoffman 1981, Zahn-Waxler et al. 1992).
wise, depending on the attribution, empathic affect
may be shaped into four empathy-based moral affects
(Hoffman 2000). (a) Sympathetic distress, when the
cause is beyond the victim’s control (illness, accident,
loss). (b) Empathic anger, when someone else is the
cause. (c) Empathic feeling of injustice, when a
discrepancy exists between the victim’s character and
the victim’s fate (a good person fares badly). (d)
Empathy-based guilt over inaction, when one does not
help or one’s efforts to help fail and the victim’s
distress continues; here one’s empathic distress combines with blaming oneself not for causing the victim’s
distress but allowing it to continue.
3. Deelopmental Stages
Empathy correlates positively with helping. There is
also experimental evidence that arousal of empathic
distress leads to helping; and that observers help more
quickly the greater the victims’ pain and the higher the
observers’ empathic distress. Furthermore, observers’
empathic distress becomes less intense and they feel
better if they help, but not if they don’t help or if
despite their best efforts and through no fault of their
own, the victim’s distress is not alleviated, which
implies that the main objective of empathy-based
helping is to alleviate the victim’s distress. There is also
evidence that empathy reduces both aggressive and
manipulative (Machiavellian) behavior. It thus seems
clear that empathic distress is a prosocial motive. See
reviews by Hoffman (1978, 2000) and Eisenberg
and Miller (1987).
Empathy has limitations, however (Hoffman 1984,
2000). (a) Egoistic motives may intervene and one
may not help, even at the price of feeling guilty
afterwards. (b) Empathic distress increases with the
level of victims’ distress, but empathic distress can
become aversive enough to shift one’s attention from
the victim’s to one’s own personal distress (empathic
overarousal). (c) People empathize with almost anyone
in distress (the victims in research are usually strangers), but they empathize more with kin, in-group
members, friends, and people who share their personal
concerns (familiarity bias)—which may not be a
problem except when intergroup rivalry contributes to
intense empathic anger (hatred, ethnic cleansing)
toward outgroup members. (d) People empathize more
with victims who are physically present (here-and-now
bias), probably because most empathy-arousing processes require immediate situational and personal
cues.
Mature empathy has a metacognitive dimension: one
knows one’s feeling of distress results from another’s
plight and how the other presumably feels. One thus
has a sense of oneself and others as separate beings
with independent inner states (that are only partly
reflected in outward behavior), separate identities, and
separate life conditions. Before 6 or 7 years children
can empathize but without this metacognitive dimension. This suggests that empathic affect develops
along with cognitive self\other development. Five
stages of empathy development have been hypothesized (Hoffman 1978, 2000).
(a) Global empathic distress: newborns show a
vigorous, agitated distress response to another infant’s
cry. (b) Egocentric empathic distress: one responds to
another’s distress as though oneself were in distress.
This occurs when children can be empathically
aroused by the three preverbal modes but still lack a
clear self-\other distinction. (c) Quasiegocentric empathic distress: one knows the other is in actual distress
but confuses the other’s inner states with one’s own
and tries to help by doing for the other what would
comfort oneself. (d) Veridical empathic distress: one’s
feeling is closer to the other’s because one realizes the
other has inner states independent of one’s own. (e)
Empathy for another’s experience beyond the immediate situation (e.g., chronic illness, economic
hardship, deprivation): this high empathy level is
possible when children realize that others have an
identity and a generally sad or happy life condition;
and empathy with an entire group (homeless; Oklahoma City bombing victims).
5. Empathy as a Prosocial Motie
4. Causal Attribution’s Shaping of Empathic
Affect
6. Socialization by Parents and Peers
Humans spontaneously attribute causality to events
(Weiner 1985) and they presumably do this when
witnessing someone in distress. If they blame the
victim, empathic distress is of course reduced. Other-
The role of parent as socializer has three facets: model,
disciplinarian, nurturer. Each contributes to children’s
empathy and prosocial behavior, although discipline
has been the most studied (Hoffman 2000). The
12231
Prosocial Behaior and Empathy: Deelopmental Processes
discipline method most likely to contribute to empathy, helping, and guilt over harming others is a type
of reasoning called induction, often used by educated
middle-class American parents when children harm or
are about to harm someone. Inductions direct the
child’s attention to the victim’s distress and may thus
engage the empathy-arousing modes noted above.
They also highlight the child’s role in causing the
victim’s distress, which may lead to empathy-based
transgression guilt. Power-assertive disciplines (physical force, threats, commands) are associated with low
empathy, low helping, and low guilt, although some
power assertion may be needed at times to get children
to attend and process an induction’s message.
Parents’ behavior outside discipline encounters may
provide prosocial models that reinforce children’s
empathic proclivity and legitimize helping (Eisenberg
and Fabes 1998, Hoffman 2000). Examples are
expressing compassion toward people in difficult
straights such as the homeless; linking a television
protagonist’s feelings or situations with the child’s
own experience; pointing out similarities among all
humans such as sadness due to separation and loss.
Parent models may thus reinforce children’s empathic
dispositions especially when they are bystanders and
someone needs help. Parent models may also make
children more receptive to inductions, and, along with
inductions, make children more receptive to claims of
their peers (Hoffman 2000).
Piaget suggested in the 1930s that interaction with
peers (not parents, who are too powerful) fosters
prosocial moral development in children (Piaget 1932).
Cognitive-developmental psychologists have recently
elaborated this view (Turiel 1998), briefly as follows:
children ‘co-construct’ and discover moral norms in
the give-and-take of peer interaction (disputes, arguments, negotiations). These peer conflicts put pressure
on children to take different points of view and to
consider and coordinate the needs and rights of self
and others (for example, regarding claims to ownership and possession of objects). This is a compelling
hypothesis that merits research. Hoffman (2000)
suggests that the peer interaction processes involved
can serve to add the finishing touches to the prosocial
outcomes of having inductive, nurturant, prosocial
models as parents.
7. The Role of Cognition
Though we deal with empathic affect, cognition’s
importance is evident in two empathy arousal processes (verbally mediated association and perspectivetaking): in the key role of self\other differentiation in
empathy development; in the production of empathic
anger and empathy-based guilt through causal attribution; and in children processing the information
in inductions. Beyond that, cognitive development
enables humans to form images, represent people and
12232
events, and imagine themselves in another’s place; and
because represented people and events can evoke
affect, victims need not be present for empathy to be
aroused in observers. Empathy can be aroused when
observers imagine or read about victims, discuss or
argue about economic or political issues that involve
victims, or make moral judgments about hypothetical
moral dilemmas (see Moral Reasoning in Psychology)
in which there are victims. See Hoffman (1987, 2000)
for discussion of the importance of cognition, including the cognitive dimension of moral principles,
in empathy’s development and prosocial functioning.
8. Gender Differences
Girls are socialized more than boys to be kind and feel
responsible for others’ well-being. Girls are thus
expected, increasingly with age, to be more empathic
and prosocial and less likely to harm others. The
research supports these expectations but in varying
degrees (Eisenberg and Fabes 1998). Girls show more
kindness and consideration for others and, to a lesser
extent, are more likely to help and share. They are less
likely to harm others and more apt to feel guilty when
they do. They are also more empathic than boys, but
this is clear only with self-report, especially questionnaire measures, in which it is obvious what is being
assessed and responses are under the subject’s control.
It is not clear with unobtrusive naturalistic observations or physiological indices of empathy. The
empathy findings may thus reflect subjects’ conceptions of what boys and girls are supposed to be like.
Whether they reflect gender differences in actual
behavior is a matter for future research to decide.
See also: Adulthood: Prosocial Behavior and Empathy; Altruism and Prosocial Behavior, Sociology of;
Antisocial Behavior in Childhood and Adolescence;
Moral Reasoning in Psychology; Social Cognition and
Affect, Psychology of; Social Support, Psychology of
Bibliography
Eisenberg N, Fabes R A 1998 Prosocial development. In: Damon
W (ed.) Handbook of Child Psychology: Social, Emotional, and
Personality Deelopment, 5th edn. Wiley, New York, vol. 3
Eisenberg N, Miller P A 1987 The relation of empathy to prosocial and related behaviors. Psychological Bulletin 101:
91–119
Hoffman M L 1978 Empathy, its development and prosocial
implications. In: Keasey C B (ed.) Nebraska Symposium on
Motiation, University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, NV. Vol.
25, pp. 169–218
Hoffman M L 1981 Is altruism part of human nature? Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 40: 121–37
Hoffman M L 1984 Empathy, its limitations, and its role in a
comprehensive moral theory. In: Kurtines W, Gewirtz J (eds.)
Prosopagnosia
Morality, Moral Behaior, and Moral Deelopment. John
Wiley, New York, pp. 283–302
Hoffman M L 1987 The contribution of empathy to justice and
moral judgment. In: Eisenberg N, Strayer J (eds.) Empathy
and its Deelopment. Cambridge University Press, New York,
pp. 47–80
Hoffman M L 2000 Empathy and its Deelopment: Implications
for Caring and Justice. Cambridge University Press, New
York
Ickes W 1997 Empathic Accuracy. Guilford Press, New York
Latane B, Darley J M 1970 The Unresponsie Bystander: Why
Doesn’t He Help? Appleton-Century Crofts, New York
Lennon R, Eisenberg N 1987 Gender and age differences in
empathy and sympathy. In: Eisenberg N, Strayer J (eds.)
Empathy and its Deelopment. Cambridge University Press,
New York, pp. 195–217
Piaget J 1932 The Moral Judgment of the Child. Harcourt, New
York
Turiel E 1998 The development of morality. In: Damon W (ed.)
Handbook of Child Psychology: Social, Emotional, and Personality Deelopment. Wiley, New York, Vol. 3
Weiner B 1985 ‘Spontaneous’ causal thinking. Psychological
Bulletin 97: 74–84
Zahn-Waxler C, Emde R N, Robinson J L 1992 The development of empathy in twins. Deelopmental Psychology 28:
1038–47
M. L. Hoffman
Copyright # 2001 Elsevier Science Ltd.
All rights reserved.
Prosopagnosia
Prosopagnosia is a neuropsychological condition involving loss of ability to recognize familiar faces.
Prosopagnosic patients instead rely on voice, context,
name, or sometimes clothing or gait to achieve
recognition of people they know. The problem in face
recognition is not due to blindness (the person with
prosopagnosia can still see) or general intellectual
impairment (people are still recognized from nonfacial
cues). Yet even the most familiar faces may go
unrecognized: famous people, friends, family, and the
person’s own face when seen in a mirror.
Face recognition impairments are socially disabling,
and most patients develop strategies for tackling the
problem. They may note carefully what clothes someone is wearing, ask relatives always to wear a particular
distinctive item, or become adept at initiating or
maintaining a conversation whilst they work out who
they are talking to. These strategies are not completely
effective. One prosopagnosic patient lost a legal action
when he discussed his case with his opponent’s
lawyer—he thought it was his own advocate because
he was wearing similar court clothes.
Prosopagnosia should not be confused with other
types of impairment that can compromise face recognition (Young 1992). In prosopagnosia, recognition
from other cues than the face is usually possible. In
contrast, cases of inability to recognize people from
face, voice, and name have been described—these
seem to reflect loss of semantic information about the
identities of individuals. There are also reports of
problems of name retrieval (anomia), in which familiar
people are successfully recognized and appropriate
semantic information is accessed, but their names
cannot be recalled. Face recognition impairments
therefore reflect damage to an underlying system
which can break down in different ways.
Although reports of problems affecting face recognition after brain injury can be traced back to the
nineteenth century, prosopagnosia was identified as a
distinct neuropsychological problem by Bodamer in
1947 (Ellis and Florence 1990). Whilst it is generally
considered a rare deficit, there are now several hundred
case descriptions in the literature. These include cases
where brain injury early or late in life has led to
inability to recognize previously familiar faces, and
developmental cases where the disorder is present
from birth. People with prosopagnosia know when
they are looking at a face, and can describe its features,
but the loss of any sense of overt recognition is often
complete, with no feeling of familiarity. In contrast,
other aspects of face processing, such as the ability to
interpret facial expressions, or to match views of
unfamiliar faces, can remain remarkably intact in
some (though not all) cases. The ability to recognize
everyday objects other than faces may also remain
good, and many prosopagnosic patients are able to
read without difficulty. In one of the cases of early
acquired deficit, a child who had remained unable to
recognize any faces since suffering meningitis and
subsequent complications in infancy was nonetheless
able to learn to read (Young and Ellis 1989); this
underlines the implication that reading and face
recognition depend on different types of visual analysis.
Deficits commonly associated with prosopagnosia
include a visual field defect in the left upper quadrant,
achromatopsia (loss of color vision), and topographical disorders (inability to find one’s way about).
These are useful clinical pointers, but they are thought
to be due to anatomical proximity of otherwise
unrelated processes rather than having any direct
functional significance; cases of prosopagnosia without each of these associated deficits have been described, and they have also each been reported in the
absence of prosopagnosia.
Studies of prosopagnosia initially concentrated on
the location of the lesions responsible, and to what
extent the problem is specific to face recognition. More
recent work has asked whether there exist different
underlying forms of deficit, and has explored the
implications of findings of covert recognition.
1. Lesions Causing Prosopagnosia
The underlying pathology involves lesions affecting
ventromedial regions of occipitotemporal cortex; these
include the lingual, fusiform, and parahippocampal
12233
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences
ISBN: 0-08-043076-7